IN REVIEW Why Are Children in the Same Family So Different? Nonshared Environment a Decade Later Robert Plomin, PhD', Kathryn Asbury, MA, PG Dip2, Judith Dunn, Objective: To review recent developments in the study ofnonshared environment; that is, the environmental influences that make children growing up in the same family different, rather than similar. Method: We review several recent influential books andpapers on the subject of nonshared environmentfrom the decadefoUowing the 1987 paper that highlighted its importance in psychological development. Results: Modest progress has been made toward identifying the specific aspects ofthe environment responsiblefor nonshared environment. A Ithough parents treat their multiple children differently, such differential treatment accountsfor only a small amount of nonshared environmental influence, once geneticfactors are controlled. It has been suggested that some degree of nonshared environment may be due to the fact that siblings react differently to ostensibly shared environmental influences. Peer influence and other experiences outside the family may be more important sources of systematic nonshared environment. Conclusions: Despite the difficulties encountered in identifying specific sources of nonshared environment, thefact remains that most environmental variance affecting the development of psychological dimensions and psychiatric disorders is not shared by children growing up in the same family. More research and theory are needed to explain why such siblings are so different. Chance, in the sense of idiosyncratic experiences, also needs to be considered. (Can J Psychiatry 2001;46:225-233) Key Words: nonshared environment, families, development, behavioural genetics, twins, adoption O ne of the most important discoveries arising from behavioural-genetic research concerns nurture rather than nature. Behavioural-genetic research provides the best available evidence for the importance of environmental influences, but it shows that the environment works in a surprising way. Although socialization theories assume that the environment of the family unit influences psychological development, with the result that shared experiences lead to similarities among siblings, behavioural-genetics research consistently indicates that children growing up in the same family do not share effective environmental influences. It is not shared experiences, but shared genetics, that make siblings resemble one another. Indeed, with regard to psychological development, environment makes siblings no more similar to one another than to children picked at random from the general population. This phenomenon—the fact that effective environments are not shared—has been termed "nonshared environment," Our goal is to review recent developments in this field and point to new directions for research. We begin with a brief overview of the phenomenon of nonshared environment. Manuscript received and accepted December 2000. 'Research Professor, Social, Genetic and Developmental Psychiatty Research Centre, Institute of Psychiatry, King's College London, London, UK. ^Research Assistant, Social, Genetic and Developmental Psyehiatry Research Centre, Institute of Psychiatry, King's College London, London, UK, •'Research Professor, Social, Genetic and Developmental Psychiatry Research Centre, Institute of Psyehiatry, King's College London, London, UK, Addressfor correspondence: Dr R Plomin, Research Professor, Social, Genetie and Developmental Psychiatry Research Centre, Institute of Psyehiatry, King's College London, DeCrespigny Park, Denmark Hill, London SE5 8AF, UK, e-mail: r,[email protected],ac,uk Can J Psychiatry, Voi 46, April 2001 The Phenomenon Nonshared environment lay hidden within behaviouralgenetic studies since such studies began 80 years ago. Twin studies and adoption studies were designed to disentangle the elements of nature and nurture in familial resemblance. For example, schizophrenia runs in families, and environmentalists had assumed that it does so for environmental reasons: family members share the same schizophrenogenic environment. Twin studies and adoption studies test this assumption by studying family members who share nature or nurture to varying degrees. Although most relevant evidence has come 225 226 The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry from twin studies, it is easiest to see the logic of behaviouralgenetic designs by using adoption studies. Studying genetically related individuals reared apart in uncorrelated (although not necessarily different) environments directly estimates the extent to which familial resemblance is mediated genetically. These are the sort of data that convinced psychiatrists in the late 1960s of the importance of genetic influence. For example, Heston's classic adoption study showed that children adopted away at birth from biological parents with schizophrenia were nonetheless at risk for schizophrenia, suggesting genetic influence on parent-offspring resemblance for schizophrenia (1), Indeed these children, adopted away at birth, were just as likely to suffer from schizophrenia as are children reared by parents with schizophrenia, implying that growing up in a schizophrenogenic environment does not add to the genetic risk for schizophrenia, A more direct test of the nurture assumption, however, lies in the other prong of the 2-pronged adoption design—studying genetically unrelated individuals reared together in the same adoptive family, which directly estimates the extent to which familial resemblance is mediated by shared environment. For schizophrenia, there is no risk from growing up in a family with a parent or sibling who suffers from the disorder (2), Taken together, these adoption data imply that familial resemblance for schizophrenia is mediated genetically, not environmentally. The environment is important, however. For example, identical twins are only 50% concordant for schizophrenia—not 100% concordant, which would be the case if schizophrenia were entirely due to genetic factors. Because they are genetically identical, identical twins growing up in the same family environment can only be 50% discordant for schizophrenia for environmental reasons. Such environmental influences have been called nonshared because they are not shared by children growing up in the same family. The distinction between shared and nonshared has many other labels, such as "common" versus "unique," "between-family" versus "within-family," and "E2" versus "Ei," The environment is important, but it does not contribute to familial resemblance. It should be emphasized that such studies only address the contributions to resemblance among family members: their goal is to disentangle nature and nurture in familial resemblance. There may be more to schizophrenogenic family environment than is indexed by schizophrenia in the rearing parents. What we know from research on nonshared environment, however, is that the effect of such measures of the family environment is to make children growing up in the same family different from one another. The importance of nonshared environment for personality, as well as for psychopathology, was obvious from behaviouralgenetic data since such research began a century ago, but it was the hidden background in a figure-background illusion in which the figure was genetics. Only in 1976 was this illusion reversed to focus on the background. In a classic book on Voi 46, No 3 a large twin study, Loehlin and Nichols reported the typical finding of genetic infiuence for personality, but in their conclusions they noted ,,. a consistetit—though perplexing—pattern is emerging from the data (and it is not purely idiosyncratic to our stud)'). Environment carries substantial weight in deterrnining personality— it appears to account for at least half the variance— but that environment is one for which twin pairs are correlated close to zero. , , , In short, in the personality domain we seem to see environmental effects that operate almost randomly with respect to the sorts of variables that psychologists (and other people) have traditionally deemed important in personality development (3, p 92), This theme was highlighted and expanded in a 1981 paper (4), The evidence for the importance of nonshared environment in the development of psychopathology, personality and cognitive abilities was brought together in a Behavioural and Brain Sciences (BBS) target article called "Why are children in the same family so different from one another?" (5), which was published with 32 commentaries and a response to the commentaries (6), Even though they were addressed in the target BBS article and response to the commentaries, the following issues resurfaced during the next decade: 1) nonshared environment needs to be distinguished from error of measurement (yes); 2) genotype-environment interaction and correlation could account for nonshared environment (no, these cannot explain why identical twins are different); 3) shared environment may have more effect in extreme situations, such as those found in abusive families (yes); 4) perceptions of environment may be an important source of nonshared experience (yes); and 5) nonshared environment may involve chance, in the sense of idiosyncratic experiences, including prenatal events (yes). None of the responses then or since have challenged the basic finding that nonshared environment is important. The message of the BBS paper was upbeat: there is a new way, and an empirical tool to study the environment. Namely, it is to study more than one child per family to find out why they are so different. Three steps were identified for this research program: 1) document differential experiences, which requires the construction of measures of the environment that are specific to each child in the family; 2) document the association between such differential experiences and differential outcomes; and 3) investigate the extent to which associations between differential experiences and differential outcomes are causal. The 1987 paper also included a table listing possible sources of nonshared environment (see Table 1), These are not limited to the psychosocial environments that psychologists typically mean when they use the word "environment," Behavioural genetics defines "genetic" very narrowly to mean inheritance, which is what is typically meant when we say, for example, that eye colour is genetic. In contrast, environment is defined extremely broadly to include anything that is not genetic in this narrow sense. For example, many DNA events (such as chromosomal anomalies or somatic mutations April 2001 Why Are Children in the Same Family So Different? that are not transmitted to offspring) are not genetic in that they are not inherited. Thus, this broad definition of environmental as nongenetic includes all noninherited intra- and interorganismic infiuences. While we are discussing basic issues, we should also reiterate the point that genetic research describes what is rather than predicting what could be. For example, high heritability for height means that height differences among individuals are largely due to genetic differences, given the genetic and environmental infiuences that exist in a particular population at a particular time (what is). Even a highly heritable trait like height can be affected by an environmental intervention, such as improving children's diet or preventing illness (what could be). Such environmental factors are thought to be responsible for the average increase in height across generations, even though individual differences in height are highly heritable in each generation. During the past decade, researchers have often emphasized a single source of nonshared environment, such as family composition (7), sibling interactions (8), peer infiuence (9), and nonsystematic factors (10), However, the list shown in Table 1 has remained unchanged, not because of the researchers' prescience, but simply because it includes all possible types of nongenetic infiuence. In one sense, thinking about environmental influences that create differences between children in the same family represents a dramatic reconceptualization of psychological environments. On the other hand, this reconceptualization need not involve mysterious elements in the environment: Any environmental factor can be viewed in terms of its contribution to nonshared envirotimental variance. For example, parental affection can be easily construed as a source of differences among children in the same family, because parents may be more affectionate toward one child than another (5). What was new was the focus on measures of experience specific to each child, including subjective perceptions of experience. As discussed later, the same event (for example, parental divorce) may be experienced differently by 2 children in the same family, and we can assess the children's differential experience of a shared event. In trying to understand why siblings are so different, however, it is reasonable first to investigate experiences that differ within families. In 1990, the BBS paper spawned a nonacademic book called Separate Lives: Why Siblings Are So Different, which reinterpreted sibling socialization research along the lines of nonshared environment. It generally showed that siblings growing up in the same families experience environments that differ from those experienced by their parents and their cosiblings as much as the environments experienced among siblings growing up in different families (11), A more detailed review of the methods and evidence for nonshared environment for the development of psychopathology, personality, and cognitive abilities was published in 1994 (12), Several nonshared environment studies of siblings were launched in the late 1980s and early 1990s; the early ones 227 were described in 1994, in an edited book called Separate Social Worlds of Siblings: Impact of Nonshared Environment on Development (]2). A recent metaanalysis, discussed later, identified 43 papers that have addressed the second stage of the nonshared environmental program of research—identifying associations between nonshared experiences and siblings' differential outcomes (10), The largest study is the Nonshared Environment in Adolescent Development (NEAD) project which sprang directly from discussions based on the BBS paper, NEAD was a decade-long study that involved a collaboration between a psychodynamic family psychiatrist, a child psychologist specialising in families, and a behavioural geneticist. The NEAD project aimed to address all 3 steps in the program of research listed above, focusing on measures of the family environment and their effect on adolescent psychopathology in a genetically sensitive design. Its results are described below. The Reaction Despite the revolutionary implications of realizing the importance of nonshared environment, there was until recently little response from the developmental psychology community, perhaps because the responses to the 1987 BBS paper were so thorough. Nonetheless, an early-warning shot was fired in a 1991 paper in Psychological Bulletin (7), The critique began with a general broadside criticizing behavioural-genetic methodology, only some of which was relevant to the issue of nonshared environment. The paper argued that, although some behaviours studied (such as IQ) showed resemblance for adoptive siblings, which suggests shared environmental infiuence, other behaviours (such as self-concept) which would show shared environmental infiuence, had not yet been studied. Although we agree that behavioural-genetic methods are only quasi-experimental designs, the convergence of results from the different designs of the twin study and adoption study that point to the importance of nonshared environment is impressive (14). As indicated above, the easiest way to see the importance of nonshared environment—one that sidesteps most of the complexities—lies in observing the considerable differences seen within pairs of identical twins reared together (even though studies of identical twins probably underestimate nonshared environment because there are special twin effects that contribute to their similarity). Concerning the hypothesis that IQ and selfconcept show shared environmental infiuence, the general rule that effective environments are nonshared does not depend on showing that there are no exceptions to it. Nonetheless, one of the most interesting results in this area involves IQ: although younger adoptive siblings resemble each other, studies of postadolescent adoptive siblings consistently show no resemblance, suggesting that, in the long run, the environment operates as nonshared environment, even for IQ (15,16), This finding suggests that in childhood we will find shared environmental infiuences that relate to cognitive 228 The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry development but that what we need to look for in childhood are nonshared environmental influences that predict cognitive abilities in the long run (17). Conceming the issue of self-concept, the first behavioural-genetic study of selfconcept showed no evidence of shared environment (18), a finding confirmed in subsequent studies (19,20). If the critique had considered psychopathology, however, it could have pointed to at least 1 exception to the rule that environmental influences are nonshared: juvenile delinquency shows some shared environmental influence (14,21), although even this evidence for shared environment may be artificial in that twins may be partners in crime (22). Despite its general attack on behavioural genetics, the critique in the end agrees that environmental influences for personality are nonshared: There is basic consensus across behavioural genetics and developmental psycholog)' that both genetics and environment play a role in personality developtnent and that environmental influences do not result in sibling similarity (7, p 190). The author suggests that developmental psychologists already knew that the way in which the environment worked was nonshared: The behavioural geneticists assume that such variables, if operating, would make siblings alike in personality. Environmentally oriented developmental psychologists, on the other hand, hold that these influences operate differenfly for different children, and thus the absence of sibling similarity' does not mean these variables are not having an effect (7, p 190). If developmentalists had known about the importance of nonshared environment, why is it that far less than 1% of all developmental studies of socialization studied more than a single child per family—the only way to investigate nonshared environment? A presidential address for the Society for Research in Child Development (23) and a double-barrelled blast of popular books by David Rowe (24) and Judith Harris (9) elicited a decade-delayed reaction from developmental psychologists (8,25,26). These publications provocatively spelled out the implications of nonshared environment for theories of socialization; they also tackled larger issues about the nature of nurture. The title of the Harris book is The Nurture Assumption, and one of the subtitles on the dust jacket is: "Parents matter less than you think and peers matter more." This book attracted much media attention and was the subject of a cover story in Newsweek, entitled "Who needs parents?" (27). It also received glowing publicity in a lengthy and influential review ("Do parents matter?") that was published in The New Yorker (28). (For the extraordinary media coverage of The Nurture Assumption, see http://home.att.net/~xchar/tna/.) The negative reaction to these publications is largely directed toward nature-and-nurture issues other than nonshared environment per se. The Harris book, for example, is criticized for arguing that peers are more important than parents (8), an Vol 46, No 3 argument to which Harris has responded (29). Fueling this controversy is the mistaken interpretation that, if parenting does not shape children's personality, parents do not matter; however, what makes siblings similar or different is a much narrower issue (30). One issue specific to nonshared environment that continues to be raised is that estimates of nonshared environment are reduced when measurement error is taken into account (26,31). The need to separate nonshared environment from measurement error was emphasized in the 1987 BBS paper, and the point is this: environmental variance (whether a proportion of total variance or variance corrected for measurement error) is not shared—the effective environments are nonshared. Another criticism is that adoptive families have restricted variance and thus underestimate the effect of shared environment on IQ (32). However, even though most families studied by developmentalists do not fully represent the population, the intemal logic of the adoption method is unaffected when adoptive families and comparison nonadoptive families have similar variances, as in the Colorado Adoption Project (33). This is also the case for comparisons between identical and fratemal twins. Moreover, the hypothesis of restricted variance ignores crucial adoption data showing that a correlation of 0.26 was found for IQ for more than 200 pairs of adoptive siblings at the average age of 8 years, but 10 years later these same siblings showed a correlation near 0.0 (34). Because shared environment is found for IQ in childhood but not after adolescence in the same families, restriction of range cannot be an important factor in finding that the long-term influence of shared environment for IQ is negligible. A more useful suggestion is that more shared environment may be found in high-risk families, which implies that nonshared environment might be more likely to be found in low-risk families (35,36). Other useful points are that nonshared environment might involve perinatal factors, especially for psychopathology (37) and sibling social-comparison processes, such as sibling rivalry and sibling de-identification (38,39). An evolutionary perspective on sibling competition for parental investment suggests that sibling interactions in relation to parental attention might be a useful place to look for nonshared environment (40,41). A more general criticism concems the need to assess the environment in behavioural-genetic research: Behaviour-genetic analyses, however, can establish that nonshared environment contributes to individual differences in a domain but cannot document the connections between objectively measured nonshared environmental events and development (25, p 221) To the contrary, as discussed in the BBS paper, it is a major strength of quantitative genetics that its twin and adoption study methods can describe the net effect of genetic and environmental influences without attempting the impossible task of assessing specific genes and specific environments. The April 2001 Why Are Children in the Same Family So Different? next Step in the environmental program of research is to identify specific aspects of the environment responsible for nonshared environment, just as the next step in the genetic program of research is to identify specific genes responsible for heritability. As difficult as it is to identify specific genes operating in multiple-gene systems (42), it may be even more difficult to identify specific environmental infiuences responsible for nonshared environment. With genes, we at least know the unit of transmission and how transmission occurs, but for the environment, especially nonshared environment, we know neither, A constructive suggestion emerging from the past decade's literature is that nonshared environmental effects can be found in children's differential responses to ostensibly shared events (26), That is, as they interact with children s characteristics, ostensibly shared events can result in nonshared environmental effects. This distinction can be seen most clearly for variables that are usually measured on a family-wide basis, such as parental illness, education, poverty, unemployment, or neighbourhood. Depending on children's characteristics, such as age, sex, and personality, the effect of such factors could differ for children in the same family. An example that has been used is research showing that the effect of paternal unemployment during the Great Depression depended on the age and sex of the child: a shared experience could have nonshared effects (43), Although it seems quite likely that such interactions could be a source of nonshared experience, it should be noted that the unemployment example is drawn from an analysis between families, rather than within families. To test whether the association occurs within families, and thus accounts for sibling differences in developmental outcomes, it would be necessary to show that the effects of paternal unemployment on sibling differential outcomes are moderated by sibling age or sex differences. Empirical research showing the importance of such interactions in explaining nonshared environment is needed. In trying to account for the differences among siblings in a family, however, it seems reasonable to begin by looking for main effects of experiences that differ for siblings (for example, differential parental treatment), rather than looking for interactions using experiences that do not differ for siblings. Also, a better strategy might be to investigate main effects of siblings' different perceptions of such shared experiences. The hypothesis that shared events can have nonshared effects sometimes leads to the conclusion that "there is nothing about the findings of these traditional studies that is invalidated by their having studied only one child" (26, p, 16), To the extent that one is interested in finding environmental infiuences that affect development, this conclusion is unwarranted, because we now know that the effective environments are nonshared. Traditional between-family associations between parenting and children's outcomes can only explain nonshared environment to the extent that they can also be shown to operate within families, to make siblings different. Other nonshared 229 Table 1. Categories of environmental influences that cause children in the same family to differ (adapted from Plomin and Daniels, |5|) Categories Examples Error of measurement Test-retest reliability Nonshared environment Nonsystematie Aeeidents, differential prenatal effeets, illness, trauma Systematie Family eomposition Birtb order, sex differenees Sibling interaetion Differential treatment or perceptions Parent-ehild relations Differential treatment or perceptions Extrafamilial Differential experienees with peers, friends, teachers, sports, otber activities and interests, education, occupations, spouses, family life environmental explanations of associations between parenting and child outcome arising from between-family studies include the possibility that parenting is an effect, rather than a cause, of differences in children's outcomes or that the associations are due to a third variable, genetics, as discussed below. The goal of nonshared environmental research is to explain that siblings growing up in the same family are so different because this is how the environment works. New Research A consensus exists that children growing up in the same family experience different environments. This is the first step in the 3-step program of research on nonshared environment. Concerning the second step—relating differential experience of siblings to differential outcomes—we predict that all the factors listed in Table 1 make some contribution to nonshared environment, A metaanalysis of 43 papers addressing this second step concluded that "measured nonshared environmental variables do not account for a substantial portion of the nonshared variability" (10, p 78), Looking at the same studies, however, an optimist could conclude that this research is off to a good start. The proportion of total variance accounted for in adjustment, personality, and cognitive outcomes was 0.01 for family constellation, 0,02 for differential parental behaviour, 0,02 for differential sibling interaction, and 0,05 for differential peer or teacher interaction. Moreover, these effects are largely independent, because aggregate measures of differential environment account for 13% of the total variance. These studies have not yet, however, taken the third step in the research program: the attempt to disentangle cause and effect. Earlier, we noted that it may be more difficult to identify specific environmental infiuences responsible for nonshared environment than it is to identify specific genes responsible for heritability. Nonetheless, one could argue that at least as much progress has been made in identifying nonshared environment as has been made in identifying genes (14), 230 The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry In this section, we focus on the results of the decade-long NEAD project because it represents the leading edge of research on nonshared environment in attempting to address all 3 steps in the research program (44). During 2 visits of 2 hours each, made at 3-year intervals to 720 families with 2 same-sex sibling offspring ranging in age from 10 to 18 years, extensive questionnaire and interview measures of the family environment were administered to both parents and offspring, and parent-child interactions were videotaped during a session in which problems in family relationships were discussed. Multiple measures across multiple sources of information were combined to create highly reliable composite measures. The first step was to identify differential experiences of siblings. Sibling correlations for children's reports of their family interactions (for example, reports of their parents' negativity) were moderate, as they were for observational ratings of child-to-parent, and parent-to-ehild, interactions. Because these measures were highly reliable, this finding suggests that such experiences are largely nonshared. In contrast, parent reports yielded high sibling correlations (as, for example, when parents reported on their own negativity toward each of the children). Although this may be due to a rater effect in that the parent rates both children, the high sibling correlations for parent reports of children's environments indicate that parent reports are not good candidates for investigating nonshared environmental factors. Once child-specific nonshared experiences are identified, the second step is to ask whether these nonshared experiences relate to psychological outcomes. For example, to what extent do differences in parental treatment account for the nonshared environmental variance known to be important for personality and psyehopathology? Although research in this area has only just begun, some success has been achieved in predicting differences in adjustment from differences in sibling experiences (13). The NEAD project provides several examples using different models and methods to investigate associations between siblings' differential experiences and differential outcomes. (A useful, simple, and general methodology has been described by Rodgers and others [45]; see also Turkheimer and Waldron [10]). For instance, negative parental behaviour directed specifically to one adolescent sibling (controlling for parental treatment of the other sibling) relates strongly to that child's antisocial behaviour and, to a lesser extent, to that child's depression (44). Most of these associations involve negative aspects of parenting, such as confliet, and negative outcomes, such as antisocial behaviour. Associations are generally weaker for aspeets of positive parenting, such as affection. At this point it would appear that NEAD supplied a happy ending for the story of nonshared environment: parents treat children differently and this differential treatment relates to differential adjustment. The issue suddenly became more complex, however, at the third step in this researeh Vol 46, No 3 program—asking whether differential parenting is a cause or an effect of children's adjustment. Longitudinal cross-lagged analyses were conducted but were not very informative: the parenting measures and adjustment measures were quite stable over the 3-year interval in whieh NEAD families were studied, whereas the success of cross-lagged analyses depends on change. A unique feature of NEAD is that its extensive measures of family environment were embedded in a genetieally sensitive design to assess possible genetic mediation of associations between nonshared environment and adolescent psyehopathology. The 720 NEAD families were selected to include identical and fraternal twins, full siblings, half-siblings, and genetically unrelated siblings. In these families, the twins and siblings were the adolescent children, not the parents, so that genetic mediation could be seen to the extent that differential parenting is a response to children's genetieally driven differential adjustment. NEAD used multivariate genetic analysis of eovadance to address this issue (46). Unlike traditional univariate genetic analysis of the variance of a single variable, multivariate genetic analysis decomposes the eovariance between variables into genetic and environmental sources of eovarianee (47). The basic idea is that instead of eomparing identical and fraternal twin correlations for a single variable in order to decompose the variance of that variable, multivariate genetic analysis eompares identical and fraternal twin crosscorrelations—that is, the correlation between variable X for one twin and variable Y for the other twin—in order to decompose the covariance between X and Y. Genetic mediation of the covariance is implied if the identical twin crosscorrelation exceeds the fraternal twin cross-correlation (see 14, for details). In addition to families with identical and fraternal twins, NEAD applied multivariate genetie analysis to the covariance between family environment and adolescent outcome for families with full siblings, half siblings and unrelated siblings. This approach estimates genetie mediation of the eovarianee between family environment and adolescent outcome, and, just as importantly, it estimates shared and nonshared environmental contributions to the eovariance, independent of genetie effects. Moreover, if the standard assumption is made that error of measurement does not correlate across measures, the nonshared environmental contribution to the eovarianee is free of measurement error. Multivariate genetie analysis of the associations between parental negativity and adolescent adjustment yielded an unexpected finding: most of these associations were mediated by genetie factors. Hardly any nonshared environmental mediating effeets remained independent of genetic mediation. The finding that nonshared environment fails to mediate these assoeiations is supported by simpler analyses that found little assoeiation between identical twin differences in family environment and identical twin differences in adolescent outcomes—an analytic approach that directly assesses April 2001 Why Are Chitdren in the Same Family So Different? nonshared environmental mediation of the association (48). The finding of genetic mediation implies that, to a substantial extent, differential parental treatment of siblings reflects genetically influenced differences between the siblings. As implausible as this finding might seem on first encounter, it is part of the second great discovery of genetic research at the interface between nature and nurture—genetics contributes substantially to experience (49). The NEAD quest for nonshared environment led to genotype-environment correlation; that is, children select, modify, construct, and reconstruct their experiences in part on the basis of their genetic propensities. Many of the recent reactions mentioned earlier (8,25,26) focus on this larger issue of genotype-environment interplay, rather than on nonshared environment per se. The NEAD book (44) is called The Relationship Code because genotype-environment correlation restores to the family some of the infiuence lost to nonshared environment factors, in the sense that genetic propensities are expressed in the family environment. Genotype-environment correlation is neither a solely genetic nor a solely environment issue—it is both. This, however, is another story for another time. The Future The relevance ofthe NEAD results in relation to the story of nonshared environment is that we must begin again to identify nonshared environment. The traditional measures of family environment used in NEAD did not result in the identification of nonshared environmental links with differential sibling outcomes. Perhaps other measures ofthe family environment will be more successful. Perhaps some sources of nonshared environment can still be found in NEAD, in age and sex interactions with shared environmental factors, as suggested by recent papers. In retrospect, however, as Harris (9) has trenchantly pointed out, it seems odd to have looked for differential experiences of siblings solely in the family because siblings live in the same family. In defense of NEAD, investigating the family environment as a first step in the quest for nonshared environment allowed NEAD to capitalize on the huge research effort that has gone into assessing family environment. Indeed, it turns out that siblings experience very different family environments and that these differential experiences are strongly associated with differential outcomes. The problem is that genetic mediation largely accounts for these associations. As suggested by the results of the metaanalysis mentioned earlier (10), extrafamilial factors seem to be good candidates for nonshared environments—candidates that have not been studied nearly as much as has family environment. Harris anticipates that research will confirm the impact of peers: although genetic influence is involved in choosing and being chosen by friends and peers (50-53), a recent report involving both NEAD and an adoption study found that peer groups largely involve nonshared environment independent of 231 genetics, as predicted by Harris (54). Nonetheless, nonshared environment appears to be present early in life, long before children experience peer infiuence, which implies that nonshared environmental factors may differ from age to age—a topic to which we shall return. No matter how difficult it may be to find specific nonshared environmental factors, it should be emphasized that the effective environment operates in terms of nonshared experience. More research is needed to understand these mechanisms. The price of admission to research on nonshared environment is to study more than a single child per family. This is not difficult because more than 80% of families have more than a single child: siblings add synergistically to any research design. You can study whatever you were going to study in the traditional between-family way and then look at the data from a within-family perspective, which can in turn clarify the interpretation of any between-family findings (55). Any study of siblings can be used to investigate the first 2 steps in the research program mentioned earlier: documenting differential experiences and documenting the association between differential experiences and differential outcomes. Longitudinal studies can begin to address the third step: interpreting the direction of effects for the association—between, for example, parenting (X) and child outcomes (Y). Does X cause Y, or does Y cause X, or is a third factor responsible for the association between X and Y? Behavioural-genetic studies of twins or adoptees are useful to investigate genetics as a possible third factor mediating such associations. We also need to consider the gloomy prospect that chance contributes to nonshared environment in terms of random noise, idiosyncratic experiences, or the subtle interplay of a concatenation of events (5,10,11,56-58). Francis Galton, the founder of behavioural genetics, suggested that nonshared environment is largely due to chance, when he commented that "the whimsical effects of chance in producing stable results are common enough." Sounding a bit like a fortune cookie, he also observed that "tangled strings variously twitched, soon get themselves into tight knots" (59, p 195). Two overlooked findings from behavioural-genetic research also point to the importance of chance. The first is multivariate genetic research showing that nonshared environmental infiuences on one trait, such as depression, are independent of nonshared environmental infiuences on other traits, such as antisocial behaviour (44,60,61). The second finding involves the application of multivariate genetic analysis to longitudinal data. This assesses the genetic and environmental origins of age-to-age change and continuity (62). Longitudinal genetic analyses indicate that nonshared environmental infiuences are age-specific for psychopathology (63,64), personality (65-67), and cognitive abilities (68). In NEAD, although most nonshared environment was unstable, some stability was found for depression and antisocial behaviour over a 3-year interval in adolescence (44,69). That is. The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry 232 nonshared environmental infiuences at one age are largely different from nonshared environmental infiuences at another age. What environmental processes other than chance could explain these 2 findings? Our view, nonetheless, is that chance is the null hypothesis, although measures of life events can assess some of its aspects (70). Systematic sources of nonshared environment need to be thoroughly examined before we dismiss it as chance. Chance might only be a label for our current inability to identify the processes by which children—even pairs of identical twins—growing up in the same family come to be so different. For example, to some extent children might make their own luck. A larger implication of nonshared environment is that it provides an excellent indication that some ofthe most important questions for genetic research involve the environment, and some of the most important questions for environmental research involve genetics (71). Genetic research will profit if it includes sophisticated measures ofthe environment, environmental research will benefit from the use of genetic designs, and understanding of development will be advanced by collaboration between geneticists and environmentalists. In these ways, behavioural scientists are putting the nature-nurture controversy behind them and bringing nature and nurture together in the study of development to understand the processes by which genotypes become phenotypes. References 1. Heston LL. Psychiatric disorders in foster home reared children of schizophrenic mothers. Br J Psychiatry 1966;! 12:819-25. 2. Kety SS, Wender PH, Jacobsen B, Ingraham LJ, Jansson L, Faber B, and others. Mental illness in the biological and adoptive relatives of schizophrenic adoptees: Replication ofthe Copenhagen study in the rest of Denmark. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1994;51:442-55. 3. Loehlin JC, Nicholls J. Heredity, environment and personality. Austin: University ofTexas; 1976. 4. Rowe DC, Plomin R. The importance of nonshared (E1) environmental influences in behavioral development. Dev Psychol 1981; 17:517-31. 5. Plomin R, Daniels D. Why are children in the same family so different from each other? Behav Brain Sci 1987;IO:1-16. 6. Plomin R, Daniels D. Children in the same family are very different, but why? [response to commentaries]. Behav Brain Sci l987;10(l):44-55. 7. Hoffman LW, The influence ofthe family environment on personality: accounting for sibling differences. Psychol Bull I991;l 10:187-203. 8. Vandell D. Parents, peers, and others. Dev Psychol 2000;699-710. 9. Harris JR. The nurture assumption: why children turn out the way they do. New York: The Free Press; 1998. 10. Turkheimer E, Waldron M. Nonshared environment: a theoretical, methodological, and quantitative review. Psychol Bull 2000;126:78-108. 11. Dunn JF, Plomin R. Separate lives: why siblings are so different. New York: Basic Books; 1990. 12. Plomin R, Chipuer HM, Nciderhiser JM. Behavioural genetic evidence for the importance of nonshared environment. In: Hetherington, EM, Reiss D, Plomin R, editors. Separate social worlds of siblings: the impact of non-shared environment on development. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Eribaum Assoc; 1994. p 1—31. 13. Hetherington EM, Reiss D, Plomin R, editors. Separate social worlds of siblings: impact of nonshared environment on development. Hillsdale {NJ): Lawrence Eribaum Assoc; 1994. 14. Plomin R, DeFries JC, McCleam GE, McGuffin P. Behavioural Genetics. 4th ed. New York: Worth Publishers; 2001. 15. McGue M, Bouchard Jr TJ, Iacono WG, Lykken DT. Behavioural genetics of cognitive ability: A life-span perspective. In: Plomin R, McCleam GE, editors. Nature, nurture, and psychology. Washington (DC): American Psychological Association; 1993. p 59-76. Vol 46, No 3 Clinical Implications • In thinking about environmental causes of psychopathology, clinicians should consider nonshared environmental factors that make siblings different. • Nonshared environtnent is likely to involve extrafamilial experiences, such as peer influence, and idiosyncratic experiences, such as those resulting from chance. • Perceptions of experience may be an important source of nonshared environment. Limitations • Research has not yet investigated the relative influence of shared and nonshared environment at the extremes—in abusive families, for example. • Few specific nonshared environmental factors have as yet been identified in genetically sensitive ways. • More measures are needed of fatnily environment specific to each child in the family. 16. Plomin R. The nature and nurture of cognitive abilities. In: Stemberg RJ, editor. Advances in the psychology of human intelligence. Volume 4. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Eribaum Assoc; 1988. p 1-33. 17. Chipuer HM, Plomin R. Using siblings to identify shared and non-shared HOME items. Br J Dev Psych 1992; 10:165-78. 18. McGuire S, Neiderhiser JM, Reiss D, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. Genetic and environmental influences on perceptions of self-worth and competence in adolescence: a study of twins, full siblings, and step-siblings. Child Dev 1994;65:785-99. 19. McGuire S, Manke B, Saudino KJ, Reiss D, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. Perceived competence and self-worth during adolescence: a longitudinal behavioural genetic study. Child Dev 1999;70:1283-96. 20. Roy MA, Neale MC, Kendler KS. The genetic epidemiology of self-esteem. Br J Psychiatry. I995;166(6):8I3-2O. 21. Gottesman II, Goldsmith HH. Developmental p.sychopathology of antisocial behavior. In: Nelson CA, editor. Threats to optimal development. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Eribaum Assoc; 1994. p 69-104. 22. Rowe DC. Genetic and environmental components of antisocial pairs: A study of 265 twin pairs. Criminology 1986;24:513-32. 23. Scarr S. Developmental theories for the 1990s: development and individual differences. Child Dev 1992;63:1-I9. 24. Rowe DC. The limits of family influence: Genes experience, and behaviour. New York: Guilford Press; 1994. 25. Collins WA, Maccoby EE, Steinberg L, Hetherington EM, Bomstein M. Contemporary research in parenting: The case for nature and nurture. Am Psychol 2000;55(2):218-32. 26. Maccoby EE. Parenting and its effects on children: On reading and misreading behaviour genetics. Annu Rev Psychol 2000;5I:l-27. 27. Begley S. Who needs parents? Newsweek 1998;August 24:53. 28. Gladwell M. Do parents matter?. The New Yorker 1998;August 17:54-64. 29. Harris JR. Socialization, personality development, and the child's environments. Dev Psychol 2000;711-23. 30. Plomin R. Parents and Personality. APA Review of Books I999;44(4):269-71. 31. Rutter M, Silberg J, O'Connor TG, Simonoff E. Genetics and child psychiatry: I. Advances in quantitative and molecular genetics. J Child Psychol Psychiat 1999;40:3-18. 32. Stoolmiller M. Implications ofthe restrictedrangeof family environments for estimates of heritability and nonshared environment in behaviour-genetic adoption studies. Psychol Bull I999;I25:392-4O9. 33. DeFries JC, Plomin R, Fulker DW. Nature and nurture during middle childhood. Oxford (UK): Blackwell; 1994. 34. Loehlin JC, Horn JM, Willerman L. Modeling IQ change: evidence from the Texas adoption project. Child Dev I989;6O:993-IOO4. 35. O'Connor TG, Dunn JF, Jenkins JM, Pickering K, Rasbash J. Family settings and children's adjustment: differential adjustment within and across families. Br J Psychiatry [forthcoming]. 36. McGuire S, Clifford J, Fink J. Parental differential treatment in different family contexts: testing multiple risk models [manuscript submitted for publication]. 37. McGue M, Bouchard Jr TJ. Genetic and environmental influences on human behavioural differences. Annu Rev Neurosci 1998;21:1-24. 38. Fienberg ME, Hetherington EM. Sibling differentiation in adolescence: implications for behavioural genetic theory. Child Dev [forthcoming]. 39. McGuire S. Nonshared environment research: what is it and where is it going? Marriage and Family Review [forthcoming]. April 2001 Why Are Children in the Same Family So Different? 40. Buss DM. Evolutionary hypotheses and behavioural genetic methods: hopes for a union of two disparate disciplines. Behav Brain Sci 1987; 10:20. 41. Lalumiere ML, Quinsey VL, Craig WM. Why children from the same family are so different from one another—a Darwinian note. Human Nature 1996;7(3):281-90. 42. Plomin R, Owen MJ, McGuffm P. The genetic basis of complex human behaviours. Science 1994;264(5l66):1733-9. 43. Elder GH Jr. Children ofthe great depression. Chicago: University of Chicago Pre.ss; 1974. 44. Reiss D, Neiderhiser JM, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. The relationship code: deciphering genetic and social patterns in adolescent development. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press; 2000. 45. Rodgers JL, Rowe DC, Li C. Beyond nature versus nurture: DF analysis of nonshared influences on problem behaviours. Dev Psychol 1994;30:374-84. 46. Pike A, McGuire S, Hetherington EM, Reiss D, Plomin R. Family environment and adolescent depressive symptoms and antisocial behavior: a multivariate genetic analysis. Dev Psychol 1996;32:590-603. 47. Martin NG, Eaves LJ. The genetical analysis of covariance structure. Heredity 1977;38:79-95. 48. Pike A, Rei.ss D, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. Using MZ differences in the search for nonshared environmental effects. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 1996; 37:695-704. 49. Plomin R. Genetics and experience: the interplay between nature and nurture. Thousand Oaks (CA): Sage Publications Inc; 1994. 50. Baker LA, Daniels D. Nonshared environmental influences and personality differences in adult twins. J PersSoc Psychol 1990;58:103-10. 51. Daniels D, Plomin R. Differential experience of siblings in the same family. Dev Psychol 1985;21:747-60. 52. Mankc B, McGuire S, Reiss D, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. Genetic contributions to adolescents extrafamilial social interactions: teachers, best friends, and peers. Social Development l995;4:238-56. 53. Pike A, Manke B, Reiss D, Plomin R. A genetic analysis of differential experiences of adolescent siblings across three years. Social Development 2000;9:96-l 14. 54. lervolino AC, Pike A, Manke B, Reiss D, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. Genetic and environmental influences in adolescent peer socialization: evidence from two genetically sensitive designs Child Dev [forthcoming]. 55. Dick DM, Johnson JK, Vikcn RJ, Rose RJ. Testing between-family associations in within-family comparisons. Psych.Sci 2000; 11:409-l 3. 56. Molenaar PCM, Boomsma DI, Dolan CV. A third source of developmental differences. Behav Genet l993;6:519-24. 233 57. Jensen AR. The problem of genotype-environment correlation in the estimation of heritability from monozygotic and dizygotic twins. Acta Genet Med Gemellol 1974;25:86-99. 58. Jenson AR. The puzzle of nongenetic variance. In: Stemberg RJ, Grigorenko EL, editors. Intelligenee, heredity and environment. Cambridge (UK): Cambridge University Press; 1998. p 42-88. 59. Galton F. Natural inheritance. London: Macmillan; 1889. 60. Boomsma Dl. Absence or underestimation of shared environment. Behav Brain Sci 1987;IO:19. 61. Van den Oord JCG, Boomsma DI, Verhulst FC. A study of genetie and environmental effects on the eo-occurrence of problem behaviours in three-year-old twins. J Abnorm P.syehol 2000; 109:360-72. 62. Plomin R. Development, genetics, and psychology. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Eribaum Assoe; 1986. 63. Kendler KS, Neale MC, Kessler RC, Heath AC, Eaves LJ. A longitudinal twin study of personality and major depression in women. Arch Gen Psyehiatry 1993; 50:853-62. 64. Van den Oord JCG, Rowe DC. Continuity and change in children's .soeial maladjustment: A developmental behaviour genetic study. Dev Psychol 1997; 33:319-32. 65. Loehlin JC, Horn JM, Willerman L. Heredity, environment, and personality change: evidence from the Texas adoption study. J Pers I990;58:221—43. 66. McGue M, Bacon S, Lykken DT. Personality stability and change in early adulthood: a behavioural genetic analysis. Dev Psychol I993;29:96-1O9. 67. Pogue-Geile MF, Rose RJ. Developmental genetie studies of adult personality. Dev Psychol 1985;21:547-57. 68. Cherny SS, Fulker DW, Hewitt JK. Cognitive development from infancy to middle childhood. In: Stemberg RJ, Grigorenko EL, editors. Intelligenee, heredity and environment. Cambridge (UK): Cambridge University Press; 1997. p 463-82. 69. O'Connor TG, Neiderhiser JM, Reiss D, Hetherington EM, Plomin R. Genetic contributions to continuity, change, and co-occurrence of antisocial and depressive symptoms in adolescence. J Child Psychol Psychiatry l99B;39:323-36. 70. Eley TC, Stevenson J. Specific life events and ehronic experiences differentially associated with depression and anxiety in young twins. J Abnorm Child 2000;28(4):383-94. 71. Rutter M, Dunn JF, Plomin R, Simonoff E, Pickles A, Maughan B, and others. Integrating nature and nurture: implications of person-environment correlations and interactions for developmental psychopathology. Dev Psychopathol 1997;9:335-64. Resume— Pourquoi les enfants d'une meme famille sont-ils si differents? Le milieu non partage, dix ans plus tard Objectif: Examiner les recents developpements d'une etude du milieu non partage, c 'est-a-dire, les influences du milieu qui font que les enfants grandlssant dans la meme famille sont differents plutot que semblables. Methode : Nous passons en revue plusieurs livres et articles recents et influents sur le sujet du milieu non partage, dans les dix annees suivant I 'article de 1987 qui en soulignait I 'importance sur le developpement psychologique. Resultats: On a realise desprogres modestes dans I 'identification des aspects specifiques de I 'environnement qui sont responsables du milieu non partage. Bien que les parents traitent leurs multiples enfants differemment, cette difference de traitement ne represente qu 'une infime partie de I 'influence du milieu non partage, unefois que les facteurs genetiques sont pris en compte. On croit qu 'un certain degre du milieu non partage peut etre attrtbuable aufait quefreres et soeurs reagissent differemment aux influences du milieu manifestement partagees. L 'influence des pairs etd'autres experiences a I exterieur de lafamille peuvent etre des sources plus importantes de milieu non partage systematique. Conclusions: Malgre les difftcultes Hies a I 'identification des sources precises du milieu non partage, it n en demeurepas moins que la majorite de la variance de I 'environnement qui affecte le developpement des dimensions psychologiques et des troubles psychiatriques n 'est pas partagee par les enfants grandissant dans la meme famille. Des recherches et theories additionnelles sont necessaires pour expliquer pourquoifreres et soeurs sont si differents. Ilfaut egalement tenir compte du hasard, au sens des experiences idiosyncrasiques.
© Copyright 2024