8 What is Said and What is Meant: Conversational Implicatures in Natural Conversations, Research Settings, Media, and Advertising MICHAELA WÄNKE One day Joe bear was hungry. He asked his friend Irving bird where some honey was. Irving told him there was a beehive in the oak tree. Joe threatened to hit Irving if he didn’t tell him where some honey was. (Schank & Childers, 1984, p. 83; example from the development of TALE-SPIN, a computer program that makes up stories) A pparently Joe bear did not understand the meaning of the word “beehive”. Needless to say, a lack of semantic understanding makes communication difficult if not impossible. But consider the following example: At a holiday resort a woman comes to the swimming pool and sits down next to another woman who is intended to strike up a conversation. “Hi”, the neighbour says, “where do you come from?” “From my room” the new guest replies friendly. “No, I mean where do you live?” “At home, of course”, the woman answers. “But where is ‘home’?” “Oh, you mean, where my house is?” “Yes”, sighs the interrogator with relief, “that’s what I mean”. “Right next to the Jones”. This example demonstrates that semantic understanding is not sufficient for a successful communication. Given that the goal of communication is to convey meaning, the task of a listener is to understand what the speaker intends to mean. Most often, to understand what is meant requires going beyond the literal meaning of what is said. In other words, listeners have to make inferences in order to arrive at a pragmatic understanding. The need for such pragmatic inferences then of course calls for rules for inferences. Moreover, successful communication requires that all conversation partners share knowledge about these rules. In this 224 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION respect, shared knowledge about inference rules is part of the “common ground” which is defined as the information a speaker and an addressee believe they share (Clark & Marshall, 1981; Clark & Schober, 1991). One shared principle from which inference rules may be derived has been expressed by Paul Grice as the cooperative principle when he observed that “our talk exchanges . . . are characteristically, to some degree at least, a cooperative effort” (1975; p 45). The cooperative principle is the general principle underlying many more specific rules, which govern conversations, and if used as inference rules determine understanding in various social settings. After a detailed discussion of the cooperative principle I will turn to its application as an inference rule in one important domain of social exchange, namely the use and understanding of irony. Interestingly, the application of the cooperative principle as an inference rule is not constrained to natural conversations. The latter part of the present chapter is devoted to inferences in nonnatural communication settings. Specifically, I will review how research participants infer the meaning of instructions and research material and what inferences recipients draw from statements in advertising and in media reports. THE COOPERATIVE PRINCIPLE AS A PRAGMATIC INFERENCE RULE Joe bear apparently did not only miss the meaning of beehives. His failure went further and caused him to act strangely – at least from a human perspective. Normally, people tacitly assume that others respond to their questions in a manner that provides the information seeker with valid and relevant information to his question. As it was, Joe bear – or the computer program – did not understand what Grice called conversational implicatures (Grice, 1975). Implicatures refer to the meaning of an utterance that goes beyond its literal meaning. They result as a consequence of the cooperative principle, which participants expect each other to observe: Make your conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged. (1975; p. 45). Had Joe assumed that Irving’s contribution was a cooperative effort with respect to the purpose of Joe’s search for honey he would have understood the implicature or pragmatic meaning of Irving’s answer, namely that beehives are a means to achieve honey. In general then, observing the cooperative principle and taking the mutually accepted purpose into account will help to work out the meaning of an utterance. Sub-principles The cooperative principle is the summary of several sub-principles referred to as maxims. CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES The Maxim of Quantity: Make your contribution as informative as is required (for the current purposes of the exchange) Do not make your contribution more informative than is required The Maxim of Quality: Do not say what you believe to be false Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence The Maxim of Relation: Be relevant The Maxim of Manner: Avoid obscurity Avoid ambiguity Be brief Be orderly Although Grice phrased them as imperatives, these maxims are less prescriptive norms that speakers follow than they are ideals that represent reference points. For example, the maxim of quantity represents an ideal point at which everything that is said is informative and everything that is informative is said. Clearly, speakers deviate either intentionally or unintentionally from these ideals in various degrees, and any deviation may in itself carry meaning. Communication involves playing with these expectations, as the later examples will illustrate. Nevertheless, these maxims provide a framework for the interpretation of a given utterance in a given context. If one assumes the communication partner to adhere to the maxim of quantity, for example, one would have to infer that all the provided details are necessary with regard to the requested information. Moreover one would have to infer that no necessary details are withheld on purpose. Such pragmatic inferences or conversational implicatures are not necessarily the same as logical implications. For example, the statement “Jane has three children” logically implies that she has any number of children greater than or equal to three. Conversationally the statement implies that she has exactly three children or the maxim of quantity would have demanded the speaker to say “Jane has at least three children”. Take another example from a conversation between business partners about a project: A: “Can you give me a call tomorrow?” B: “Tomorrow is my wife’s birthday”. Logically B’s answer seems unrelated to A’s request and makes no sense. However, most people will understand that B does not intend to do business the following day, as he has plans to celebrate his wife’s birthday. What may be debatable is how much effort this particular inference requires. Does it come automatically or does it involve some thinking? I will turn to this issue later. Grice acknowledges that there are all sorts of other maxims depending on the specific purpose of the talk, for example influencing others or directing others’ actions. Particularly when it comes to direct social exchange, speakers may additionally consider the injunction “be polite”. The four core maxims, which are listed here, are those mainly connected with the purpose of a maximally efficient exchange of information. Given, however, that the exchange or the disseminating of information is – even if it is not the main purpose – one purpose in most communication, one may safely assume that these four maxims are the most important ones. By and large these four maxims overlap with the rules and norms 225 226 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION postulated in other models. McCann and Higgins (1992) list eight rules for communicators, which are almost fully congruent with the Gricean maxims. Sperber and Wilson (1986) subsume all maxims under the principle of relevance, probably the most important one of the four. Certainly, as already mentioned above, these maxims are not descriptive of everyday discourse. Rather they represent a set of expectations about communication that allows for interpreting a speaker’s intended meaning. When the exchange is assumed to be governed by conversational norms one would expect clear, informative, relevant, true, and maybe polite utterances. A particularly intriguing aspect of the cooperative principle is that deliberate violations can be as meaningful as is compliant observance. Meaningful Violations Based on the cooperative principle, a listener would assume that any apparent flouting by the speaker is not to be taken literally and is not the intended meaning. Thus, apparent violations of conversational norms may serve to indicate that statement is not meant literally and instigate the recipient to reinterpret the utterance to infer the pragmatic rather than the semantic implications. Recipients may read between the lines, for example, if an utterance is obviously less informative than it should be. Consider the example given by Grice of the following statement in a letter of recommendation for a philosopher’s job: “Dear sir, Mr. X’s command of English is excellent, and his attendance at tutorials has been regular, Yours, etc.” For anyone familiar with the requirements of a letter of reference it is obvious that the writer omitted far more important information. It may be presumed that the writer also knew the requirements of a letter of reference and hence one may infer that he did omit the information on purpose in order to implicate that the candidate is unsuitable for a philosopher’s job. A deliberate flouting of the maxim of quality is of course the principle of irony as illustrated later. But also rhetoric figures such as metaphors, meioses, and hyperboles (e.g. “every nice girl loves a sailor) are obviously not meant to be literally true. Last but not least (for more examples see Grice, 1975), a speaker may be deliberately obscure to signal to a recipient that the contents of the talk should not be known to a third party who is also present. If A says to B “I will not do what you asked me to do in your letter but will do what we discussed the other day”, then A makes clear that he does not want C to know what B had requested and what they had discussed. These examples illustrate that successful communication also requires that recipients recognize intended violations. How essential these basic communication skills are for social interaction becomes evident when we imagine having a conversation with someone lacking these skills, as for example in the introductory example at the vacation resort. People who suffer from autistic spectrum disorders, especially Asperger’s syndrome, and patients with damage in certain brain areas often have difficulties in understanding the pragmatic meaning of what is said and may feel confused by non-literal speech. Hence they may fail to respond to indirect requests such as “Can you pass the salt” and would respond to “where CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES do you come from?” with “from outside”. Jokes and irony may send them into states of high anxiety and they therefore miss out on some essential parts of human interaction. How Much Effort Does it Take and What Else is Needed? What becomes clear from a look at the maxims and their implications is how communication involves highly complex tasks. For a successful communication speakers need to find out what is informative for the partner and shape their utterances according to the common ground. Receivers are not passive either. They are highly skilled to infer different meanings according to the situational context. The question “Where do you work ?” will yield different answers depending on whether the question is posed at the company’s inter-office Christmas party or at a local bar. The question remains whether these inferences occur automatically or whether they require more effortful thinking. I would assume that both modes are possible. In the above example of the man mentioning his wife’s birthday, it helps to share the cultural knowledge that some couples like to do something special for each other’s birthday and may take the day off from work. Having such a conception will make the utterance immediately understood. In fact having any conception about the relation of wives’ birthdays and going to work will make the sentence immediately understood, although maybe not as had been intended. Someone coming from a culture where wives spend their birthdays with their female friends at a retreat may interpret the answer differently: “Tomorrow, I’m all alone and I have ample time to do business.” More interesting is the case where the recipient has no conception. At first glance, the mentioning of the wife’s birthday would make no sense. Still, a listener who fails to see the relevance at first glance – as Joe Bear did – but who would assume the partner to behave cooperatively – as Joe Bear did not – would search for a meaning that would fulfill the required relevance. To do so may entail the use of additional contextual cues and more cognitive effort. In either case, high or low effortful inferences, the cooperative principle serves as the general inference rule: If something is mentioned it must be relevant to the purpose of the communication. This principle alone however is not sufficient to make a specific inference, but specific knowledge is needed as illustrated in the above paragraph. Either pre-existing background knowledge or contextual cues may help to identify the intended meaning. THE COOPERATIVE PRINCIPLE IN DIFFERENT COMMUNICATION SETTINGS One may argue that the ability to share a joke or enjoy a friendly teasing is one of the most important types of social interaction as it promotes getting acquainted and establishes closeness. For this reason I chose humor and irony in the next section as an example to illustrate the cooperative principle in more detail. But just as the cooperative principle may create understanding, it may also create 227 228 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION misunderstanding if one partner adheres to it and the other does not, or even deception if the defection is intentional. In the latter parts of the chapter, I will focus on these two aspects. I will do so for two reasons. First, just as cognitive biases may teach us about cognitive processes, and optical illusions are enlightening with regard to how visual perception works, misunderstandings in communication lend themselves superbly to illustrate the communicative principles. Second, a rather influential research perspective in social psychology has suggested that research settings are examples of one-sided adherence to the cooperative principle and some classical research findings are partly due to research participants’ pragmatic (mis)interpretations of the verbal materials (Bless, Schwarz, & Strack 1993, Hilton, 1995; Schwarz, 1996). I will review the basic assumptions and main findings of this perspective. While the role of conversational norms in experimental research and in survey research is well explored, a further and more speculative part of the chapter will apply conversational logic to mass communication and in particular to advertising. Needless to say that this is where deception comes in. Pragmatic Implicatures in Humorous Social Exchanges Obviously the ability to go beyond the literal meaning in conversations is the base for having meaningful discourses and understanding each other. It is also important for identifying and detecting irony and teasing, as these most often imply utterances which should not be taken literally. Often a cue in recognizing that a statement is not to be taken literally is that if it were taken literally it would violate conversational norms. It would not be informative, true, or polite, to name just a few examples. Hence, the cooperative principle serves as a general inference rule. However, additional inferences are necessary. Parting from conversational norms may have many reasons, and an addressee needs to make the correct attributions in order to see the irony in a remark rather than feeling deceived, or to feel teased rather than insulted. A few examples illustrate such processes. The Maxim of Quality A statement is not ironic per se but a speaker is ironic to a particular listener, namely to a listener who knows that the speaker does not believe the statement to be true or informative and who also knows that the speaker is aware of the listener knowing this. Consider an example presented by Wyer and Collins in their treatise on humor (1992): “Central Illinois is certainly lovely – all that humidity and corn.” This statement is probably funny to most people because few people get enthusiastic about humidity and cornfields. But it is only recognized as irony when the listener believes that the speaker is not one of those rare people. Irony is about pretense (Grice, 1978), just like deception. But unlike a deceiving speaker the ironic speaker wants the pretense to be recognized. This all involves a number of decision steps for a listener to detect irony: 1. Does speaker believe utterance to be true? CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES • • If YES: STOP If NO: Does the speaker want the addressee to believe the statement to be true? – If YES: Speaker wants to deceive or is ironic for a third person’s or own sake – If NO: Speaker is ironic and wants addressee to share the irony. To begin with an addressee’s task is to find out whether the speaker could possibly believe the statement. Often one’s world knowledge may allow such inferences. Something so outrageous and bizarre that no one in his right mind would believe it is probably intended to be ironic. Clark and Gerrig (1984) point to Swift’s essay “A Modest Proposal” as a model piece of irony. In this essay, Swift pretended to propose to serve Irish children as food for the rich. “Surely Swift’s irony works just because the idea is so absurd that no one could ever have entertained it seriously” (Clark & Gerrig, 1984, p. 123). Sometimes, a listener needs a more intimate knowledge of the speaker’s attitudes and beliefs to recognize a violation against the maxim of quality. A remark may thus be recognized as ironic by some listeners who know the speaker’s true feelings, but not by others who are less familiar. The Maxim of Quantity Violations against the maxim of quality are not the only form of using conversational implicatures for humorous purposes. Telling others something they certainly know already and thereby being deliberately redundant and uninformative is also a form of mocking or teasing. The general underlying principle is that by pointing out something to someone the speaker signals that he or she believes this to be new information to the addressee. In mocking or teasing, the speaker of course only pretends to believe this. Why a speaker pretends to think of the addressee as ignorant may have different reasons. Possibly, the speaker wants to point out a neglect or shortcoming. Telling somebody who asks to borrow a cigarette that one can actually buy cigarettes in stores is a (friendly or unfriendly) reminder that the borrower is overstretching the lender’s generosity. “Call your son, his name is John by the way” may be a sarcastic remark to a parent who in the eye of the speaker takes too little interest in the kids. “There is a new invention, they call it telephones” may ridicule the partner’s negligence to call. Some remarks are more tricky and require more background knowledge about the speaker’s attitude to the addressee. Telling George Bush for example that Berlin is the capital of Germany may be intended as: 1. informative (if one believes he does not know that); 2. a somewhat hostile emphasis of George Bush’s reputation for being ignorant about the world (meant for others and independent of whether the speaker does or does not believe George Bush knows the capital of Germany); 3. a friendly tease playing on the same reputation (meant directly for Bush by someone who believes Bush knows the capital of Germany). Telling Nobel laureate Daniel Kahneman that he should not judge the probability 229 230 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION of an event by the ease with which instances come to mind may be considered as an acknowledgement of his famous work on the availability heuristic1 and represents another class of violations against the informativeness principle. It should have become clear that to go through such attributions in order to detect a statement’s meaning may be complex and may require knowledge about the speaker as well as of conventions and norms (e.g., how many people like corn fields; what is adequate to tell the president of the United States). Clearly the closer one is to a speaker, the better one gets at detecting irony, and can distinguish friendly teasing from hostile mocking. Politeness Although the maxim of politeness is not one of the core maxims it is nevertheless important in social interactions and also in humor. “Would you be so kind and pass the salt if it is not too much trouble” may be considered as perfectly appropriate in some social settings but would be considered as violating the briefness principle in most other settings. Using formal and complicated language or being overly polite in informal settings seems inappropriate. An audience would need to decide whether the speaker knows that the behavior is inappropriate and is trying to be funny or whether the speaker is simply socially inept and does not know what is and what is not suitable. To some extent the same logic applies to overly impolite statements but the case of impoliteness is trickier. According to the maxim of politeness one should not say anything that may offend the addressee. Therefore one can conclude that everything that, if taken literally, is offensive cannot be meant literally unless one has reason to assume that the speaker is hostile. Hence, literally rude remarks are likely to be reinterpreted as teasing (Wyer & Collins, 1992). An addressee of an impolite remark has to go through the following steps: 1. Is the speaker aware that the remark is literally impolite? (For example, can one assume that the speaker knows the social and cultural rules, knows the language adequately, etc.) • • If NO: speaker is socially inept If YES: Does the speaker intend to be offensive? (For example, is there a reason why the speaker may be hostile, is the speaker known to be an aggressive person, etc.) – If YES: Speaker is hostile toward addressee – If NO: Remark is not meant literally, speaker is teasing. Anything that helps to infer that the statement is not meant literally would thus increase the chance that it is considered as funny bickering. For example, when the statement is blatantly inaccurate it not only violates the norm of politeness but also the norm of quality. Saying to Jamie Oliver “too bad, you can’t cook” is thus quite likely considered as friendly bickering, but this may not be so easily concluded if the statement is directed at a less famous and successful chef or amateur cook. Note that a literally rude comment about a person only violates the maxim of CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES politeness if it is made in the presence of the person.2 A disparaging remark in the person’s absence may thus be more likely to be interpreted as reflecting the speaker’s true feelings, unless the remark is blatantly inaccurate (maxim of quality). What may be hurtful if one overheard the speaker say it behind one’s back may be taken good humouredly if said to one’s face. Another intriguing implication is that the more impolite a comment to one’s face, the less likely it is to be taken seriously (Wyer & Collins, 1992). Paradoxically, then, a moderately offensive statement (“The suit you are wearing is a bit unflattering”) may hurt more than an extremely offensive statement (“We all agree that you are fat and ugly”) – although of course this is not necessarily so. So far all examples pertain to a partner understanding correctly what other the partner meant. Note however that it takes two to cooperate. If one partner relies on the cooperativeness principle but the other does not adhere to it, misunderstandings are likely. Worse yet, a partner may also intentionally defect in order to deceive the other one without lying explicitly. These two dynamics are the topics of the remainder of this chapter. Pragmatic Implicatures in Research Settings Research participants are usually given information, for example person descriptions, scenarios, or choice options, etc. They are instructed what to do with the information, for example form a judgment, and they are asked questions in order to assess judgments or behavior. Although research settings are often quite standardized and formal, it has been suggested that research participants nevertheless abide by the same conversational rules they follow in less formalized and more natural communication settings (Bless, Schwarz, & Strack, 1993; Hilton, 1995; Schwarz, 1996). Research participants who rely on conversational norms would assume that the presented information is complete, unambiguous, and relevant to the task at hand. They would also assume that the questions that are asked are reasonable and do not involve trick questions or require knowledge they cannot be expected to have. They would further assume that the answer formats provided are adequate to express their response and are not arbitrarily chosen. Unfortunately, researchers do not necessarily follow conversational norms. Nor would they expect that participants do, or that these norms may mislead them. Researchers may have chosen the information to be irrelevant or incomplete in order to investigate the impact of such irrelevant or incomplete information in judgment and decision making. They may have chosen tasks that are unsolvable for specific reasons. And they may use standardized answer formats that do not suit the specific situation. This adherence to the cooperative principle on the participants’ side and the defection on the researcher’s side may account for some of the findings in classical (social) psychological experiments as well as in survey research (for reviews see Bless, Schwarz, & Strack, 1993; Hilton, 1990, 1995; Schwarz, 1996).3 Stimulated by this perspective, several studies analyzed research settings as a function of violations of the cooperative principle and could support this hypothesis. Two basic principles characterize this perspective. First, if research participants 231 232 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION assume that the information they are given conforms to the conversational norms (mainly the maxims of quantity and the maxim of relevance), they will assume that the information is relevant, complete, and sufficient. More importantly, they will assume that because no irrelevant, redundant, or unnecessary information is given, all information should therefore be used. Many results in socialpsychological research can be explained according to the participant’s notion: “If the experimenter presents it, I should use it” (Schwarz, 1996, p. 17) The second basic principle in this perspective is that research participants themselves strive to make their contributions informative. To do so they have to figure out what exactly the researcher wants to know. As is shown, research participants use any information to get a clearer picture about what would be informative and how they can shape their responses adequately. Research Participants Assume that the Presented Material is Relevant, Complete, and Sufficient Several effects have been reinter- preted from this account of the cooperative principle. A classic test for whether conversational norms are at least partially responsible for an observed effect is to replicate the paradigm used in the original study with an additional condition, in which the validity of conversational norms is undermined. If the classic effect is diminished or even eliminated when participants no longer presume conversational norms to be valid, one may conclude that conversational norms at least contribute to the effect. Consider the so-called dilution effect, for example (Nisbett, Zukier, & Lemley, 1981; Zukier,1982). In the normal experimental paradigm, in one condition only information that is diagnostic (relevant) for the judgment is presented, whereas in the other condition non-diagnostic (irrelevant) information is added. For example, in the diagnostic condition participants are asked to predict the Grade Point Average of a target person and are given this piece of information “He often starts things he does not finish”. In the non-diagnostic (dilution) condition another irrelevant piece of information is added, such as “A few times a year he is bothered by bad dreams”. The lesser impact of the diagnostic information on judgments in the dilution condition is interpreted as a sign that participants do not ignore irrelevant information although it does not bear on the judgment. It is assumed that participants base their judgment on the representativeness of the target for the judged dimension and this representativeness is diluted by additional nondiagnostic information. From the participants’ perspective, however, any information that is presented is likely to be relevant, otherwise the experimenter would hardly present it. At least this is what researchers assumed who suspected that the adherence to conversational norms was responsible for the dilution effect. In their experiments, participants in one half of the conditions were informed that some of the information may in fact not be relevant. As a result the dilution effect diminished (Igou & Bless, 2003a; Tetlock, Lerner, & Boettger, 1996). Likewise other studies undermined the validity of conversational norms in classic studies on representativeness and base-rate neglect. Typically, in the scenarios used by Tversky and Kahneman (Kahneman & Tversky, 1973; Tversky & Kahneman, 1973) the statistical information (e.g. better repair record for Saab vs. CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES Volvo) is given first and the contradicting individuating information (“my brotherin-law has had one problem after another with his Saab”) afterwards. What is usually found is that the individuating and vivid information has more influence in decisions than the pallid base-rate. Krosnick and colleagues (Krosnick, Li, & Lehmann, 1990) however noticed that when two-sided messages are presented, conversational norms would make the second piece of information more relevant. Given that a speaker who strongly believes in the first argument need not mention the contradictory evidence, recipients would pragmatically infer that the later argument must be important and relevant. When base-rate information was given last it indeed had more impact. More importantly even, when participants were made to believe that the order was chosen at random and thus the informational value of the order was undermined, recency effects again diminished. Similarly Schwarz, Strack, Hilton, and Naderer (1991) found diminished effects in another classical experiment on base-rate neglect when they undermined the relevance of presented information. There are many other examples showing that participants use information that is presented unless the guarantee of relevance is undermined. In the classic study on the fundamental attribution error, participants rated a writer of a pro-Castro essay more Castro friendly than the writer of a contra-Castro essay even when they were told the writers had no choice in the topic of the essay (Jones & Harris, 1967). Wright and Wells (1988) point out that researchers violate the maxim of relevance when asking participants to infer an essay writer’s true attitude from an essay after they had just undermined the diagnosticity of the essay by pointing out that the topic was assigned rather than freely chosen. As such a request would make no sense at all, participants may presume that the experimenter nevertheless believes the essay to have some diagnosticity. Indeed when participants were told that the information they were given was randomly selected and may not necessarily contain diagnostic information, the effect of the essay’s content diminished (Wright & Wells, 1988). The cooperative perspective has also been claimed to contribute to the findings of ingroup favoring in studies on the minimal group paradigm (Blank, 1997). In the minimal group paradigm participants are assigned to two utterly meaningless categories (e.g. “over-estimators” vs. “under-estimators”). They then have to distribute goods between an anonymous member of the same category and an anonymous member of the other category. Blank argued that in such an artificial situation with no cues to base their decision on participants are likely to assume that they are supposed to use the otherwise irrelevant category information. In a condition where the researcher gave a reason why this category membership information was presented, the typical ingroup bias diminished. So far all examples follow the principle “if the experimenter presents it, I should use it” (Schwarz, 1996, p. 17). Another principle that follows from the cooperative principle is: If the experimenter presents it, it is valid and sufficient information. Research on fault trees compared people’s estimates for possible causes for an event (e.g. a car failure) when they were given a large number of possible causes or only a subset of this list (pruned tree) (Fischhoff, Slovic, & Lichtenstein, 1978). As it turns out, estimates for each listed cause were higher 233 234 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION when there were fewer causes listed compared to the full list. Moreover, the estimate for “other causes” was well below the sum for the causes that were not presented in the pruned tree but were presented in the full tree. The insensitivity to omitted alternatives is also referred to as the fault tree phenomenon. Again, from a conversational perspective, participants may well assume that the researcher listed the major causes. More precisely, participants interpreted the task as assigning their estimates to what experts have already identified as the main causes. They did not interpret the task as a test on their knowledge to come up with other causes. However, when this assumption that the presented information is complete and the “other causes” category is negligible was undermined, the fault tree phenomenon was reduced (Choi & Choi, 2003). A Gricean perspective may however also account for the neglect of information that the participant considers irrelevant. For example, Ariely and Loewenstein (2000) noted that the duration neglect (e.g. Fredrickson & Kahneman, 1993; Varey & Kahneman, 1992) in the evaluations of experiences may be an artefact due to the interpretation of the question, rather than an actual insensitivity to duration. Usually requests for a global rating of an experience or a sequence of experiences come from conversational partners who want an estimate on the desirability of the event. One spectacular week at the Grand Canyon does not really alter the overall desirability of a visit to the Grand Canyon compared to one spectacular day. Although the traveler would have probably gained more pleasure from a whole week than from one day, it would be entirely inappropriate to figure duration into an answer to a question “How was your trip to the great Canyon”. Research Participants Try to Make Their Responses Informative The cooperative principle dictates how to make one’s contribution informative. To do so requires one to find out what is most informative for the partner, in this case the researcher. In normal conversations, one may draw inferences from one’s knowledge of the conversation partner, the previous conversation, the context and if in doubt one may ask for clarification. In standardized research situations however only the context remains as a possible cue. Accordingly, respondents will use any cue in the provided information to infer the intended meaning of a question, even if it does not make sense to the respondent, and to disambiguate vague concepts or ambiguous answering scales. Previous questions, introductions, the question wording, answer formats, and any other information may serve this purpose. Not surprisingly then, minimal and apparently irrelevant changes may affect responses quite significantly, as some examples will illustrate. Taking Cues from Who is Sampled Behavioral frequencies are often assessed by vague quantifiers (e.g. often, seldom, etc.) rather than by objective frequencies. Respondents may have their own thoughts on how many times constitutes “often” but they also seem to take cues from the survey context in order to find out what the researcher would consider as “often”. In one survey, students were told in the introduction that the survey was either representative for all adult people living in that town or for the student population at that university. When asked how often they were going to see a movie, student respondents reported a higher frequency CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES on a vague quantifier scale ranging from “hardly ever” to “very often” when the survey was believed to be representative for the general population as compared to when the survey was allegedly representative for university students only (Wänke, 2002). The introduction rendered the respective population a likely standard. Presumably, respondents inferred that if the study is representative for students only the researcher wants to know “how often I go to the movies compared to other students”, whereas when the whole population was surveyed the assumed standard of comparison changed. Because students (correctly) assumed a higher frequency among students than among other adults, they gave lower estimates when they compared themselves to other students. Taking Cues from Response Scales The survey context may help respondents interpret what the researcher meant by the vague quantifiers. Conversely, and probably equally unintentional by the researcher, vague quantifiers and temporal frames may help respondents to interpret and clarify the behavior in question. Respondents reported three times more headaches when asked whether they suffer frequently from headaches compared to when they are asked whether they occasionally suffer from headaches (Loftus, 1975). Presumably respondents interpreted the question to comprise also less severe cases in the former case. Likewise respondents who were asked to report how often they felt irritated subsequently reported more severe annoyances when the answer scale ranged from several times a year to less than three times per month compared to several times a day to less than once a week (Igou, Bless, & Schwarz, 2002; Schwarz, Strack, Müller, & Chassein, 1988). Respondents who strive to make their answer informative must come up with an interpretation of what is meant by “irritated”. As one can hardly be expected to remember all small hassles over a year, respondents conclude that the question cannot refer to these minor annoyances. Taking Cues from Repeated Questions In a normal conversation one would not ask the same questions twice – at least not immediately. Doing so would imply that the speaker is not satisfied with the answer just given. After all, assuming cooperative partners, asking a question is a request for information one does not already have (Clark & Clark, 1977). Thus, repeating a question although one has already been given an answer signals that one wants additional or different information. Again, this conversational rule is sometimes violated in research settings. Take a child’s perspective in a study on number conversation (Piaget, 1952). The experimenter shows two rows of an equal number of items and asks which row has more items or whether they are equal in number. Correctly the child answers that they both contain the same number of items. Then the experimenter moves the items in the one row to make it longer but does not add or remove items. Again the experimenter asks which row contains more. It does not take much imagination to see how this question may confuse the child. After all, the items did not change since the last answer, but still the experimenter asks again. Most likely the experimenter must mean something else, and length is a likely candidate. Indicating the longer line is then the answer of someone striving to make sense of a weird situation rather than a cognitive bias. In a highly inventive study, 235 236 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION McGarrigle and Donaldson (1974) found evidence for that interpretation. When the rearrangement was not done by the experimenter but by a “naughty teddy” who tried to spoil the game by extending one row while the experimenter was not looking, the number of children who showed number conversation increased dramatically. Given the destructive interference by the teddy bear, the experimenter’s question is quite reasonable because, unknown to the experimenter, the naughty teddy may have changed the number of items. In other words, the experimenter was now requesting information he did not have already. The motive not to repeat a previous response has been shown to account for erroneously low test–retest correlations in projective tests. In Thematic Apperception Tests (TAT) participants are shown a picture and are told to be creative and make up an imaginative story. As Tomkins (1961, cited in Winter & Stewart, 1977) noted, when individuals are shown the same picture at a later time by the same experimenter they are faced with the dilemma of whether they should tell the same story or whether they should follow the test instructions which call for creativity and therefore tell a new story. When instructions stressed that it did not matter whether the story was old or new (Heckhausen, 1963; Lundy, 1985; Winter & Stewart, 1977), or when participants were explicitly instructed to repeat the old story (Winter & Stewart, 1977), test–retest correlations soared. The respondents’ tacit assumption that a question is a request for new information also accounts for a number of question order effects in survey research. Answers to related concepts correlate less when both questions are asked within the same context or close proximity compared to when both questions are asked in different contexts. For example, reported satisfaction and reported happiness correlated higher when both were assessed in different surveys coming from different sources compared to when both questions were presented in the same survey following each other (Strack, Schwarz, & Wänke, 1991). Apparently, respondents interpreted satisfaction as something different from happiness when both questions followed each other, as there would be no need to report the same feeling twice. Whereas one may expect that activating relevant information in a preceding question heightens its accessibility and therefore its use in answering a subsequent question, conversational norms would forbid the use of that information. Instead of assimilation effects – a higher positive correlation between the two answers – the opposite, contrast effects, may result if respondents perceive both questions within one communication context. Presumably, presenting both questions in direct succession implies that both questions must refer to different issues. A specific question about whether or not abortion should be allowed in cases of birth defects in the unborn child lowered support to abortion in general when it was asked before the general question (Schuman, Presser, & Ludwig, 1981). Whereas the general question presented alone included all reasons for abortion, asking the specific question first implied for the respondents that the second question pertained only to abortion when no birth defects were likely. Consequently fewer respondents supported this more limited scenario. Likewise, endorsement for freedom of speech increased when the question was immediately preceded by a question of whether the Ku Klux Klan should have the right to express its opinion in public (Ottati, Riggle, Wyer, Schwarz, & Kuklinski, 1989). CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES Having just expressed concerns about guaranteeing freedom of speech for the Ku Klux Klan, respondents interpreted the general question to be about freedom of speech for groups other than the Ku Klux Klan. Interpreting More Meaning than the Researcher Intended: The Case of Framing Effects Asking the same question twice forces respondents to find another meaning for the second question. Similar are forced choices between options that do not differ, as is standard procedure in decision making and in particular framing. Participants are typically presented with two statistically equal scenarios. For example, in the Asian disease problem in one scenario 200 out of 600 survive whereas the other gives 1/3 probability that 600 survive and a probability of 2/3 that nobody survives (Tversky & Kahneman, 1981). Cooperative participants may infer that the way the two scenarios are presented must represent some difference because, otherwise, asking which of two equal options one prefers would make no sense. In other words, they give subjective meaning to an otherwise absurd question. Other framing effects involve simpler tasks. Often the alternatives are presented between groups and the way an option is framed still has a considerable effect. For example, labeling ground beef as 75% lean made it more attractive to consumers than labeling it as 25% fat (Levin & Gaeth, 1988). Likewise therapies seem more acceptable when described in terms of survival rates as opposed to mortality rates (e.g. Levin, Schnittjer, & Thee, 1988; McNeil, Pauker, Sox, & Tversky, 1982). But as McKenzie and Nelson have pointed out (2003), although formally equivalent both statements differ in their pragmatic meaning. Their research showed that when the outcome of a new therapy lay above the previous survival rate for a disease, a large majority of speakers chose to express this rate in the survival frame (e.g. 25% survival). When the survival rate lay below a previous reference point, they chose a mortality frame. In turn, listeners were sensitive to the speakers’ choice of frame. When a treatment was described in terms of survival rates, it was assumed to be better than a previous treatment compared to when the mortality rate was given. In this realm it is interesting to note that framing effects in the Asian disease problem disappeared when the problem was presented as a statistical rather than a medical problem (Bless, Betsch, & Franzen, 1998). In fact, when participants considered the task as a statistical problem, either option was chosen by about 50%. This suggests that participants realized that both options were statistically equivalent and chose at random. Presumably, choice of words was seen as less diagnostic when the task was to calculate expected values. When perceived as a medical problem, the choice of words presumably communicates reference points of other treatments. A speaker does not only choose slightly different words to express different things. The way something is framed apparently also carries meaning, and research participants and survey respondents seem more sensitive to such underlying meanings than researchers. A similar example comes from comparative questions. For example when asked whether traffic contributes more than industry or less than industry to air pollution, 45% of the respondents thought traffic contributes 237 238 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION more. When the question was framed differently and respondents were asked whether industry contributes more than traffic or less than traffic to air pollution, only 24% thought traffic was the main polluter (Wänke, 1996; Wänke, Schwarz, & Noelle-Neumann, 1995). The reason for such asymmetric comparison judgment lies in respondents focusing on the (grammatical) subject of the comparison and neglecting the referent (Tversky, 1977). Why they do so is an open question, but presumably they assume that the speaker chose this particular comparison object as the subject because this is the target of interest. When people were asked to phrase comparative questions about a target, they themselves chose this target as the subject of the comparison and compared it to another object rather than vice versa (Wänke, 2006). Likewise the asymmetry in comparative judgments following from a focusing on the subject diminished when respondents were told that the target of interest is the referent (Wänke, 2006). Focusing on what the question is all about makes perfect sense. If the Answer is Obvious – Why Ask? Reinterpreting Obvious Questions Conversational norms not only forbid asking the same question twice unless one requests a different answer. Neither would one ask questions to which one knows the answer or to which both partners know the answer is self-evident. Being asked whether Berlin or Gummersbach is the larger city would probably raise some puzzlement and one may begin to wonder whether the question is referring to physical size, because everyone knows that Berlin is bigger. Possibly this violation of conversational rules is the basis of some manifestations of the conjunction fallacy, whereby the co-occurrence of two events is estimated more likely than one event alone. For example, in the famous Linda problem, most respondents guess that Linda is a bank teller and active in the feminist movement rather than merely a bank teller (Tversky & Kahneman, 1983). Yet,“Linda is a bank teller” comprises the more special case of Linda being a bank teller and active in the feminist movement. Therefore logic clearly prescribes that the more special subcategory cannot be more likely than the more general superordinate category. It has been argued that research participants may be aware of the triviality of the problem and therefore reinterpret the question to make it less trivial (Dulaney & Hilton, 1991; Politzer & Noveck; 1991). They do not expect to be asked such obviously nonsense questions and following the cooperative principle try to find out what the researcher really means. As a result they may infer that what is meant by “Linda is bank teller” is that Linda is a bank teller and not active in the feminist movement. Why Doubt a Question? The Case of Fictitious Questions and Presuppositions Yet another violation of the cooperativeness principle is asking about non-existent events or objects. Asking your conversation partner about her opinion on the “educational contribution” presupposes that such a thing exists. Furthermore it communicates that you expect her to know about its existence and to have an opinion on it. Not so in research. In order to demonstrate that responses to social and political surveys may not reflect informed and well-formed attitudes but rather random responses (mental coin flips) which respondents make up in order CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES to avoid admitting ignorance, survey researchers assessed attitudes toward fictitious (or not well known) issues. If respondents reported an attitude rather than admitted that the issue was unfamiliar to them, this was seen as evidence for the random response. A closer look at the data however suggests that respondents did not answer in a random fashion. Rather they seemed to have made sense of the obscure issue in a very reasonable way by using other cues to give the issue a meaning. For example, systematic research showed that respondents used previous topics in the questionnaire to interpret the unfamiliar topic. An “educational contribution” was likely to be interpreted as money students have to pay for their education when a previous question referred to tuition fees, but as a stipend for students when the previous question had referred to stipends. Consequently the proposal was rated as more favorable in the second context compared to the first (Strack et al., 1991). Answers to an equally fictitious “Public Affairs Act” were highly correlated with preceding questions about domestic issues (Bishop, Oldendick, Tuchfarber, & Bennett, 1980). Without a meaningful context, respondents use their general knowledge to interpret ambiguous issues. Several studies showed that respondents did not arbitrarily provide answers to questions about fictitious issues but derived their opinions from other apparently relevant attitudes. For example, opinions on the obscure Monetary Control Bill correlated with concern about inflation (Schuman & Presser, 1981). Those concerned with inflation welcomed the bill, presumably because they interpreted it as an instrument to keep inflation under control. Opinions toward the similarly obscure “Agricultural Trade Act” correlated with one’s general attitude toward the government (Schuman & Presser, 1981). Apparently, respondents in everyday conversations assumed that the interviewer was asking them about an existing issue of which they could be expected to have an opinion. This principle that the researcher’s questions are taken with a guarantee of validity also accounts for some of the astonishing effects in eyewitness research, where merely asking a question may create memories. For example, Elizabeth Loftus (1975) showed research participants a film and then asked them whether they had seen a particular object or event (e.g. “did you see the children getting on the school bus?”). Note that the participants had no reason to believe that there had actually been no school bus and that the researcher led them astray. When participants in such research settings were asked later, they often incorrectly remembered the non-existent object they had earlier been asked for. These findings have attained some publicity in the debate about planted and repressed memory (Loftus & Bernstein, 2005). But planting memories may not be as easy as it sounds; the reconstruction may depend on who asks the question. Witnesses are more influenced when they have every reason to presume that the questioner is knowledgeable about the event and unbiased. If so, they would trust the questions to refer to accurate events. Memory biases were much rarer when witnesses had reasons to mistrust the questions as misleading, for example when asked by a defendant’s lawyer (Dodd & Bradshaw, 1980) or when the questioner was known to be unfamiliar with the event (Smith & Ellsworth, 1987). In the latter case, the presupposition in the question did not come with a guarantee of validity and was therefore dismissed. Below, in the section on media reports, I will give other 239 240 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION examples of how this assumption that questions pertain to valid occurrences can also affect judgment rather than memory. Moderating Conditions There has been little systematic research on condi- tions that might moderate the influence of the cooperative principle on participants’ responses. One may easily assume that the more motivated respondents are to cooperate, the more likely they will try to make sense of the materials, and the more likely they may show effects as discussed. And clearly there may be differences in the ability to attend to others and to read cues. Two results support this view. First, participants high in conversational skills were more likely to show the conjunction fallacy (Slugoski & Wilson, 1998), which is in line with the perspective of the conjunction fallacy being the result of a question reinterpretation. Second, it was found that individuals with an interdependent self-concept, who should be more sensitive to conversational norms, also differentiated more between two seemingly related and adjacent questions than individuals with an independent self-concept (Haberstroh, Oyserman, Schwarz, & Kühnen, 2002). Summary and Appraisal What this research perspective points out is that many of the classic findings in judgment and decision making may be less due to cognitive bias and shortcomings in human judgment and information processing that to a communicative bias: Participants adhere to conversational norms where they are not appropriate. Research participants act as cooperative communicators who assume that all information in the situation is valid and relevant and therefore take it all into account. Likewise survey respondents do their best to find out what information is requested and provide this information. Not surprisingly, in their quest to find meaning, they are influenced by all kinds of seemingly (in the eyes of the researcher) irrelevant features such as previous questions or response scales. However, for a cooperative communicator these features are anything but irrelevant because they give crucial information as to what exactly the researcher wants to know. Rather than response “errors”, order effects, scale effects, or effects of question wording reflect respondents as thinking and socially adept human beings. As valid as this perspective has been proven and as impressive as its evidence sounds, it should be pointed out that Gricean reinterpretations cannot account entirely for the biases identified in judgment and decision making (for a discussion see Shafir & Le Boeuf, 2002). Only rarely did the undermining of conversational norms wipe out the effects completely. Significant reductions attested to some contribution but in many cases the effects were still significant. One should thus not declare 30 years of research invalid merely on Gricean accounts – but maybe it is safe to say that the effects have been inflated to an unknown degree. The more important lesson from this research is, however, to take the cooperative principle into account when planning and conducting research. A final observation may be in order. I have sketched several studies where in order to undermine the maxim of relevance participants were explicitly told that the information was selected at random or may not be diagnostic. Assuming the maxim of relevance, participants now will have to discount this information unless they are uncooperative. But to discount it they may have to find out first how they CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES would normally use it and then correct their judgment. Suppose a participant would not infer any meaning from the order in which arguments in a two-sided message are given. Now the researcher announces that the order is chosen at random. This implies for the participant to consider how order might have an effect if it were not chosen at random. Apparently order is important, otherwise the researcher would not have pointed out not to rely on it. Once the participant has arrived at a theory of how order may influence the judgment, he or she will try to correct for this influence. Presumably, telling participants to discount any information even if it normally has no effect may alter the judgments because participants are likely to produce a theory on how to correct their judgment. To the extent that this occurs, the influence of undermining the cooperativeness itself may be inflated. Pragmatic Implicatures in Mass Communication The examples from research settings have shown that even outside of natural conversations people use the cooperative principle as a general framework to interpret the meaning of communication. Another example of non-natural conversations where the cooperative principle may be used to generate meaning is mass communication. However, the implications of the cooperative principle can vary between different fields, depending on the presumed purpose of the communication. In the field of advertising the purpose is to persuade the audience, whereas the purpose of media reports is to inform an audience of new information. Consequently, the rule “if it is presented it must be relevant” would signal potential persuasiveness of a statement in the advertising context but potential newsworthiness in the news context. Advertising Advertising and marketing are domains where recipients probably do not always assume that statements are true and valid. Although consumers may not suspect explicit lying, many consumers mistrust advertising claims or show at least some caution (e.g. Shavitt, Lowrey, & Haefner, 1998). Whether consumers hedge doubts about the truth of advertising or not, they know that the goal of advertising is to influence them. Paradoxically, it is exactly this knowledge of the communication goal that enables implicatures in advertising statements – and thus possibly deception. Grice’s maxim of relation requires contributions to be relevant to the accepted purpose of the communication. In advertising, the obvious and accepted purpose is to persuade recipients of the benefits and advantages of the advertised good. If this is the accepted goal, then consumers should interpret any statement, whether it be obscure, incomplete, or ambiguous, in a favorable manner to the advertised product. The underlying inference rule is: If an advertiser presents this claim in order to persuade me, then the claim must signal a benefit. The following will give some examples of such implicatures in advertising. Inferring Benefits from Incomplete Information Advertising statements may contain claims or benefits, on the one hand, and supporting data or what 241 242 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION advertisers call the “reason why” on the other hand. Examples for benefits are that the product is healthy, makes hair shiny, shrinks pores, etc. As for why it does so, any product attribute or combination of product attributes may be given. Quite often an ingredient (oat bran; enzymes) or the manufacturing process (hand-made; organically grown) is given to support the claimed benefit but any attribute will do. Of course, these attributes should only support the claimed benefit if consumers see a link between the two. For example “yoghurt X has a rich and creamy flavor (benefit) because it is made of whole milk (reason why)” is credible if consumers believe that whole milk makes for a rich flavor. “Yoghurt X has a rich flavor because it comes in glass containers” does not seem particularly convincing at first glance, unless consumers believe that glass containers are beneficial to flavor. One would expect then that advertising would only use such attributes as reasons where the implications are clear, or that they would educate the consumers on why a particular attribute has a particular benefit. However, as Areni (2002) pointed out, a much used rhetoric form in advertising, the enthymeme, lacks this link or conditional rule between attributes (data) and benefit. Consider the following example taken from Areni (2002; p. 179). By combining 2 liquids that activate to form a foam, New Liquid Plumr Foaming Pipe Snake cleans your pipe walls quickly and easily. Here, the benefit “effective pipe cleaning” is supported by a single attribute “foam”. Why foam should be particularly efficient for cleaning pipes is, however, not said. The link between data and benefit is missing. This is where pragmatic implicatures come into play. According to the maxim of relation, one should only give information that is relevant to the point one wants to make. Therefore presenting any attributes in an advert – whose goal is to claim a particular benefit – implicates a link between these attributes and the benefit. As Areni put it, “Grice’s prescription dictates that presenting data conversationally implicates a conditional rule, and it is this principle that allows enthymemes to be transformed into coherent arguments” (p.179). Note that sometimes the link between attributes and benefit pertains to beliefs that consumers already have, for example that full milk gives yoghurt a rich flavor. The “Liquid Plumr” example illustrates however that merely by presenting data and benefits together consumers may newly form such associations. Here, consumers implicitly learn that foam is efficient for cleaning pipes. In this respect, the example “yoghurt X has a rich flavor because it comes in glass containers” may not turn out so incredible after all. Consumers might start to believe that glass containers enable a rich flavor – or why else would the advertiser say so. Enthymemes are incomplete insofar that they do not account for why a particular attribute supports the benefit. Conversational implicatures fill this missing link. This strategy may even be drawn one step further. Quite often products advertise certain features or attributes although no explanation or benefit is given. Consider a body lotion featuring “with Recitin” in bold letters on the package. What Recitin is and what it is good for is not known. For all we know it may be harmful. Nevertheless, because consumers expect that what is conveyed CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES in an advert is relevant to product quality they are likely to infer positive benefits no matter how obscure the attributes. If a feature is advertised it must signal a benefit, otherwise the marketers would not emphasize it. Several studies support this assumption (Wänke & Friese, 2006). For example, consumers were shown a body lotion featuring “with Recitin” – a fictitious ingredient – quite prominently on the package. These consumers then believed that body lotions that contain Recitin were healthier, better for the skin, and generally of better quality than body lotions that did not contain Recitin. In another study, participants estimated higher prices and were willing to pay higher prices for products that claimed obscure attributes compared to no attribute information. Real world examples are plenty: detergent with active oxygen, yoghurt with acidophylis bacteria, sun-screen lotion with PABA, anti-aging cream with fructo-enzymes, etc. Of course, this may present itself as an attractive and versatile marketing strategy: Let the consumers come up with something they find believable. Note that according to this logic the absence of a feature if advertised in bold letters would also signal a benefit, otherwise the marketer would rather hide the lack. And indeed consumers who had seen a body lotion featuring the claim “without Recitin” rated body lotions that contain Recitin less favorably compared to body lotions that were free of Recitin. Estimated prices and willingness to pay were also higher compared to a control group that saw no claims when the products claimed the lack of the respective attributes (Wänke & Friese, 2006). Whether a product advertised the presence or the absence of an obscure feature, both enhanced the product’s estimated price and what consumers were willing to pay. In principle, marketers could just invent an obscure feature and advertise the absence of it in their products: “guaranteed enzyme-free”, “no artificial bacteria”, “has not been processed over 25 degrees Celsius”. Given that consumers have no knowledge about an ingredient and its benefits, they infer its significance from the fact that it is advertised and therefore meant to persuade them. If a marketer emphasizes that a brand contains X, then X must be good or in principle a feature that enhances the brand’s attractiveness. If, however, marketers stress that the brand does not contain X, this lack of ingredient must be an advantage, otherwise they would not highlight it. The same also applies to quantifiers. Consumers are quite often ignorant about what constitutes high or low amounts or degrees of a feature. As mentioned above they can easily be misled by labels such as 25% fat or 75% lean (Levin & Gaeth, 1988; Sanford, Fay, Stewart, & Moxey, 2002). Again, however, if what is advertised signals benefits then even arbitrary numbers may become meaningful. When featured prominently on a package of a diet or “light” product 25% fat is likely to be interpreted as low, particularly when phrased as “only 25% fat” (see also Moxey & Sanford, 2000). A third form of presenting incomplete information and relying on recipients’ own inferences are incomplete comparisons. Claims like “brand X shampoo leaves hair shinier” are common in advertising. Consumers are likely to conclude that brand X leaves hair shinier than (all) other brands (Shimp, 1978). This however is not stated. In fact, brand X might leave hair only shinier than no shampoo would or, worse yet, soap would. Again, consumers implicitly assume the claim to be informative and relevant (and true in that case), a requirement that is best fulfilled 243 244 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION by a meaningful comparison standard such as another brand but not by obvious or ridiculous comparisons. Inferences about Competitors So far I have only considered implicatures regarding the advertised product. The above examples however also illustrate a second implicature. Claiming that brand X does not contain enzymes may not only lead consumers to infer that enzymes are undesirable but also that other brands may contain enzymes (which is undesirable). Likewise of course, highlighting a particular feature may suggest that other brands do not have this feature. In this way, advertising may be misleading. For example, advertising avocados as cholesterol free is, although true, misleading because consumers may falsely infer that other fruits do contain cholesterol. Consider the advert in Figure 8.1. At first glance this advert may seem to reflect a weird sense of humor. Normally restaurants do not serve dogs, cats, rats, or worms. This advert, however, was taken from a tourist magazine in South East Asia, where tourists may be willing to believe that restaurants might serve all of the above. If so this advert will certainly strengthen that belief. A claim of a dog-free cuisine would hardly be necessary if that were normal in this part of the world. So the advert becomes informative in two respects: this restaurant does not serve dog but other restaurants do. The advert also has a double meaning. Recipients who know that tourist restaurants in Cambodia are unlikely to serve dogs will find the advert amusing as it mocks the stereotype. It suggests – or pretends to suggest – that there are people who believe that Cambodian restaurants might serve dogs and it is thus entertaining for those who know better. Two-Sided or Negative Messages In advertising, two-sided messages increase credibility. Moreover, unfavorable information may enhance the product appeal compared to one-sided messages if the unfavorable information supports the implications of the favorable one (Bohner, Einwiller, Erb, & Siebler, 2003; Pechmann, 1992). For example, the headline in the Nikon advert in Figure 8.2 below claims the camera is “too big, heavy, complicated, and expensive”. The finer print reveals that the camera is made for professional photographers who need more versatility, better materials, and more advanced technology than amateur photographers, which makes the camera also a bit bigger, heavier, more complicated, and more expensive. Here, the negative and positive attributes are correlated and as a whole the advert becomes more credible. Possibly, the recipients’ expectation that whatever is conveyed in an advert should be persuasive contributes to this effect. Assuming that advertising information is meant to increase the appeal of the product, recipients may be particularly prone to interpret negative product information positively. If the unfavorable product information were encountered in a different context where recipients expect a different communication purpose, for example the same headline as in the advert in a consumer report, the unfavorable information may decrease a product’s attractiveness. Consider an advert for a chili sauce saying “Warning: Unbearably hot”. Then consider the same verdict given by a food magazine’s taste testing. Clearly the statement coming from the second source may be CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES FIGURE 8.1 Advertisement 1: Example of implicatures about competitors. considered as a warning to stay away from the sauce whereas coming from the marketer it is not at all considered literally. No marketers in their right mind would seriously deter consumers from their product. Hence, the statement is not to be taken literally as a warning but rather as an allure for spicy food lovers. Within the context of advertising, two-sided and negative messages may thus represent an efficient communication strategy because the recipients reinterpret 245 246 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION FIGURE 8.2 Advertisement 2: Example of two-sided messages in advertising (reproduced with permission). the presumably negative attributes. Yet the order of presentation may also be crucial. The Order of Arguments As mentioned above, conversational norms would suggest presenting the more important – in this case the favorable information – last. Later arguments are seen as more important in two-sided messages, because recipients may infer that if the first argument was all there is to say the communicator may have left it at that. Apparently, the communicator is giving vital information; otherwise adding information would violate the conversational rule to be brief and informative. Studies that varied the order in two-sided messages found indeed that the later argument was considered as more important for the communicator (Krosnick et al., 1990) and was also more persuasive (Igou & Bless, 2003b). Note however that theses studies only investigated the impact of arguments that had really opposite implications but not adverts where the negative arguments were actually meant to convey positive information. Bohner and his colleagues (2003) presented the negative arguments last in the restaurant advert but found no negative impact. One may only wonder whether a reversal would even show a larger advantage compared to a one-sided message or whether in two-sided advertising the order of the negative and positive arguments does not matter because all are interpreted favorably anyway. Two-sided advertising, even if it is only rhetorical, is however the exception. Usually all arguments are favorable. Nevertheless, when more than one argument is presented the arguments may vary in strength. This renders the question about the best sequence of presenting them. Should one begin with the strongest and CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES most compelling feature or save the best for last? Primacy and recency accounts from information processing make different predictions depending on other conditions. Communicative aspects also allow for contradictory predictions. On the one hand, one may argue that because according to conversational norms contributions should be relevant, informative, and brief, the most important information should be placed at the beginning. One the other hand, one may equally argue that if the initially presented information was all there is to say one may just stop there, therefore the later information would be more important. Although the latter prediction was supported for two-sided communication as mentioned above, for one-sided messages the former hypothesis was supported. An audience seems to expect a communicator to present the strong arguments at the beginning (Igou & Bless, 2003b). Moreover, persuasion was higher when stronger arguments were presented first and the weaker arguments last rather than vice versa (Igou & Bless, 2003b; Unnava, Burnkraut, & Erevelles, 1994). Are Advertising Implicatures Effective? Paradoxically, knowing about the advert’s persuasive purpose may make recipients particularly susceptible because they might interpret any statement, whether positive, obscure, or even negative, as intended favorably. The question however remains whether conversational implicatures are more successful than direct assertions. Some evidence suggests that they may be at least not inferior to direct assertions (Harris, 1977; Harris, Pounds, Majorelle, & Mermis, 1993)4 and one may speculate when they are actually superior. Harris and his colleagues (1977, 1993) pitted assertion commercials against different types of implication commercials. For example, the assertion commercial read “. . . . Taking Eradicold Pills as directed will get you through a winter without colds” whereas the implication commercial juxtaposed imperatives to imply a causal connection “Get through a winter without colds. Take Eradicold Pills as directed”. When later asked whether the advert had stated a causal relationship, recipients saw little difference between the two versions in particular after a delay. When it came to purchase decisions, implied claims were just as successful as asserted claims (Harris, 1977) or even more successful (Harris et al., 1993). Moreover, evidence from another domain suggests that self-generated inferences from adverts are particularly effective in that they are recalled better (Moore, Reardon, & Durso, 1986) and are more persuasive (Sawyer & Howard, 1991). Explicitly presented claims have the disadvantage that consumers are likely to scrutinize them critically, even more so if they are generally rather skeptical about advertising. Lengthy and complicated explanations why a particular feature brings a particular benefit may sound unconvincing unless they are self-evident. Areni (2002) therefore suggests – although he has not tested his hypothesis yet – that plausible links between a feature and a benefit should be stated, but implausible and less obvious ones are better implied by enthymemes. One should note that even skeptical consumers do not mistrust all advertising statements equally. Consumer researchers distinguish between search attributes, experience attributes, and credence attributes (Darby & Karni, 1973; Nelson, 1974). Whereas before consumption the choice was based on search attributes 247 248 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION (price, brand, product design, and attributes), experience attributes, such as taste or comfort, are available only after product trial, and credence attributes, such as reliability, require a long-term usage. Note that in contrast to experience attributes, which are by definition of subjective nature, most search attributes are, at least in principle, objectively verifiable. Their verifiability would predict that they tend to be true because the market and legal regulations would punish untruthful marketers. Accordingly, consumers tend to be more skeptical of claims regarding experience attributes such as taste compared to claims about search attributes (Ford, Smith, & Swasy, 1990). By and large, consumers trust that the product contains the features listed on the package and other verifiable claims. They would not believe that marketers would lie so obviously. If the advert says the margarine contains alphabetamins that is hardly doubted. What may be doubted is that alphabetamins give a boost of energy and improve one’s health. Thus, it may be better to let consumers make those inferences by themselves rather than explicitly state them. When advertising mere features without claiming benefits, the actual benefit is left to the imagination of the consumer. This makes for a very versatile strategy. The feature does whatever the consumer wants to believe. Quite likely indirect or implied claims have yet another advantage. Marketers may be able to implicate what they could not say explicitly without being challenged legally or otherwise. A statement “leaves hair shinier than all other brands” would certainly be challenged by competitors. In some countries advertisers would be required to give some evidence to prove their claim. Not so for the statement “leaves hair shinier”. Advertisers cannot be accused of deception if all they do is advertise a certain feature and leave it to the consumer to infer why it is favorable. In summary, implicated benefits seem to be a highly effective advertising strategy. Some of the assumptions and suggestions discussed here were of course speculative and need further empirical testing. However, if we assume that the market provides some kind of test, then at least some of the strategies seem to fare rather well in the real world. Media Reports “Can media questions become public answers?” Merely phrasing this question would suggest that the answer is “yes”. At least this was the conclusion of a highly influential research article (Wegener, Wenzlaff, Kerker, & Beattie, 1981). In this research, newspaper headlines in the form of incriminating questions (Is Karen Downing Associated With Fraudulent Charity?) led to equally negative evaluations of a person as an assertive headline (Karen Downing Associated With Fraudulent Charity). Although different accounts are possible, one explanation is that media recipients apply the cooperative principle when interpreting media messages. Such a question as “Is Karen Downing associated with fraudulent charity?” could be answered either with yes or no, and therefore there may seem nothing wrong with merely asking the question. At least this is the media’s defense argument. But the question acquires an added meaning when posed in the context of a newspaper headline. The purpose of the newspaper is to inform readers of new events and developments. Based on this assumption readers would infer from such a headline that new evidence appeared that makes CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES this question plausible. Completely off the wall assumptions would hardly make headlines, at least not in the serious media. The underlying inference rule here is that if it is reported in the news it must be informative and new for a general audience. Such an assumption would also explain pragmatic interpretations of newspaper assertions and denials (Gruenfeld & Wyer, 1992). When a statement that was a priori not believed (e.g. The CIA is currently involved in illegal drug trafficking) was presented as a newspaper headline, its credibility increased just as if it were presented from a reference source (encyclopedia, almanac, etc.). This may be considered an indicator for people’s trust that the media speaks the truth. However, the credibility of the statement increased just the same when the newspaper headline denied the statement, whereas denials in reference sources did not increase credibility significantly. Presumably, when media recipients encounter a statement that is congruent with their former beliefs (The CIA is not involved in illegal drug trafficking), they may begin wondering why the seemingly uninformative and redundant statement was made. In turn, this may lead them to infer that there are reasons that make the denial necessary, one of them being that there may be some truth to the accusation. Consequently, their belief in the proposition is heightened. Gruenfeld and Wyer (1992) argue that reference sources whose primary purpose is to record archival knowledge would invoke pragmatic interpretations to a lesser degree and readers would rely on the semantic implications. Therefore denials in reference sources would lead readers to believe the proposition rather than its denial. This assumption, although in line with the obtained results, is not entirely convincing at first glance. After all, why should an encyclopedia record a denial unless there was a reason, for example countering a widespread but false belief. Possibly, readers trusted the truth of reference sources more, whereas for media headlines some doubts remained. Interestingly, although denials in reference sources did not increase the credibility of the denied propositions, they nevertheless increased the credibility of related propositions (e.g. The CIA has been involved in illegal drug dealing in the past). Apparently readers did interpret the denial as evidence that there was some truth to the fact, otherwise a denial would not be necessary. The effect also works the other way around. A newspaper headline that affirms a proposition, which readers do believe anyway (e.g. Republican congressmen belong to elitist country clubs), may decrease beliefs in its validity, although these effects are less robust. Clearly this research illustrates how printing the truth and nothing but the truth may still create false impressions. How pragmatic interpretations may influence opinions is also suggested by other examples. Imagine a headline “Not all American college students drive American cars”. Although media reports may give statistics and facts for facts’ sake, one known purpose of the media is to draw the public’s attention to undesirable and (less so) desirable states of affairs. Hence, a pragmatic interpretation would also affect the inferred desirability and thus readers’ attitudes. In line with these considerations, exposure to the above statement increased recipients’ beliefs that more college students should drive American cars, and this effect was greater when the source was a newspaper rather than a reference volume (Gruenfeld & Wyer, 1992). When it appears in a newspaper 249 250 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION headline the phrasing “not all students” is not interpreted as a descriptive figure any longer but rather as an indicator of an undesirable state. It may not even take such loaded phrases as “not all”, which are probably suggestive in most contexts. Imagine that according to a statistic 35% of children under 16 play an instrument. Unless one has some benchmark statistics at hand, it is unclear whether that number is high or low. Now imagine a headline “More than a third of children under 16 play an instrument” vs. “Less than 40% of children under 16 play an instrument”. A media recipient would not assume that the reference points of “a third” and “40%” are chosen arbitrarily but that these are the critical benchmarks known to the writers of the news article (see also McKenzie & Nelson, 2003). After all, the fact that this statistic is given in the news implies that it represents a deviation from some standard or expectation, otherwise it would hardly be noteworthy. By the comparative phrasing the direction of the deviation is communicated as well and the recipient gets the impression that the incidence rate is high in the first headline but low in the second one (Teigen, Halberg, & Fostervold, in press). One may further imagine that the second headline is more suitable in raising money for public music education than the first. Summary The postulate that “communicated information comes with a guar- antee of relevance” (Sperber & Wilson, 1986) may take different forms. Advertising claims come with a guarantee that the claim is favorable for the consumer; news items come with the guarantee that the item is informative to a general audience, noteworthy, and possibly important. What is intriguing about this perspective is the reversal of dynamics. According to most persuasion models, one would expect that persuasion is the result of being presented with favorable information. The present perspective suggests however that an argument may be perceived as favorable merely because it is part of a persuasion attempt. Likewise, a fact may become noteworthy merely because it is presented in the news. CONCLUSION Grice’s (1975) principle of cooperation is the key to understand meaning not only in natural conversations but in many other, artificial and technical, communication settings. It is the key to understand irony and teasing, and it is exploited in mass communication and marketing. It leads research participants astray in standardized research settings where they inappropriately adhere to it. But although it represents a valuable rule to generate meaning, it is not sufficient. As has been discussed, the cooperative principle has different implications depending on the purpose of the communication. Hence, knowing the purpose is a crucial requirement for inferences. In addition, other knowledge and cues, such as being familiar with the speaker’s background or shared cultural knowledge, may be necessary. In the beginning of the chapter I suggested that Joe bear could have figured out the meaning of Irving’s comment about the beehive had he – or the computer program TALESPIN – only known that Irving was cooperative. The reliance on conversational norms may not guard against all misunderstandings, however, as is CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES illustrated by the next story that TALESPIN produced. Understanding now that beehive is a reasonable answer, Joe did not beat up Irving anymore but instead went and ate the beehive. NOTES 1. 2. 3. 4. That people are often led astray by judging the likelihood of an event by the ease with which instances come to mind (Tversky & Kahneman, 1973). To be exact, close others may also feel offended if present. Where possible I will present recent research not covered in the previous reviews. Many other studies have shown the effectiveness of implied claims but they refer to different types of implications (e.g. Burke, DeSarbo, & Robertson, 1988; Russo, Metcalf, & Stephens, 1981; Searleman & Carter, 1988). REFERENCES Areni, C.S. (2002). The proposition-probability model of argument structure and message acceptance. Journal of Consumer Research, 29, 168–187. Ariely. D., & Loewenstein, G. (2000). When does duration matter in judgment and decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 129, 508–523. Bishop, G.F., Oldendick, R.W., Tuchfarber, A.J., & Bennett, S. E. (1980). Pseudo-opinions on public affairs. Public Opinion Quarterly, 50, 240–250. Blank, H. (1997). Cooperative participants discriminate (not always): A logic conversation approach to the minimal group paradigm. Current Research in Psychology, 2. www.uiowa.edu/∼grpproc/crisp/crisp.2.5.htm Bless, H., Betsch, T., & Franzen, A. (1998). Framing the framing effect: The impact of context cues on solutions ot the “Asian disease” problem. European Journal of Social Psychology, 28, 287–291. Bless, H., Schwarz, N., & Strack, F. (1993). The informative functions of research procedures: Bias and the logic of conversation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 23, 149–165. Bohner, G., Einwiller, S., Erb, H.-P., & Siebler, F. (2003). When small means comfortable: Relations between product attributes in two-sided advertising. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 13, 454–463. Burke, R.R., DeSarbo, O., & Robertson, T.S. (1988). Deception by implication: An experimental investigation. Journal of Consumer Research, 14, 483–494. Choi, I., & Choi, D. W. (2003). The logic of conversation and the fault tree. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 25, 205–212. Clark, H.H., & Clark, E.V. (1977). Psychology and language. New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich. Clark, H.H., & Gerrig (1984). On the pretense theory of irony. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 121–126. Clark, H. H., & Marshall, C.R. (1981). Definite reference and mutual knowledge. In A. K. Joshi, B. Webber, & I.Sag (Eds.). Linguistic structure and discourse setting (pp. 10–63). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Clark, H.H., & Schober, M.F. (1991). Asking questions and influencing answers. In J.M. Tanur (Ed.), Questions about questions (pp. 15–48). New York: Russell Sage. 251 252 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION Darby, M., & Karni, E. (1973). Free competition and the optimal amount of fraud. Journal of Law and Economics, 16, 67–86. Dodd, D.H., and Bradshaw, J.M. (1980). Leading questions and memory: Pragmatic constraints. Journal of Verbal Learning and Behavior, 19, 695–704. Dulaney, D.E., & Hilton, D. J. (1991). Conversational implicature, conscious representation, and the conjunction fallacy. Social Cognition, 9, 85–110. Fischhoff, B., Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein, S. (1978). Fault trees: Sensitivity of estimated failure probabilities to problem representation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 4, 330–344. Ford, G. T., Smith, D. B., & Swasy, J. L. (1990). Consumer skepticism of advertising claims: Testing hypotheses from economics of information. Journal of Consumer Research, 16, 433–441. Fredrickson, B.L., & Kahneman, D. (1993). Duration neglect in retrospective evaluations of affective episodes. Psychological Science, 46, 401–405. Grice, H.-P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P.Cole & J.L. Morgan (Eds.) Syntax and semantics, 3: Speech acts (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press. Grice, H.-P. (1978). Further notes on logic and conversation. In P.Cole (Ed.) Syntax and semantics, 9: Pragmatics (pp. 113–128). New York: Academic Press. Gruenfeld, D. H., & Wyer, R. S. (1992). Semantics and pragmatics of social influence: How affirmations and denials affect beliefs in referent propositions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 38–49. Haberstroh, S., Oyserman, D., Schwarz, N., & Kühnen, U. (2002). Is the interdendent self more sensitive to question context than the independent self? Self-construal and the observation of conversational norms. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 323–329. Harris, J.H., Pounds, J.C., Maiorelle, M., & Mermis, M. (1993). The effect of type of claim, gender and buying history on the drawing of pragmatic inferences from advertising claims. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 13, 454–463. Harris, R.J. (1977). Comprehension of pragmatic implications in advertising. Journal of Appplied Psychology, 62, 603–608. Heckhausen, H. (1963). Hoffnung und Furcht in der Leistüngsmotivation. Meisenheim am Glan: Verlag Anton Hain. Hilton, D.J. (1990). Conversational processes and causal explanation. Psychological Bulletin, 107, 65–81. Hilton, D.J. (1995). The social context of reasoning: Conversational inference and rational judgment. Psychological Bulletin, 118, 248–271. Igou, E.R., & Bless, H. (2003a). The conversational basis for the dilution effect. Journal of Language and Social Psychology, 22, 1–11. Igou, E.R., & Bless, H. (2003b). Inferring the importance of arguments: order effects and conversational rules. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 39, 91–99. Igou, E.R., Bless, H., & Schwarz, N. (2002). Making sense of standardized survey questions: The influence of reference periods and their repetition. Communication Monographs, 69, 179–187. Jones, E.E., & Harris, V. A. (1967). The attribution of attitudes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 3, 1–24. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1973). On the psychology of prediction. Psychological Review, 80, 237–251. Krosnick, J. A., Li, F., & Lehman, D, R. (1990). Conversational conventions, order of information acquisition, and the effect of base rates and individuating information on social judgment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 1140–1152. CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES Levin, I. P., & Gaeth, G. J. (1988). How consumers are affected by the framing of attribute information before and after consuming the product. Journal of Consumer Research, 15, 374–378. Levin, I.P., Schittler, S.K., & Thee, S.L. (1988). Information framing effects in social and personal decisions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 24, 520–529. Loftus, E. (1975). Leading questions and eye witness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 560–572. Loftus, E., & Bernstein, D.M. (2005). Rich false memories: The royal road to success. In A. Healy (Ed.), Experimental cognitive psychology and its applications: festschrift in honor of Lyle Bourne, Walter Kintsch, and Thomas Landauer. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Lundy, A. (1985). The reliability of the Thematic Apperception Test. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49, 141–145. McCann, C.D., & Higgins, E.T. (1992). Personal and contextual factors in communication: A review of the communication game. In G.R. Semin & K. Fiedler (Eds.), Language, interaction and social cognition (pp. 144–172). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. McGarrigle, J., & Donaldson, M. (1974). Conversation accidents. Cognition, 3, 341–350. McKenzie, C.R.M., & Nelson, J.D. (2003). What a speaker’s choice of frame reveals: Reference points, frame selection and framing effects. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 10, 596–602. McNeil, B.J., Pauker, S.G., Sox, H.C. Jr., & Tversky, A. (1982). On the elicitation of preferences for alternative therapies. New England Journal of Medicine, 306, 1259–1262. Moore, D.J., Reardon, R., & Durso, F.T. (1986). The generation effect in advertising appeals. Advances in Consumer Research, 6, 123–140. Moxey, L.M., & Sanford, A. J. (2000). Communicating quatities: A review of psycholinguistic evidence of how expressions determine perspectives. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 14, 237–255. Nelson, P. (1974). Advertising as Information. Journal of Political Economy, 82, 729–754. Nisbett, R.E., Zukier, H., & Lemley, R.E. (1981). The dilution effect: Nondiagnostic information weakens the impact of diagnostic information. Cognitive Psychology, 13, 248–277. Ottati, V.C., Riggle, E.J., Wyer, R.S., Schwarz, N., & Kuklinski, J. (1989). The cognitive and affective bases of opinion survey responses. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 404–415. Pechman, C. (1992). Prediciting when two-sided ads will be more effective than one-sided ads: The role of correlational and correspondent inferences. Journal of Marketing Research, 29, 441–453. Piaget, J. (1952). The child’s conception of number. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Politzer, G., & Noveck, I.A. (1991). Are conjunction rule violations the result of conversational rule violations? Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 20, 83–103. Russo, J.E., Metcalf, B.L., & Stephens, D. (1981). Identifying misleading advertising. Journal of Consumer Research, 8, 119–131. Sanford, A. J., Fay, N., Stewart, A. J., & Moxey, M. (2002). Perspectives in statements of quantity, with implications for consumer psychology. Psychological Science, 13, 130–134. Sawyer, A.G., & Howard, D.J. (1991). Effects of omitting conclusions in advertisements to involved and uninvolved audiences. Journal of Marketing Research, 28, 467–474. Schank, R.C., & Childers, P.G. (1984). The cognitive computer. Reading, MA: AddisonWesley. 253 254 SOCIAL COMMUNICATION Schuman, H., & Presser, S. (1981). Questions and answers in attitude surveys. New York: Academic Press. Schuman, H., Presser, S., & Ludwig, J. (1981). Context effects on survey responses to questions about abortion. Public-Opinion-Quarterly, 45, 216–223 Schwarz, N. (1996). Cognition and communication., Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum. Schwarz, N., Strack, F., Hilton, D.J., & Naderer, G. (1991). Judgmental biases and the logic of conversation: The contextual relevance of irrelevant information. Social Cognition, 9, 67–84. Schwarz, N., Strack, F., Müller, G., & Chassein, B. (1988). The range of response alternatives may determine the meaning of the question: Further evidence of informative functions of response alternatives. Social Cognition, 6, 107–117. Searleman, A., & Carter, H. (1988). The effectiveness of different types of pragmatic implications found in commercials to mislead subjects. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 2, 265–272. Shafir, E., & Le Boeuf, R.A. (2002). Rationality. Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 491–517. Shavitt, S., Lowrey, P., & Haefner, J. (1998). Public attitudes toward advertising: More favorable than you might think. Journal of Advertising Research, July–August, 7–22. Shimp, T.A. (1978). Do incomplete comparisons mislead? Journal of Advertising Research, 18, 21–27. Slugoski, B. R., & Wilson, A. E. (1998). Contribution of conversational skills to the production of judgmental error. European Journal of Social Psychology, 28, 575–601. Smith, V.L., & Ellsworth, P.C. (1987). The social psychology of eyewitness accuracy: Misleading questions and communicator expertise. Journal of Applied Psychology, 72, 294–300 Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Strack, F., Schwarz, N., & Wänke, M. (1991). Semantic and pragmatic aspects of context effects in social and psychological research. Social Cognition, 9, 111–125. Teigen, K. H., Halberg, A.-M., & Fostervold, K. I. (in press). Single-limit interval estimates as reference points. Applied Cognitive Psychology. Tetlock, P.E., Lerner, J.S., & Boettger, R. (1996). The dilution effect: Judgmental bias, conversational convention or a bit of both? European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 915–934. Tversky, A. (1977). Features of similarity. Psychological Review, 84, 327–352. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207–232. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90, 293–315. Unnava, H.R., Burnkraut, R.E., & Erevelles, S. (1994). Effects of presentation order and communication modality on recall and attitude. Journal of Consumer Research, 21, 481–490 Varey, C.A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Experiences extended across time: Evaluation of moments and episodes. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 5, 169–185. Wänke, M. (1996). Comparative judgments as a function of the direction of comparison versus word order. Public Opinion Quarterly, 60, 400–409. Wänke, M. (2002). Conversational norms and the interpretation of vague quantifiers. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 16, 301–307. CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURES Wänke, M. (2006). Determining the focus of comparison: Simply choose what seems most relevant. Unpublished manuscript. Universität Basel. Wänke, M., & Friese, M. (2006). Unpublished data. Universität Basel. Wänke, M., Schwarz, N., & Noelle-Neumann, E. (1995). Question wording in comparative judgments: Understanding and manipulating the dynamics of the direction of comparison. Public Opinion Quarterly, 59, 347–372. Wegener, D.M., Wenzlaff, R., Kerker, R.M., & Beattie, A.E. (1981). Incrimination through innuendo: Can media questions become public answers? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 40, 822–832. Winter, D. G., & Stewart, A. J. (1977). Power motive reliability as a function of retest instructions. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 45, 436–440. Wright, E.F., & Wells, G.L. (1988). Is the attitude-attribution paradigm suitable for investigating the dispositional bias. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 14, 183–190. Wyer, R.S., & Collins, J. E. III (1992). A theory of humor elicitation. Psychological Review, 99, 663–688. Zukier, H. (1982). The dilution effect: The role of the correlation and the dispersion of predictor variables in the use of nondiagnostic information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 1163–1174. 255
© Copyright 2024