P Parametric Sample Selection Models regression and are distinguished thereby from William Rhodes Abt Associates Inc., Cambridge, MA, USA Overview James Heckman’s work (1976, 1979) regarding the consequences and solutions for sample selection bias has influenced three decades of social science research. For this and related contributions, he won a Nobel Prize in economics. Heckman’s original solution requires strong parametric assumptions. When wrong, those assumptions can lead to parameter estimates with mean-squared errors worse than those of estimators that ignore selection bias. Nevertheless, the parametric approach remains popular. Discussions appear in econometrics textbooks (Davidson and MacKinnon 1993, pp. 542–545; Cameron and Trivedi 2005, pp. 546–569; Greene 2008, pp. 863–903) and technical papers; estimation routines appear in standard econometrics software; and the approach is frequently used in criminal justice research (Bushway et al. 2007). Criminologist and criminal justice researchers cannot disregard the parametric approach. All estimators require some parametric assumptions, so what distinguishes estimators that are parametric from another class? Estimators considered in this entry require strong distributional assumptions about error terms in a estimators that impose weaker assumptions. Without being comprehensive, this entry identifies six cases where selection bias occurs in criminal justice research: • Sample selection due to unobserved variables • Estimating treatment effects using observational data • Breakdowns in randomized controlled trials • Survival models with censoring and competing events • Endogenous stratification/choice-based sampling • Missing data This entry shows how parametric assumptions can overcome bias but also how the approach can fail. It illustrates points with Monte Carlo experiments. Theoretical Background To motivate a discussion, consider a data generation process (DGP) comprising two equations. The first is the outcome equation: It explains the outcome of interest in terms of explanatory variables. The objective is to estimate one or more parameters of this outcome equation. The second is the selection equation: It explains how data get sampled for analysis. Selection bias may occur when the same factors affect both sampling and outcome (Rosenbaum 2002). After introducing notation, this entry explains when selection bias occurs and how parametric models correct for bias. G. Bruinsma, D. Weisburd (eds.), Encyclopedia of Criminology and Criminal Justice, DOI 10.1007/978-1-4614-5690-2, # Springer Science+Business Media New York 2014 P 3430 When writing the two equations, use the notation: Y Denotes the outcome measure: the dependent variable in the first equation. A subscript denoting the ith observation is implicit. S Denotes the selection measure: the dependent variable in the second equation. Its interpretation will differ across the six cases. X This is an observed row vector of variables that affect both Y and S. Observed means that the researcher has measured these variables and uses them in the analysis. X typically includes a constant. W This is an unobserved row vector of variables that affect both Y and S. The researcher has not measured these variables or else omits them from the analysis. Assume that unobserved variables are distributed independent of other explanatory variables appearing in the outcome equation; consequences of assuming otherwise are discussed subsequently. V This is a vector of observed variables that affect Y but not S. Z This is a vector of variables that affect S but not Y. When observed, the vector comprises instrumental variables used to impose identification restrictions. b This represents a conformable column vector of parameters appearing in the outcome equation. Subscripts will denote whether these pertain to X, W, or V. Conformable means the column vector b has as many elements as the row vectors X, W, and V. a This represents a conformable column vector of parameters appearing in the selection equation. Subscript will denote whether these parameters pertain to X, W, or Z. e This represents an error term pertaining to the first equation. u This represents an error term pertaining to the second equation. For simplicity, assume the error terms are mean-zero, identically and independently Parametric Sample Selection Models distributed within each equation, independently distributed across equations, and independent of X, W, V, and Z. Assuming otherwise would add complications without enhancing insight. Given this notation and limiting the immediate discussion to linear models, a general data generation process (DGP) is written: Y ¼ XbX þ WbW þ VbV þ e (1) S ¼ XaX þ WaW þ ZaZ þ u (2) A DGP is the actual stochastic process generating the data. The researcher necessarily omits unobserved variables from the analysis, so a model of the DGP is expressed as: Y ¼ XbX þ VbV þ e (3) S ¼ XaX þ ZaZ þ u (4) The error terms change to e* and u*: e ¼ e þ WbW u ¼ u þ WaW (5) Some additional notation will be useful: This is the variance of e*. This is the variance of u*. se u This is the covariance of e* and u*. Although e is independent of X in the population, the following section will show that e* is not independent of X in the sample used for estimation. Consequently, a regression based on model (3) will violate a fundamental assumption: errors must be independent of explanatory variables. Standard regression procedures yield biased and inconsistent estimates of bX. Is the DGP encapsulated by Eqs. 1 and 2 plausible or just abstract mumbo-jumbo? In fact behavioral models often translate into DGPs with counterparts to Eqs. 1 and 2. Based on perceptions of self-interest, individuals elect to participate in activities (Eq. 2) studied by researchers (Eq. 1). Alternatively, based on perceptions of community interests, agents (prosecutors, judges, probation officers, etc.) perform selection to s2e s2u Parametric Sample Selection Models 3431 enhance community safety. Thus, the DGP and statistical models cover situations common to criminology/criminal justice. Correctly specified parametric models eliminate selection bias. One approach uses maximum likelihood or partial likelihood to estimate parameters of the joint distribution of e* and u* in the sample. The joint distribution is written as fb ðe ; u jsampleÞ (6) The a, b, and s parameters are implicit arguments in this distribution. The notation indicates that the distribution depends on the sampling procedure, and different sampling procedures lead to various distributions (Maddala 1983), only a few of which are discussed in this entry. A second approach is to estimate the expected value of e* in the sample and introduce this expected value into the model. Equation 3 now becomes Y ¼ XbX þ VbV þ BE½e jselection þ v (7) The new error term v is mean-zero in expectation but heteroscedastic, so computed standard errors require adjustment (Cameron and Trivedi 2005, p. 567; Greene 2008, p. 888). Modern software applies these corrections. Some parametric assumptions are required. Although other distributions might be used, typically analysts assume that e* and u* are distributed as bivariate normal, perhaps after transformations to increase model flexibility and perhaps after converting the s from scalars to functions of explanatory variables. Inferences are asymptotic, meaning that valid inferences require large samples. Econometricians have introduced semiparametric approaches for estimating E½e jselection (Vella 1998). These approaches are not commonly used; they do not appear in standard computing software; and (Greene 2002, pp. E23–2) for one is skeptical that semiparametric approach will reach mainstream application. This entry does not discuss semiparametric approaches. P In practice Eqs. 6 and 7 will not produce the same results. Results may be very different if the distributional assumptions are wrong. Furthermore, Eq. 6 can be adapted for models that are nonlinear in the outcome equation. This is unclear for Eq. 7 (Cameron and Trivedi 2005, p. 192). Many models are nonlinear, so Eq. 6 seems preferable, but Eq. 7 has heuristic and practical value. The form provided by Eq. 7 is especially useful for interpreting results. Let x represent a single component of X and let bx represent the corresponding parameter. If the researcher’s interest is how x changes Y in the population, then the answer is bx. But often the researcher’s interest is how Y changes with x given a selection mechanism that has behavioral interpretations. Then the answer is @Y @E½e jselection ¼ bx þ B @x @x (8) The correct interpretation depends on a wellspecific research question (Heckman and Vytlacil 2007a, b). The difficulty of applying these solutions depends on an as yet unspecified assumption about the selection process. When population data are available for estimating Eq. 4 but only selected data are available for estimating Eq. 3, the data are censored. When only sampled data are available for estimating both Eqs. 3 and 4, the data are truncated. This entry deals exclusively with censored data although similar concepts apply to truncated data. Unfortunately there is room for confusion, because the censoring problem is sometimes referenced as incidental truncation to mean that the data for estimating Eq. 3 are truncated by the process described by Eq. 2. This entry is focused on selection rules that bifurcate the population, but other selection processes occur. Especially in criminal justice applications, where justice administration acts as a sieve, selection may involve a sequence of decisions (Vella 1998, p. 153). Also in criminal justice applications, the selection rules may put individuals into ordered categories (low risk, medium risk, high risk) or into nominal P P 3432 categories. There exist suitable econometric models (Vella 1998), some of which have been programmed into conventional computing software, but discussion of alternative selection rules goes beyond the scope of this entry. Six Cases Illustrating Selection Bias Sample Selection Due to Unobserved Variables Assume that the selection equation determines which data enter into estimation of the outcome equation. Specifically, a data point is selected when S is larger than a threshold value; the threshold is 0 here. Elaborate the data generation process: S 0 implies selection into the sample used to estimate the outcome equation. S < 0 implies exclusion from the sample. From Eq. 2, sample selection occurs when S ¼ XaX þ WaW þ ZaZ þ u 0 or when WaW XaX ZaZ u When the linear combination XaX is very large in the population, any value of the linear combination WaW will likely pass the test for inclusion in the sample; when XaX is very small, only large values of WaW will likely pass the test. This induces a negative correlation between XaX and WaW in the sample. The reason is that the linear combination WbW is an element of e* in the model represented by Eq. 3. Given their common elements, WaW and WbW are likely correlated, in which case elements of X will be correlated with the error term e* in the sample. The same argument establishes that X will be correlated with Z in the sample. This does not matter, however, because Z is not part of the outcomes equation. V appears in the outcomes equation, but V does not affect e*. The entire explanation for selection arises because the unobserved W appears in both the outcome equation and the selection equation (Rosenbaum 2002). The classification of variables as X, W, V, and Z depends on the model, an observation important for model building (Pearl 2000; Gerring 2012), but those implications are not discussed here. Parametric Sample Selection Models What are the solutions? An obvious solution is to assure that X comprises variables that affect both the selection and outcome equations so there are no W variables. That may be impossible and the solution is uncertain because there is seldom reason to justify that X is inclusive. A researcher who relies on this reasoning will typically face validity challenges. Nevertheless, this assumption underlies all estimation procedures that assume selection on the observables. In contrast, Heckman’s solution assumes selection on the unobserved W. As noted, estimation requires assuming a joint distribution of e* and u*. Assuming that e* and u* are bivariate normal is problematic. Even if e and u are independent normal, bivariate normality of e* and u* depends on WaW and WbW being distributed as normal in the population. Although possible, it is a strong ^ will be inconsistent. assumption, and if wrong, b Criminologists and criminal justice researchers have used the parametric model to deal with selection bias (Bushway et al. 2007). For example, in an early application in criminal justice research, the author used Heckman’s approach to estimate how risk factors predict pretrial misconduct; the sample selection mechanism entered because the worst pretrial risks were detained pending trial so they were omitted from the sample for estimating the outcome equation. That application illustrates a point: Eq. 4 can be estimated consistently because the analyst observes release/detention decisions for every offender. Selection bias affects the estimation of Eq. 3 because the outcomes are observed for only those offenders released pending trial, but the inference is about risk in the population of offenders. The application motivates two-step estimation: Estimate the pretrial release decision first and then estimate the pretrial misconduct equation. Estimating Treatment Effects Using Observational Data In the second case, the selection equation determines who enters treatment. An explanation requires modest changes to Eq. 1 through Eq. 4. Let T is a dummy variable that denotes treatment when T ¼ 1 and no treatment when T ¼ 0 Parametric Sample Selection Models d a vector of parameters (the treatment effect), which is the objective of estimation Then S 0 implies selection into treatment (T ¼ 1). S < 0 implies no treatment (T ¼ 0). Treatment potentially changes all the parameters in Eq. 1, so rewrite Eq. 1 as Y ¼ Xb0X þ Wb0W þ Vb0V þ e if treated Y ¼ XbX þ WbW þ VbV þ e otherwise Equivalently the DGP can be rewritten as a single equation with interactions Y ¼XbX þ WbW þ VbV þ ½XdX þ WdW þ VdV T þ e The model becomes Y ¼XbX þ VbV þ ½XdX þ VdV T þ ½WbW þ WTdW þ e ¼ XbX þ VbV þ ½XdX þ VdV T þ e Where e ¼ WbW þ WTdW þ e Often selection into treatment depends on whether the person being treated his or her agent perceives treatment to be beneficial. This theory motivates specification of the selection equation. It is common to assume that the d are zero except for a constant—that is, XdX + VdV ¼ d and WTdW ¼ 0. This assumption has negative consequences if wrong. Nevertheless, for simplicity, treat d as a scalar. T is not orthogonal to e**. The reasoning is the same as before. T is partly determined by W; also, e** is correlated with W. Hence, T is correlated with e**. An analyst could not estimate d consistently in a regression that fails to account for selection. Simple solutions follow when selection on observables holds (Imbens and Wooldridge 2009). Otherwise, estimation rests on strong parametric assumption about the joint distribution for e** and u**. As a practical matter, parameter identification requires that Z be observed and included in the model. Identification is discussed later. For example, in the 3433 P criminal justice literature, the author and his or her colleagues (Rhodes et al. 2001) used the parametric approach to evaluate within prison substance abuse treatment. Breakdowns in Randomized Controlled Trials RCT imposes selection by design. Unless the design is perverse, random assignment typically solves the selection bias problem. There are three situations. First, selection is purely random: The selection mechanism contains no variables in common with the outcome equation. Estimation is straightforward: the mean difference between the treated and control group is an unbiased estimate of the average treatment effect; a regression might be used to increase efficiency or to learn about heterogeneous treatment effects. Second, selection is random conditional on X (exogenous sampling). Stratified sampling obviously qualifies, as do most complex survey designs. There is no sampling bias provided the evaluator uses an estimator that accounts for X. This might be done with weighting, but that topic goes beyond the scope of this entry. Third, selection is random conditional on W. This perverse case happens. Consider a multisite study where the researcher samples randomly from within a site but does not select randomly across sites – perhaps because many sites decline to participate in the study. Or, consider the problem where some subjects assigned to treatment refuse the treatment or some subjects assigned to the control condition cross over to the treatment condition, or both. Random assignment involves selection bias in these common cases. Evaluators sometimes use the terms internal and external validity to describe this perverse case. Thus, well-crafted and implemented RCTs are free of selection bias. However, true RCTs are difficult to design and implement, and selection bias occurs when design/implementation is faulty. Selection may be present in RCT (Berk 2005; Sampson 2010), and furthermore, the RCT may be unable to answer important policy questions about the distribution of treatment effects (Heckman and Vytlacil 2007a; Heckman et al. 1997). Meta-analysis (Borenstein et al. 2009) P P 3434 often integrates experimental and quasiexperimental studies to understand selection bias and better estimate treatment effects. Survival Models with Censoring and Competing Events Survival analysis has a long history in the study of criminal recidivism. Advances have incorporated competing events into the study of criminal recidivism. Selection bias can occur when estimating survival models for the reasons discussed in 2.2 through 2.4, but survival models sometimes raise special selection problems. Equations 1 and 2 will again be useful but now recast those equations by assuming there are two events, A and B. Event A might represent the occurrence of criminal recidivism, defined as an arrest for a new crime while under community supervision. Event B might represent the occurrence of a revocation for a technical violation of the conditions of supervision, treated here as a competing event. Y and S represent the logarithm of the time until events A and B, respectively. The error term e is the distribution of log-time until an arrest conditional on X, W, and V; the error term u is the distribution of log-time until a revocation conditional on X, W, and Z. The analyst can observe the timing for whichever event occurs first: A or B. Consequently, one can treat B as “selecting” what is observable about A. Almost always, analysts assume that the timing of event A (the outcome of interest) is conditionally independent of the timing of event B (competing events). This is equivalent to assuming selection on observables. If selection on observables is wrong, traditional survival analysis will result in biased parameter estimates. Given censoring because of unobservables, the solution is also familiar. The analyst needs to model the joint distribution of e* and u*, but accounting for the error structure is complicated (van den Berg 2008). Moreover, commonly available software lacks estimation routines. Nevertheless, the maximum likelihood approach introduced earlier provides a solution requiring parametric assumptions; the author used this approach to study criminal recidivism under community supervision. Parametric Sample Selection Models To extend this observation, the reader might note that survival models are simply censored regressions. Therefore, the same selection problems that affect survival models also affect Tobit models, which are frequently used in criminal justice research. Endogenous Stratification/Choice-Based Sampling Many samples depend on the occurrence of some event. For example, data from the Arrestee Drug Abuse Monitoring (ADAM) survey requires a subject to be arrested and booked. Samples used in the criminal careers literature require a subject to acquire a criminal history. Such samples involve endogenous stratification or choicebased sampling. To illustrate the problem, return to Eq. 1 and think of Y as a count variable – zero arrests, one arrest, two arrests, and so on occurring from a Poisson process. The research question is to estimate the arrest rate during a period of interest. Return to Eq. 2 and think of S as being the event: arrested and booked on the day that ADAM arrestees were sampled. Selection bias occurs because offenders with high crime commission rates have relatively high sampling probabilities. The sample will not represent the general population of offenders. Notice a subtle difference between endogenous stratification and the other selection problems: Selection into the sample depends on the process determining the outcome. To illustrate, assume a subject is sampled into the study depending on the outcome, so: Y > 0 implies selection into the sample Y 0 implies no selection into the sample The outcome equation is written as Y ¼ XbX þ VbV þ e The expected value for e*** in the sample is E½e ¼ E½eje > XbX WbW VbV The error term e*** will be correlated with X and V in the sample. Endogenous stratification raises complex estimation issues (Cameron and Trivedi 2005, pp. 822–829). Solutions may be best developed for Poisson and negative binomial models (Cameron and Trivedi 1998), which is fortunate Parametric Sample Selection Models 3435 given the ubiquitous role of Poisson models in criminal justice modeling. The criminal careers literature has sometimes dealt with the issue; early illustrations come from the Rand Corporation and others. The author has used a negative binomial model with endogenous stratification to estimate the arrest rate for drug-involved offenders in the community based on a sample of arrestees (Rhodes et al. 2007). Missing Data Analysts often deal with missing data (Schaefer 1997; Little and Rubin 2002). For example, within a data set, sex may be missing for some subjects, age may be missing for others, and both age and sex may be missing for still others. The variable is observed (it is an X variable), but its value is missing for some observations. One way to deal with missing data is to exclude cases where any data are missing. This is called list-wise or case-wise deletion. This depletes the sample and thereby reduces power; it can bias parameter estimation. An alternative approach is to impute values for the missing data, and imputation software is available for common problems. Imputation and estimation with imputed data is complicated. Consider a simple problem: A single variable x from the vector X has missing values. Assume that x is the Kth element of X and that the other K-1 elements are never missing. To focus attention on x, rewrite Eq. 1 equivalently as Y ¼ X1:K1 bX1:K1 þ xbXK þ WbW þ VbV þ e (9) Interpret the selection equation as determining when x is observed (S > 0) and missing (S < 0). To emphasize the role of x, rescale so the aK ¼ 1 and rewrite Eq. 2 as S ¼ X1:K1 aX1:K1 þ x þ WaW þ ZaW þ u (10) This implies that x is observed when x X1:K1 a1:K1 ZaZ WaW u (11) P As before, the motivation is to estimate the parameters in the model: Y ¼ X1:K1 bX1:K1 þ xK aK þ VbV þ e (12) Consider three cases. The first is when elements of a in Eq. 11 are 0 except perhaps for the constant. Selection, which depends only on u, is called missing completely at random. Missing data will not bias the parameter estimates for Eq. 12 because the error term e* will not be correlated with X, x, or V. The second situation is when aW is zero but other a parameters are not zero. Selection, which now depends on one or more of the observed variables, is called missing at random. Missing data will not bias parameter estimates because the error term e* will be uncorrelated with X, x, and V. The third situation is where aW 6¼ 0. Selection, which now depends on unobservable variables, is called missing not completely at random. This leads to biased parameter estimates because the missing data will be correlated with the error term e*. There are parametric solutions to the first two cases and approximate solutions to the third case. The solution requires specifying x as a function of observables. A specification might be x ¼ YBY þ X1:K1 BX1:K1 þ VBV þ ZBZ þ RBR þ v (13) There are some surprises in Eq. 13. One is that the outcome variable Y appears in the specification. The intuition is that x predicts Y, so Y predicts x, and predicting x is the purpose of Eq. 13. A second surprise is inclusion of a vector of variables R that did not appear elsewhere in the DGP. Again, the instrumental objective is to predict x, and it seems plausible that some set of variables R might predict x yet not explain Y. Finally, v is an error term whose distribution is known except for some unspecified parameters. The solution is parametric because of the linear specification and the assumed distribution for v. Estimation of Eq. 13, including the parameters of the distribution of v, leads to a predicted (posterior) distribution for missing values for x. P P 3436 Estimation of Eq. 9 proceeds by sampling values of x from this posterior distribution and using those sampled values to estimate the parameter appearing in Eq. 9. The approach is conceptually simple but estimation rests on the specified distributional assumptions, is computer intensive, and requires specialized software. In the first two cases—missing completely at random and missing at random—Bayesian logic leads to consistent estimates for the parameters in Eq. 9. This is not true in the third case. There the analyst has two choices. The first is to construct an imputation model that is explicit about the selection mechanism; this is not frequently done. The second is to use imputations from Eq. 13 with an expectation that these will reduce mean-squared errors in the b. This is plausible because the imputations are based on additional information that would otherwise be ignored by case-wise deletion. The single imputation problem is simple compared with a multiple imputation problem where all of the X and V variables may have missing values. In that case, the starting assumption is that X and V are distributed as multivariate normal perhaps after transformations and after conditioning on other variables such as Y and R. This solution is highly parametric and probably unrealistic. Nevertheless, experience shows that estimation is insensitive to distributional assumptions although one would be dubious of applying this approach to data that have a high proportion of missing to known values. As an illustration, the ADAM survey randomly samples arrestees, questions them about drug use, and requests a urine specimen to test for recent drug use. Not all arrestees are able or willing to comply with the request, leading to missing results for urine tests. ADAM analysts have developed procedures used to impute urine test results conditional on self-reports about recent drug use. Identification The first five cases share a common problem: The arguments assume that W is orthogonal to X and V. This assumption was convenient because it meant that in the absence of any Parametric Sample Selection Models selection bias, an analyst could consistently estimate the b parameters. What if the distribution of W is not orthogonal to X and V? Then when W is omitted from the outcome equation, the b parameters would not be identified even absent selection bias. The problem is omitted variable bias, which is discussed in introductory textbooks and is widely appreciated by researchers. One can nevertheless think of Eq. 3 as estimating a conditional mean for the population (Angrist and Pischke 2009). Provided the analyst considers his or her estimates to pertain to a conditional mean function, the argument regarding selection bias does not require any assumptions about independence between W and either X or V, so one can focus on selection bias as the problem. Putting this discussion about orthogonality aside, the parametric solution to selection bias requires an assumption about the joint distribution between e* and u*. Suppose the assumption is correct. Is this sufficient to identify the b? The answer is a qualified yes, but asymptotic justification for the parameter estimates and their sampling distributions may require very large samples. Equation 7 provides some intuition. Absent Z, E[e*|sample] will be nearly collinear with X. The relationship will not be perfectly collinear because the nature of the joint distribution fb will induce nonlinearities, but the departure from collinearity will be slight in most real-world applications. Consequently, the standard errors for bX would be large and inference tenuous. Few analysts would feel comfortable relying on identification resting on nonlinearities induced by correct specification of the joint distribution of e* and u*. A more compelling case for identification requires the presence of Z. Intuition is again useful. The larger is the explanatory power of Z in Eq. 4, the smaller is the correlation between X and E[e*|sample]. The availability of Z mitigates the collinearity problem. There is an extensive literature on instrumental variables (Hahn and Hausman 2003; Stock et al. 2002). This entry is not the place to summarize that literature except to review some properties of a good instrument. Parametric Sample Selection Models First, to be an instrument, Z must appear in the selection equation but not in the outcome equation. Second, to be a useful instrument, Z must account for a good deal of the variance in S. A weak instrument (e.g., one that accounts for a negligible amount of the variance in S conditional on X) can provide an estimate with worse mean-squared error properties than estimates from models that ignore selection bias. Unfortunately, good instruments are difficult to find and to justify, a fact that greatly limits the appeal of the Heckman estimation procedures. This is a good point to pose the question: If correcting for selection bias can worsen estimates, can an analyst tell if correcting for selection bias is necessary? The answer is a tentative yes: The test is equivalent to testing whether se*u* ¼ 0. The practical problem is that without a strong instrument, this test will lack power. An analyst would frequently fail to reject the null hypothesis of no selection bias when, in fact, selection bias is serious. There are tests of whether the parameters are identified by nonlinearities or identification restrictions, but these tests require correct parametric assumptions and, anyway, do not answer the question of whether selection bias exists. A final point closes this section: Much of the argument regarding instrumental variables pertains to linear regression models and does not translate readily into the nonlinear models often used in criminology/criminal justice research. For useful discussions, see Davidson and MacKinnon (1993), pp. 224–226 and Cameron and Trivedi (2005), pp. 192–199. This is a difficult problem. Angrist and Pischke (2009) advise researchers to assess if the research question is answerable without actually estimating the b. The author (Rhodes 2010) adopted that recommendation in a justice context. Monte Carlo Illustrations A Monte Carlo experiment illustrates points based on the first case (section “Sample Selection Due to Unobserved Variables”). There are single X, W, V, and Z variables. X, V, and Z are 3437 P distributed as independent normal with mean of zero and standard deviation of 1; W has different distributions across the experiments. The a and b parameters all equal 1. The error terms e and u are distributed as normal with mean of zero and standard deviation of 2. The simulation generates 1,000 observations before selection (about 500 after selection), and the experiment is replicated 5,000 times. In the first experiment (see Table 1), W is distributed as normal with mean of 0 and standard deviation of 2. This is ideal for the Heckman estimator because e* and u* are distributed as joint normal. The table shows parameter estimates using an OLS regression, Heckman’s maximum likelihood, and Heckman’s two-step procedure. The table reports the average of the three b parameters across 5,000 replications (bC is the constant), the “true” standard error across those 5,000 replications (based on the 5,000 replications) and the average of the estimated standard errors across those 5,000 replications. OLS with a robust covariance estimator yields biased and inconsistent parameter estimates for bX and bC. The estimate for bV is not biased. The maximum likelihood Heckman procedure yields consistent parameter estimates at the expense of inflating standard errors. The two-step procedure yields consistent parameter estimates although the standard errors are even larger. The Heckman estimators perform well in this ideal case. The second exercise changes the distribution for the instrument Z. Although still normally distributed with mean of zero, it now has a standard deviation of 0.01. This simulates a weak instrument. Everything else in the simulations remains the same. Results are reported as exercise 2 in Table 1. The table shows no results for the maximum likelihood procedure, which often fails to converge on a solution. The two-step estimator is less demanding and makes the intended points. First, the two-step estimator yields seriously biased parameter estimates, which should give pause to those who seek to rely upon nonlinearity to identify parameters. Second, the mean-squared error properties of the two-step estimator are worse P P 3438 Parametric Sample Selection Models Parametric Sample Selection Models, Table 1 A Monte Carlo demonstration of selection bias Experiment 1 bX bV bC Experiment 2 bX bV bC Experiment 3 bX bV bC Experiment 4 bX bV bC Experiment 5 bX bV bC Exercises: Least squares True standard Estimate error 0.728 0.123 0.999 0.118 2.077 0.121 0.694 0.122 1.001 0.118 2.145 0.120 0.872 0.112 1.000 0.107 1.306 0.110 0.034 0.397 1.002 0.375 3.432 0.416 0.973 0.090 0.999 0.086 1.576 0.088 Estimated standard error 0.122 0.118 0.121 0.121 0.117 0.120 0.112 0.106 0.113 0.373 0.351 0.403 0.090 0.086 0.089 Maximum likelihood Two-step True Estimated True standard standard standard Estimate error error Estimate error 0.993 0.163 0.160 1.002 0.176 0.999 0.117 0.117 0.999 0.117 1.024 0.416 0.407 0.990 0.487 0.859 1.023 1.001 0.118 1.522 3.925 1.025 0.175 0.153 1.006 0.151 1.000 0.106 0.105 1.000 0.107 0.806 0.436 0.353 0.867 0.351 1.638 3.941 1.006 0.374 3.744 17.346 0.999 0.121 0.119 0.999 0.121 0.999 0.086 0.086 0.999 0.086 1.499 0.244 0.240 1.498 0.242 Estimated standard error 0.174 0.117 0.485 1.406 0.146 5.365 0.150 0.105 0.343 5.708 0.499 24.586 0.120 0.086 0.241 1. W has a normal distribution and the instrument is strong 2. W has a normal distribution and the instrument is weak 3. W has a lognormal distribution with variance of 1.02 and the instrument is strong 4. W has a lognormal distribution with variance of 1.02 and the instrument is weak 5. W has a binomial distribution with probability equal to 0.5 than those of the OLS estimator: 0.329 for OLS and 1.033 for Heckman. The third exercise is the same as the first but changes the distribution for W. Previously distributed as normal, it is now distributed as lognormal. This is easily accomplished by taking the exponential of the original W multiplied by 0.7. The distribution of W now has a mean of 1.278 and a standard deviation of 1.02. The exercise subtracts 1.278 from the simulated values of W to center the new distribution of W on zero. The assumption of a lognormal distribution for W violates the assumptions that e* and u* are distributed as bivariate normal. Nevertheless, the maximum likelihood and two-step procedures perform tolerably given a strong instrument. The fourth exercise is the same as the third but weakens the instrument by changing Z to have a normal distribution with standard deviation of 0.01. As before, convergence is a problem for the maximum likelihood solution, but the two-step approach provides a solution. Estimates are biased with large sampling variances. The fifth and final exercise uses the original W but now changes it to a dummy variable coded 1 if W exceeds 0 and coded 0 otherwise. The instrument is strong. As before, the Heckman procedure provides tolerable solutions especially for the slope coefficient despite the faulty distributional assumptions. Simulations cannot cover all situations, but generalizing based on the above leads to two conclusions: First, the Heckman procedure is fairly robust to departures from bivariate normality provided the instrument is strong. Second, the Heckman procedure provides poor estimates when instruments are weak regardless of whether distributional assumptions are correct. Conclusions Application of the parametric approach is demanding, but this is equally true of partially parametric approaches. An applied researcher should provide a sober, informed consideration Parametric Sample Selection Models of whether his or her data can answer the research question. The following observations might inform that consideration. First, when the researcher has access to a rich set of data, which includes all variables relevant to the outcome equation according to substantive theory, the researcher might assume selection on the observables. In general, assuming selection on the observables is difficult to justify, but justification is advanced when the setting allows repeated observations (difference-in-differences) and exogenous interruptions (regression discontinuity) provided the researcher is content with estimating a subset of the b identified by these designs. Second, when selection on the observables is untenable, the researcher needs strong instruments to impose identifying restrictions. Good instruments are difficult to find and justify, but examples exist in criminal justice research. Although nonlinearities can provide identifying restrictions, these are not reliable. Weak instruments are a problem. All the estimators discussed in this entry provide estimates of b that are biased but consistent provided distributional assumptions hold. The weaker the instrument, the larger the sample required to reduce the bias to an acceptable level. Asymptotic justification can require samples in the tens of thousands when instruments are weak. Third, it is common for a researcher to estimate two competing models that (1) do not adjust for selection bias and (2) adjust for selection bias using parametric assumption. If the two approaches provide different results, the researcher might conclude that the second model is preferred and even necessary. Exercise 2 demonstrated that this is a poor test that provides no basis for concluding that the Heckman model is an improvement. Along this line, this entry does not cover an important body of work that uses RCT to estimate a treatment effect (case 2 from above) and then applies the Heckman estimator to observational data to estimate ostensibly the same treatment effect. Researchers interpret the difference between the two estimates as demonstrating failure of the Heckman approach, but this 3439 P comparison does not accurately quantify the bias. Rather, observational data have different coverage and consequently provide estimates for a different population (Heckman et al. 1998). Thus, the comparison does not demonstrate failure of the parametric approach to produce useful estimates of treatment effectiveness. One final point ends this entry: This entry has treated estimation of the outcome equation as providing the estimates of scientific interest. This is not always the case. Especially when making policy recommendations, the researcher may be interested in estimation and interpretation of the selection equation, or the researcher might be interested in the distribution of treatment effects across the population, or both (Heckman and Vytlacil 2007a, b). Even when the selection equation has little scientific interest, careful thought about the selection equation is essential for applying the parametric approach. This thought exercise is a design consideration driven by substantive theory. Statistical theory alone cannot provide a magic solution. Related Entries ▶ Causes ▶ Econometrics of Crime ▶ Interrupted Time Series Models ▶ Longitudinal Studies in Criminology ▶ Propensity Score Matching ▶ Randomized Experiments in Criminology and Criminal Justice ▶ Recent Perspectives on the Regression Discontinuity Design ▶ Sample Selection Models ▶ Sample Selection Problems Recommended Reading and References Angrist J, Pischke J (2009) Mostly harmless econometrics: an empiricist’s companion. Princeton University Press, Princeton Berk R (2005) Randomized experiments as the bronze standard. J Exp Criminol 1:417–433 Borenstein M, Hedges L, Higgins J, Rothstein H (2009) Introduction to meta-analysis. Wiley, West Sussex P P 3440 Bushway S, Johnson B, Slocum L (2007) Is the magic still there? The use of the Heckman two-step correction for selection bias in criminology. J Quant Criminol 23:151–178 Cameron A, Trivedi P (1998) Regression analysis for count data. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Cameron A, Trivedi P (2005) Microeconometrics: methods and applications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Davidson R, MacKinnon JG (1993) Estimation and inference in econometrics. Oxford University Press, New York Gerring J (2012) Social science methodology: a unified framework, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Greene W (2002) LIMDEP version 8.0: econometric modeling guide, volume 2. Econometric Software, Plainview Greene W (2008) Econometric analysis, 6th edn. Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River Hahn J, Hausman J (2003) Weak instruments: diagnostics and cures in empirical econometrics. Am Econ Rev 93:118–125 Heckman J (1976) The common structure of statistical models of truncation, sample selection and limited dependent variables and a simple estimator for such models. Ann Econ Soc Meas 5:475–492 Heckman J (1979) Sample selection bias as a specification error. Econometrica 47:153–161 Heckman J, Vytlacil E (2007a) Econometric evaluation of social programs, part I: causal models, structural models and econometric policy evaluations. In: Heckman J, Leamer E (eds) Handbook of econometrics volume 6B. North Holland Press, Amsterdam Heckman J, Vytlacil E (2007b) Econometric evaluations of social programs, part II: using the marginal treatment effect to evaluate social programs, and to forecast their effects in new environments. In: Heckman J, Leamer E, Leamer E (eds) Handbook of econometrics volume 6B. North-Holland Press, Amsterdam Heckman J, Smith J, Clements N (1997) Making the most out of programme evaluations and social experiments: accounting for heterogeneity in programme impacts. Rev Econ Stud 64:487–535 Heckman J, Ichimura H, Smith J, Todd P (1998) Characterizing selection bias using experimental data. Econometrica 66(5):1017–1098 Imbens G, Wooldridge J (2009) Recent developments in the econometrics of program evaluation. J Econ Lit 47(1):5–86 Little R, Rubin D (2002) Statistical analysis with missing data, 2nd edn. Wiley, Hobokan Maddala G (1983) Limited-dependent and qualitative variables in econometrics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Pearl J (2000) Causality: models, reasoning and inferences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Rhodes W (2010) Estimating treatment effects and predicting recidivism for community supervision Parole using survival analysis with instrumental variables. J Quant Criminol 26:391–413 Rhodes W, Pelissier B, Gaes G, Saylor B, Camp S, Wallace S (2001) Alternative solutions to the problem of selection bias in an analysis of federal residential drug treatment programs. Eval Rev 25:331–369 Rhodes W, Kling R, Johnson P (2007) Using booking data to model drug use arrest rates: a preliminary to estimating the prevalence of chronic drug users. J Quant Criminol 23(1):1–22 Rosenbaum P (2002) Observational studies, 2nd edn. Springer, New York Sampson R (2010) Gold standard myths: observations on the experimental turn in quantitative criminology. J Quant Criminol 26:489–500 Schaefer J (1997) Analysis of incomplete missing data. Chapman & HALL/CRC, Boca Raton Stock J, Wright J, Yogo M (2002) A survey of weak instruments and weak identification in generalized methods of moments. J Bus Econ Stud 20:518–529 van den Berg G (2008) Competing risks models. In: Durlauf S, Blume L (eds) The new palgrave dictionary of economics, 2nd edn. Palgrave, MacMillan Vella F (1998) Estimating models with sample selection bias: a survey. J Hum Resour 33(1):127–169 Parole ▶ Desistance and Supervision ▶ Early Release from Prison ▶ Front Door and Backdoor Sentencing ▶ Mentally Disordered Offenders Community Supervision ▶ Probation and Community Sanctions Under Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States Joan Petersilia Stanford Law School, Stanford University, Stanford, CA, USA Overview The US prison and parole population declined in 2009 for the first time in 30 years, perhaps indicating the beginning of the end of America’s Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States long commitment to mass incarceration. But current prison population declines may well be reversed if we do not do a better job of planning for the reentry of prisoners who have finished their sentences. At release, many prisoners are unable to find jobs and suitable housing. Some will be legally barred from voting, receiving public assistance, obtaining a driver’s license, or retaining custody of their children. If the past is any lesson, many (upward of two-thirds) eventually return to crime and prison, where the cycle begins again. Faced with these realities, what can we do? Fortunately, there is much that can be done. We must focus attention on parole policies and practices. Parole – which refers to both a release mechanism and a method of community supervision – is central to crime control and prisoner reintegration. If parole is effective, dangerous offenders remain in prison, and those who are released are better prepared for reentry. If parole resources are misdirected, community safety is threatened as prisoners return home with few resources and little surveillance. Which scenario proves true will depend on realistic expectations and an understanding of parole’s history, current operations, needs of the parole population, and “what works” in reentry programming. Fundamentals of Parole and Reentry Definition and Functions of Parole People often confuse probation and parole. Probation is a judge’s sentence that allows a convicted offender to continue to live in the community after criminal conviction, with restrictions on activities and with supervision for the duration of the sentence. Parole refers to offenders who have spent time in prison and are released to complete the remainder of their sentence under community supervision. Parole is usually granted from authorities in the correctional system (i.e., a parole board), since responsibility for offenders passes from the judicial system to the correctional system upon imprisonment. Parolees are technically still in state custody; they have merely been granted the privilege of living in the community instead of prison. 3441 P If parolees or probationers violate the rules of their release, they can be returned to incarceration. Inmates are released from prison mandatorily or discretionarily. Mandatory release is release after a specified period of time, as required by law, and occurs in jurisdictions using determinate sentencing. In determinate sentencing, the offender is given a set amount of time to serve by the court, although these sentencing structures may still incorporate a degree of discretion. Determinate sentencing eliminates parole boards, although the exact requirements vary by state. Discretionary release is at the paroling authority’s discretion, within boundaries established by the sentence and by law. In those states that permit discretionary release, state laws give parole boards the authority to change, within certain limits, the length of a sentence that is actually served. Parole officials may also change the conditions under which convicted offenders are supervised and may release offenders from prison to supervision in the community or to an outside facility. Parole authorities can also issue warrants revoking parole and reincarcerating offenders who violate parole conditions. For jurisdictions with determinate sentencing and no discretion for the timing of release, the paroling authority may still determine conditions of release. They thus can have a direct effect on prison management. For example, they can increase the number of prisoners required to be on post-prison supervision, or they can decrease, by policy, the number of parole revocations returned to prison. It is this gatekeeper role that makes paroling authorities so central to current debates about prisoner reentry and prison crowding. With parole, like probation, information about an offender is gathered and presented to a decision-making authority, and that authority has the power to release the offender under specific conditions, which are articulated in a contract signed by the offender. Contractual conditions may be standard (applicable to all parolees) or tailored to particular offenders. Standard parole conditions are similar throughout most jurisdictions and include payment of P P 3442 supervision fees, finding employment, not carrying weapons, reporting changes of address and employment, not committing crimes, and submitting to search by the police and parole officers. Examples of special conditions include periodic drug testing for substance abusers and registration for sex offenders and arsonists. The principal responsibility of the parole officer is to monitor this court-imposed contract and conditions. If offenders fail to live up to their conditions, they can be revoked and returned to jail or prison to serve out the remainder of the original sentence or to serve a new sentence. Parole can be revoked for two reasons: (1) the commission of a new crime or (2) the violation of the conditions of parole (a technical violation). Technical violations pertain to behavior that is not criminal, such as the failure to refrain from alcohol use or remain employed. In either event, the violation process is rather straightforward. Given that parolees are technically still in the legal custody of the court or prison authorities, their constitutional rights are severely limited. When parole officers become aware of violations of the parole contract, they notify their supervisors, who make a recommendation to the parole authorities and can easily return a parolee to prison. Two US Supreme Court cases, Morrissey v. Brewer, 408 U.S. 471 (1972) and Gagnon v. Scarpelli, 411 U.S. 778 (1973), established minimum requirements for the revocation of parole, giving parolees some rights (such as written notice of the violation and the opportunity to confront the accuser) in revocation proceedings. The goals of probation and parole supervision are identical: to protect the community and help rehabilitate offenders. These dual functions are referred to as the law enforcement function, which emphasizes surveillance of the offender and close control of behavior, and the social work function, which attempts to provide supportive services to meet offenders’ needs. Both have always been a part of community corrections, and debating which should be of higher priority has always caused strain. Currently, the social work function has given way to the law enforcement function, and probation and parole officers are often less interested today in treating Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States clients than in controlling their behavior. Higher risk clients, combined with shrinking resources, has caused many agents to prioritize offender monitoring. Parole agents are equipped with legal authority to carry and use firearms; to search places, persons, and property without the requirements imposed by the Fourth Amendment (i.e., the right to privacy); to order arrests without probable cause; and to confine without bail. Monitoring parolee behavior and delivering services is managed through caseloads (the number of parolees assigned to a single parole agent). Higher-risk parolees are placed on smaller caseloads, which facilitate more intensive services and surveillance. Caseload assignment is usually based on a structured assessment of parolee risk and an assessment of the needs or problem areas that have contributed to the parolee’s criminality. By scoring personal information relative to the risk of recidivism and the particular needs of the offender (i.e., a risk/need instrument), a total score is derived, which determines the particular level of parole supervision (e.g., intensive, medium, regular, administrative). Each jurisdiction has established policies that dictate the contact levels (times the officer will meet with the parolee). Officers may also contact family members or employers to inquire about the parolee’s progress. The purpose of the contacts is to make sure that parolees are complying with parole conditions. Parole and Reentry The term prisoner reentry began affecting community corrections in early 2000. Unlike probation and parole, prisoner reentry is not a legal status or program, but a new conceptual framework for thinking about the processing of criminal offenders, from sentencing to parole discharge. Prisoner reentry is defined as the process of leaving incarceration and returning to society and includes all activities and programming conducted to prepare ex-convicts to return safely to the community and to live as law-abiding citizens (Petersilia 2003). Reentry is an inevitable consequence of incarceration. As Jeremy Travis (Travis 2005, p. xxi) reminds us, “reentry is not a form of supervision, like Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States parole. Reentry is not a goal, like rehabilitation or reintegration. Reentry is not an option. Reentry reflects the iron law of imprisonment: they all come back.” Refocusing the justice system around a reentry perspective represents a fundamental paradigm shift that impacts decisions about the timing of release, the procedures for making the release decision, the preparation of the prisoner for release, supervision after release, and the linkages between in-prison and post-release activities. Except for those who die naturally or are executed in prison, 95 % of all state prisoners will eventually leave prison (Petersilia 2003). Estimates from the Department of Justice show that nearly one-half of all state inmates will be released within 1 year and three-quarters will be released within 5 years (U.S. Government Accountability Office 2001). Parolees represent 11 % of the 7.2 million people “under correctional control” (incarcerated or on community supervision) (Glaze and Bonczar 2010). Regardless of whether ex-prisoners are on formal parole supervision, they all return home forever changed, often facing isolation, stigma, and a narrowed array of life chances. Today’s parole population is mostly male (88 %), although the number of females has risen steadily over the past decade. The average parolee is in his or her mid-thirties, with a median age of 34. For both males and females, most parolees are members of racial or ethnic minorities (37 % are black and 19 % are Hispanic or Latino) (Glaze and Bonczar 2008). The Bureau of Justice Statistics reported that 37 % of all adults on parole in 2007 were convicted of drug crimes (Glaze and Bonczar 2008). Many states are reconsidering the harsh drug laws passed in the 1980s and 1990s, rolling back mandatory sentences and accelerating releases for some drug offenders. The anticipated accelerated pace of drug-involved prison releases will strain parole and community resources even further. Most of those released from prison today have serious social and medical problems. More than three-fourths of all prisoners have a history of substance abuse (one-fourth have histories of 3443 P injection drug use), and one in six suffers from mental illness (Ditton 1999). Yet less than a third of exiting prisoners have received substance abuse or mental health treatment while in prison. And while some states have recently provided more funding for prison drug treatment, the dramatic increase in the prison population has resulted in a decline in the percentage of state prisoners participating in such programs that have been declining, from 25 % in the 1990s to about 10 % in 2001 (Lynch and Sabol 2001). A significant share of the prison population also lives with an infectious disease. Two to three percent of state prisoners are HIV positive or have AIDS, a rate five times higher than that of the US population (Hammett et al. 2002). According to the Centers for Disease Control, about 25 % of all individuals living with HIV or AIDS in the United States had been released from a prison or jail that year (National Commission on Correctional Health Care 2002). This proportion may continue to increase as more drug offenders, many of whom engage in intravenous drug use, share needles, or trade sex for drugs, are released from incarceration. Prisoners with health problems may have a more difficult reentry process than others, as they are additionally confronted with the tasks of managing their health problems, obtaining health care, and keeping up with medications or appointments. Few inmates have marketable skills or sufficient literacy to become gainfully employed at release. A third of all US prisoners were unemployed at their most recent arrest, and just 60 % of inmates have a GED or high school diploma (compared to 85 % of the US adult population). The National Adult Literacy Survey established that 11 % of inmates, compared with 3 % of the general population, have a learning disability and 3 % are mentally retarded (National Center for Education Statistics 1994). Again, despite evidence that inmates’ literacy and job readiness has declined, fewer inmates are participating in prison education or vocational programs. Just over 25 % of all those released from prison in 2001 had participated in vocational training programs, and about a third of exiting prisoners will have participated in P P 3444 education programs – both figures down from the previous decade (Lynch and Sabol 2001). In 2007, the nation spent about $47 billion in state general funds on corrections (which was 7 % of all state general fund spending), yet spending on treatment equaled just 6 % of the annual cost of housing a prisoner (Pew Center on the States 2009). The need for services for substance-abuse treatment and educational programming in prison has never been greater, but the percentage of prisoners receiving these services has declined. More punitive attitudes, combined with diminishing rehabilitation programs, mean that more inmates spend their prison time “idle.” Ironically, as inmate needs have increased and inprison programs decreased, parole supervision and community services have also decreased for most returning prisoners. Current Issues and Controversies The Decline of Rehabilitation and Discretionary Parole Release The pillars of the American corrections systems – indeterminate sentencing coupled with parole release, for the purposes of offender rehabilitation – collapsed during the late 1970s and early 1980s. Attacks on indeterminate sentencing and parole release centered on three major criticisms. First, there was little scientific evidence that parole release and supervision reduced subsequent recidivism. Robert Martinson and his colleagues published the now-famous review of the effectiveness of correctional treatment and concluded, “With few and isolated exceptions, the rehabilitative efforts that have been reported so far have had no appreciable effect on recidivism” (1974, p. 25). Of the 289 studies they reviewed, just 25 (9 %) pertained to parole, and yet Martinson’s summary was interpreted to mean that parole supervision (and all rehabilitation programs) did not work. Once rehabilitation could not be legitimated by science, there was nothing to support the “readiness for release” idea and, therefore, no role for parole boards or indeterminate sentencing. Second, parole and indeterminate sentencing were challenged on moral grounds as unjust and inhumane, especially when imposed on unwilling Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States participants. Research at the time showed there was little relationship between in-prison behaviors, participation in rehabilitation programs, and post-release recidivism. If that were true, then why base release dates on in-prison performance? Prisoners too argued that not knowing their release dates held them in “suspended animation” and contributed one more pain of imprisonment. Third, indeterminate sentencing permitted parole authorities to use a great deal of uncontrolled discretion in release decisions, and these decisions often were inconsistent and discriminatory. Since parole boards had a great deal of autonomy and their decisions were not subject to outside scrutiny, critics argued that it was a hidden system of discretionary decision making that led to race and class bias in release decisions. It seemed as if no one liked indeterminate sentencing and parole in the early 1980s, and the time was ripe for change. Crime control advocates denounced parole supervision as being largely nominal and ineffective; social welfare advocates decried the lack of meaningful and useful rehabilitation programs. A political coalition resulted, and soon incapacitation and “just deserts” replaced rehabilitation as the primary goal of American prisons. With that changed focus, indeterminate sentencing and parole release came under serious attack, and calls for “abolishing parole” were heard in state after state. In 1975, Maine became the first state to eliminate parole. The following year, California and Indiana established determinate sentencing and abolished discretionary parole release. By 2002, 16 states had abolished discretionary parole release for nearly all offenders. In 19 other states, parole authorities had discretion over a small and decreasing number of parole-eligible inmates. Likewise, at the federal level, the Comprehensive Crime Control Act of 1984 created the US Sentencing Commission and phased out discretionary parole for most federal prisoners in 1997 (Petersilia 2003). Proponents hoped that determinate sentencing with mandatory parole would make sentencing more consistent across offenders and offenses – and it has (Marvell and Moody 1996). It was also thought that abolishing parole would lengthen the Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States time inmates spent behind bars. After all, parole release was widely regarded as letting them out early. Solomon et al. (2005) did find that prisoners released to post-prison supervision served nearly a year less than those released without supervision (mandatorily), but it is not clear whether the longer prison terms served were the result of discretionary parole systems or the nature of the inmate’s crime or institutional misconduct. Opponents of parole also assert that there is no evidence that placing offenders on parole supervision helps reduce their recidivism rates. A controversial study by the Urban Institute “Does Parole Supervision Work?” found no difference in the rearrest rates of offenders released from prison with and without parole supervision. After statistically controlling for the offenders’ demographic characteristics and criminal histories, the researchers found that 61 % of mandatory parolees (those without supervision) were rearrested, compared with 57 % of discretionary (with supervision) parole releasees. Solomon et al. (2005, p. 37) concluded that “Parole has not contributed substantially to reduced recidivism and increased public safety.” This is not to say that parole supervision could not reduce recidivism, only that at the aggregate level in which it was studied, there was no evidence that it reduced rearrests. Rehabilitation Programs, the Cost of Parole Supervision, and Civil Disabilities Although 70 % of all persons under correctional control are on probation or parole, nearly nine out of ten correctional dollars goes to funding prisons. Nationally, the 2008 average annual cost of a year in prison was $29,000. In contrast, the average annual cost of parole supervision was $2,750. In California, with the nation’s largest prison and parole population, the figures are dramatic: for every dollar California spends on prisons, it spent 15 cents on parole (Pew Center on the States 2009). Parole officers complain of growing paperwork and diminishing resources devoted to treatment of parolees. Some parolees do not participate in any parole programming at all. It is no wonder that recidivism rates are so high. In a sense, we get what we pay for, and we have never chosen to invest sufficiently in parole or reentry programs. 3445 P In addition to few treatment resources, parolees are also subject to a number of statutory restrictions or “civil disabilities” when they return home. Many restrictions are statutory, stemming from a common-law tradition that people who are incarcerated are “civilly dead” and have lost all civil rights (Travis 2005). Their criminal record may preclude them from voting or retaining their parental rights and be grounds for divorce, and they may be barred from serving on a jury, holding public office, and owning firearms. In 11 states in 2004, ex-prisoners were permanently denied the right to vote (Manza and Uggen 2006). Employers are also increasingly forbidden from hiring parolees for certain jobs and are mandated to perform background checks for many others. The most common types of jobs with legal prohibitions against parolees are in the fields of childcare, education, security, nursing, and home health care – exactly the types of jobs that are expanding. Since the mid-1980s, the number of barred occupations has increased dramatically. Even if a parolee is not legally barred from a particular job, research shows that ex-offenders face bleak prospects in the labor market, with the mark of a criminal record representing an important barrier to finding work (Pager 2003). More than 60 % of employers claim that they would not knowingly hire an applicant with a criminal background (Holzer et al. 2002). Overcoming the barriers that ex-offenders face in finding a job is critical to successful reintegration, since employment helps ex-prisoners be productive, take care of their families, develop valuable life skills, and strengthen their self-esteem and social connectedness. Research has also empirically established a positive link between job stability and reduced criminal offending. Lipsey’s (1995) metaanalysis of nearly 400 studies found that the single most effective factor in reducing re-offending rates was employment. Revolving Door Justice: Inmates Release, Recidivism, and Prison Return Staying out of prison is a lot harder than getting out. The landmark BJS study of prisoners released in 15 states in 1994 found that fully P P 3446 two-thirds (67 %) were rearrested and just over one-half (52 %) were back in prison, serving time for a new prison sentence or for a technical violation of their release, within 3 years (Langan and Levin 2002). The “two-thirds rearrest rate” after 3 years has been documented in the United States for about 35 years, ever since Daniel Glaser conducted his classic follow-up study of prisoners in The Effectiveness of a Prison and Parole System (1969). The Langan and Levin (2002) study also found that certain characteristics were associated with parole failure: black parolees had higher rearrest rates, as did males in general, those with fewer prior arrests, those incarcerated for property offenses, and those who were younger at release (under 25). The failure rate for prisoners who had been previously released on parole and were now being re-released was much higher (64 %) than for prisoners being released to parole for the first time (21 %) (Travis and Lawrence 2002). Rosenfeld et al. (2005), using data from the BJS recidivism study, calculated arrest probabilities by month for each of the 36 months after release. They adjusted the probability of arrest by subtracting out persons who were in jail, in prison, or dead during the month and therefore not eligible for arrest. Their results show that the probability of arrest declines with months out of prison and that the probability of arrest during the first month out of prison is roughly double than that during the fifteenth month. Arrest probabilities also differ by type of crime: prison releasees arrested on property or drug offenses are more likely to be arrested early in the post-release period than those arrested for violent offenses. Clearly, the first few months after prison release represent high crime risks, but Binswanger et al. (2007) also found that death rates for new prison releases – within the first days and weeks – are much higher than for matched demographic groups in the general population. The higher prisoner-release death rates (12 times the average for the general population) were caused by high rates of homicide and drug overdoses. These results have led to calls to front-load parole services and surveillance so as to reduce these and other negative outcomes Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States during the first 6 months after release (National Research Council 2008). While individual recidivism studies have always shown high failure rates, until recently there was little attention paid to the overall amount of crime returning prisoners were responsible for. Rosenfeld et al. (2005) reanalyzed the BJS data and estimated that parolees accounted for 10–15 % of all violent, property, and drug arrests between 1994 and 1997 and the share of total arrests attributable to released prisoners grew as general crime rates declined during the 1990s. In 1994 the arrests of prisoners released in the previous 3 years accounted for 13 % of all arrests. By 2001 that figure had increased to more than 20 %. If former prisoners are accounting for nearly one-fifth of all the nation’s arrests, then investing in prisoner reentry is unquestionably a matter of public safety. Such evidence has encouraged law enforcement organizations such as the International Association of Chiefs of Police (IACP) and the National District Attorneys Association to develop policies, training, and other tools that support effective prisoner reentry (La Vigne et al. 2006). Parole Violators and Their Impact on Prison Populations The BJS reports that about 50 % of released prisoners will be returned to prison in the 3 years following release – and most of them will eventually be re-released, and the revolving door process will continually be repeated. Prisoners refer to it as “doing a life term on the installment plan.” The constant churning of parolees in and out of incarceration is a major contributor to the growing US population. As a percentage of all admissions to state prisons, parole violators more than doubled from 17 % in 1980 to nearly 35 % in 2006 (Sabol and Couture 2008). In these budget-strapped times, many question the public safety benefits of violating parolees for technical violations, such as missing a meeting with a parole agent, being out after a curfew time, and, increasingly, failing a drug test. Processing admissions of parole violators takes as much time and costs as much money as processing admissions of new convictions and for offenders who Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States often will be in prison for only a few months. Many advocates argue that technical violations should not result in a return to prison and can be handled in the community with less-drastic intermediate sanctions. The contrary view is that some violations, even of a procedural nature, are significant signs that a parolee is not respecting the terms of the parole contract and should suffer consequences. This can also be a sign that even if the current violation is minor, if left unattended, it might lead to more serious ones. Several states have begun to use parole violation decisionmaking instruments to respond systematically to violations. The goal of such instruments is to differentiate technical violations and the response to them by the severity and risk posed by the offender, ultimately decreasing prison admissions for technical violations and reducing disparities in parole decision making. Responding appropriately to parolee recidivism is one way to manage correctional resources better, but preventing parolees from failing in the first place is a more proactive strategy. But that begs the all-important question of whether we can implement reentry programs to increase the odds of success. Future Directions No one believes that the current parole and reentry system is working, but the $64,000 question is, can we do better? Can we improve the outcomes for people returning from prison so that they are less likely to be rearrested? Fortunately, the last decade has seen an explosion of interest in parole and prisoner reentry, and the “what works?” literature has improved. After extensively reviewing all of the literature, the National Research Council (2008, p. 82) concluded, “‘Nothing works’ is no longer a defensible conclusion from assessment of program effects on re-entry outcomes.” What Works in Reentry Programming? Using a variety of techniques, researchers have developed a list of principles of effective intervention and found that programs adhering to these principles significantly reduced recidivism, sometimes by as much as 30 % (Andrews and 3447 P Bonta 2006; Lowenkamp et al. 2006). Petersilia (2004) summarized these principles and their applicability to reentry programs: • Treatment services should be behavioral in nature; interventions should employ the cognitive behavioral and social learning techniques of modeling. • Reinforcements in the program should be largely positive, not negative. • Services should be intensive, lasting 3–12 months (depending on need), and occupy 40–70 % of the offender’s time during the course of the program. • Treatment interventions should be used primarily with higher-risk offenders, targeting their criminogenic needs (dynamic risk factors for change). • The best strategy for discerning offender risk level is to rely on actuarial-based assessment instruments. • Conducting interventions in the community as opposed to an institutional setting will increase treatment effectiveness. • In terms of staffing, there is a need to match styles and modes of treatment service to the learning styles of the offender (specific responsivity). It is impossible to know the extent to which these evidence-based principles are being used in current parole and reentry programs. Interest in prisoner reentry over the last decade has fueled the development of hundreds of programs across the United States. Some reentry programs are small and administered by community- and faith-based organizations, whereas other programs are large statewide initiatives, often administered by the state’s corrections department. Some programs start inside the prison and continue into the community, whereas others begin when the prisoner has returned home. Some programs are residential, others involve day reporting, and still others involve a meeting every month or two. They rely on existing and volunteer community treatment services, primarily Alcoholics Anonymous and Narcotics Anonymous. The academic “what works” literature barely touches these programs, but these programs are delivering vital services and P P 3448 should not be dismissed, as they are the foot soldiers of the reentry movement. Many other reentry programs are part of federally funded reentry initiatives implemented in recent years. The “what works” literature is influencing their design and evaluations. The largest effort to implement evidence-based reentry principles systematically is the federal government’s Serious and Violent Offender Reentry Initiative (SVORI). In 2003, 69 agencies representing all 50 states received more than $110 million in federal funds to develop programs to improve the outcomes of serious and violent prisoners coming home (Lattimore et al. 2005). The federal government’s SVORI goals were to improve a variety of outcomes, including family relationships, work, health, community integration, housing, and reduced crime. Programs were also encouraged to focus specifically on serious and violent offenders, or both. Most programs used a formal risk assessment tool to identify risks and needs, as recommended in the “what works” literature. Early outcome results appear promising. SVORI participants were more likely to receive services and participate in needed programs, and SVORI participants are doing better across a wide range of outcomes. Recidivism outcomes are not yet reported, but other outcomes, including housing, employment, mental health, and substance abuse, have improved. As Lattimore and Visher (2009) reported to Congress, “In most cases, the difference in outcomes between those participating in SVORI programs and the comparison subjects indicates that SVORI program participation resulted in an improvement in outcomes.” It is important to note that most SVORI participants were repeat serious offenders (the males had an average of 13 prior arrests), so that even relatively small reductions in recidivism rates may be quite cost-beneficial. In sum, it is possible to reduce offender recidivism in a cost-effective manner. The answer lies in investing in reentry programs that incorporate “what works” principles, targeting those programs on specific offenders who can most benefit, and continually evaluating and revising program models as the science accumulates. Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States Conclusions and Future Research Parole and prisoner reentry issues have captured the nation’s attention, and the US parole system is entering another chapter in its history. Attacks on parole and community-based programs have virtually disappeared and have been replaced with calls for investing more, not less, in parole and prisoner reentry. Where there was little scholarly attention paid to parole just 10 years ago, the volume and visibility of work around parole and prisoner reentry issues has grown to such an extent that it is now commonly referred to as a full-fledged movement (Petersilia 2009). And the reentry momentum is likely to continue. Voters are tiring of our dependence on mass incarceration as a response to crime and more willing to embrace a more balanced system of punishment. For all that has been learned about parole and reentry in recent years, a number of important research questions remain. We now know a good deal about the needs of returning prisoners and have some evidence about the services they receive. However, much less research exists on the effectiveness of particular approaches to delivering services, and only a small number of studies have used rigorous scientific methods to test promising practices. The highest priority for future research is more credible program evaluations. To date, no studies have analyzed the differences among low-, medium-, and high-risk offenders using an experimental design. A recent panel of the National Research Council (2008, p. 82) concluded that while there is a great deal of experiential and practitioner knowledge with regard to the apparent efficacy of reentry programs, “the challenge now is to subject these promising practices to rigorously designed evaluations.” Rigorous program evaluations should accompany every significant reentry initiative, and outcomes for these studies should focus not solely on recidivism but also on other behavioral outcomes, such as sobriety, stability in housing and employment, and attachment to families and communities. Our studies must also disaggregate the characteristics of the offender population so that we can design better programs for specialized populations, such as women, Parole and Prisoner Reentry in the United States the elderly, sex offenders, or the mentally ill. A higher proportion of parolees in the future are likely to be composed of one of these distinct population groups, and we know very little about how to deliver services to meet their specific needs. We also need a better understanding of how neighborhood characteristics affect the reintegration of offenders. Hipp et al. (2010) recently reported that the presence of more social service providers nearby (within two miles) led to lower recidivism rates and that this protective effect was particularly strong for African American and Latino parolees. They also found that parolees living in neighborhoods with higher levels of concentrated disadvantage experienced greater rates of recidivism, even after taking into account the individual characteristics of these parolees. This study highlights the importance of social context for successful reintegration. Research must move beyond simple statistical models that attempt to explain parolees’ return to prison solely as a function of the parolees’ background and behavior, since the characteristics of their agent, supervising agency, and community may be significant predictors as well. Finally, researchers must study successful parolees in order to uncover the factors that encourage offenders to shift from formal social controls to informal social controls. Ultimately, parolees who make it shift from being accountable to programs and criminal justice agencies (e.g., police, parole) to being accountable to more informal social controls (e.g., families, neighbors). Ideally, formal criminal justice sanctions should act as “presses” to increase social bonds to law-abiding family members and conventional institutions. Ethnographic studies can identify how to promote positive social bonds between ex-convicts and community members. We are now witnessing the start of a new ideological pendulum shift in US punishment policy. A declining economy that is pressuring states to reduce incarceration, combined with a growing body of evidence identifying effective reentry programs, has created a window of opportunity for change. Parole and prisoner reentry 3449 P may well serve as a major conceptual framework for reorganizing criminal justice policy in the twenty-first century. Related Entries ▶ Aging Correctional Populations ▶ Aging Prison Population: Factors to Consider ▶ Crime and the Racial Composition of Communities ▶ Criminal Careers and Public Policy Responses ▶ Deterrent Effect of Imprisonment ▶ Drug Abuse and Alcohol Dependence Among Inmates ▶ Drug Courts ▶ Health Issues in Prison Reentry Models ▶ History of Corrections ▶ History of Probation and Parole in the United States ▶ Intensive Probation and Parole ▶ New Penology ▶ Offender Change in Treatment ▶ Probation and Parole Practices ▶ Probation Officer Decision-Making ▶ Punishment as Rehabilitation ▶ Re-entry ▶ Reentry Courts ▶ Sex Offenders and Criminal Policy Recommended Reading and References Andrews D, Bonta J (2006) The psychology of criminal conduct, 4th edn. Anderson, Cincinnati Binswanger I, Stern M, Deyo R, Heagerty P, Cheadle A, Elmore J, Koepsell T (2007) Release from rison – a high risk of death for former inmates. N Engl J Med 356:157–165 Ditton P (1999) Mental health and treatment of inmates and probationers. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington DC Glaze LE, Bonczar T (2010) Probation and Parole in the United States, 2009. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington, DC Glaze LE, Bonczar TP (2008) Probation and Parole in the United States, 2007 – statistical tables. Bureau of Justice Statistics. U.S. Department of Justice, Washington, DC Hammett T, Harmon P, Rhodes W (2002) The burden of infectious disease among inmates and releasees from P P 3450 correctional facilities. In: National Commission on Correctional Healthcare (ed) The health status of soon-to-be-released inmates. National Institute of Justice, Washington DC Hipp J, Petersilia J, Turner S (2010) Parolee recidivism in California: the effect of neighborhood context and social service agency characteristics. Criminology 48(4):947–979 Holzer H, Raphael S, Stoll M (2002) Can employers play a more positive role in prisoner reentry? Urban Institute, Washington, DC Langan P, Levin D (2002) Recidivism of prisoners released in 1994. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington, DC Lattimore PK, Visher CA, Winterfield L, Lindquist C, Brumbaugh S (2005) Implementation of prisoner reentry programs: findings from the serious and violent offender reentry initiative multi-site evaluation. Justice Res Policy 7(2):87–109 Lattimore PK, Visher CA (2009) The multi-site evaluation of the serious and violent offender reentry initiative. The Urban Institute. Available at http://www.urban. org/publications/412075.html Lipsey MW (1995) What do we learn from 400 research studies on the effectiveness of treatment with Juvenile Delinquency? In: McQuire J (ed) What works: reducing reoffending. Wiley, West Sussex Lowenkamp CT, Latessa EJ, Smith P (2006) Does correctional program quality really matter? The impact of adhering to the principles of effective intervention. Criminol Public Policy 5(3):575–594 Lynch JP, Sabol WJ (2001) Prisoner reentry in perspective. Urban Institute, Washington, DC Manza J, Uggen C (2006) Locked out: felon disenfranchisement and American democracy. Oxford University Press, New York Martinson R (1974) What works? Questions and answers about prison reform. Public Interest 35(Spring):22–35 Marvell TB, Moody CE (1996) Determinate sentencing and abolishing parole: the long-term impacts on prisons and crime. Criminology 34(1):107–128 National Center for Education Statistics (1994) Literacy behind prison walls. U.S. Department of Education, Washington, DC National Commission on Correctional Health Care (2002) The health status of soon-to-be-released inmates: a report to congress. National Institute of Justice, Washington, DC National Research Council (2008) Parole, desistance from crime, and community integration. National Academy of Sciences, Washington, DC Pager D (2003) The mark of a criminal record. Am J Sociol 108(5):937–75 Petersilia J (2003) When prisoners come home: parole and prisoner reentry. Oxford University Press, New York Petersilia J (2004) What works in prisoner reentry? Reviewing and questioning the evidence. Fed Probat 68(2):4–8 Pathways to Delinquency Petersilia J (2009) Transformation in prisoner reentry: what a difference a decade makes. Afterword in When Prisoners Come Home by Petersilia, Oxford University Press Pew Center on the States (2009) One in 31: the long reach of American corrections. The Pew Charitable Trusts, Washington, DC Rosenfeld R, Wallman J, Fornango R (2005) The contribution of ex-prisoners to crime rates. In: Travis J, Visher CA (eds) Prisoner reentry and crime in America. Cambridge University Press, New York Sabol WJ, Couture H (2008) Prison inmates at midyear 2007. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington Solomon AL, Kachnowski V, Bhati A (2005) Does parole work? Analyzing the impact of postprison supervision on rearrest outcomes. Urban Institute, Washington, DC Travis J (2005) But they all come back: facing the challenges of prisoner reentry. The Urban Institute, Washington, DC Travis J, Lawrence S (2002) Beyond the prison gates: the state of parole in America. Urban Institute, Washington, DC U.S. Government Accounting Office (2001) Prisoner Releases: trends and information on reintegration programs, Washington, DC Vigne L, Nancy G, Solomon A, Beckman K, Dedel K (2006) Prisoner reentry and community policing: strategies for enhancing public safety. Urban Institute, Washington, DC Pathways to Delinquency Rolf Loeber Department of Psychiatry, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA, USA Overview Modern criminological theories aim to explain crime, but they do so with a different emphasis on pathways to crime and ranges of explanatory factors (e.g., Farrington 2005; Thornberry and Krohn 2003). Although theories of antisocial and delinquent behavior often have several factors in common (e.g., juveniles’ relationships with parents and peers), they differ in their relative emphasis on domains, settings, and details of explanatory factors, and the ways that these factors are developmentally interrelated (see above Pathways to Delinquency sources and chapters in Farrington 2005, and in Lahey et al. 2003). The models also much differ in the extent to which they are two-dimensional (i.e., on one surface) on paper or can be visualized in a better ways. This entry concerns advances in the conceptualization and visualization of development of behavioral stages, leading to serious forms of delinquency and explanatory factors that account for individual differences in how far individuals progress in their offending. Issues in the Construction of Models to Explain Delinquency and Crime Criminological theories (Thornberry and Krohn 2003) almost always share three themes with the goals of explaining: (a) antisocial and delinquent behavior over the life-course, particularly in terms of prevalence, frequency, and severity of delinquent acts; (b) individual differences in antisocial/delinquent behavior and developmental changes in these differences; and (c) nonoffending or low-level offending. The key is for researchers, practitioners, and policy makers to understand how the combination of (a), (b), and (c) explains why some individuals and not others become serious property offenders or violent offenders and understand this both on the population level (e.g., all youth in a particular city) and on the individual level (i.e., a particular juvenile minor offender at risk of becoming a serious offender). Along these lines, there is a need for better life-course models that incorporate the development and accumulation of risk and protective factors. To date, the integration of these components in a model has taken place almost exclusively through the following methods. Firstly, model specification is usually visually illustrated in a two-dimensional plane of variables in boxes (representing usually a single outcome of delinquency, such as violence or property crime) and their interrelationships are expressed by arrows between the boxes. Secondly, virtually, all model specification rests on multivariate statistical tests of the hypothesized relationships between independent measures also called risk factors 3451 P (the boxes) and an outcome, such as serious delinquency. Risk factors are defined here as events or conditions that are associated with an increased probability of serious forms of delinquency, distinguishing risk factors from protective factors, which are factors associated with lowered risk of delinquency. However, there are at least five limitations to the models tested to date (Loeber et al. 2006). Firstly, the empirical results of the multivariate models have been enormously diverse. The second disadvantage is that most models have not delineated developmental pathways to serious forms of antisocial behavior (such as violence) by the specification of developmental antecedents to such serious outcomes (e.g., nonviolent forms of aggression). Third, current models do not specify differences between individuals in their exposure to an accumulation of specific risk (or protective) factors with development. A fourth disadvantage has to do with the fact that the majority of studies focus only on risk factors as a way of explaining antisocial behavior and either neglect to consider protective factors or the combined effect of risk and protective factors on antisocial outcomes. We argue that criminological theories can be enhanced in at least two other ways, firstly by incorporating past development, and secondly, by incorporating possible future development. In the first category are differences in individuals’ past history of offending (and history of behavior problems that are precursors to delinquency), and differences in the individuals’ exposure to earlier risk factors (e.g., prenatal exposure to toxins or child abuse during the preschool period) and protective factors (e.g., a good relationship with an adult). The second understudied area has to do with two aspects of individuals’ futures: firstly, the possible course of subsequent delinquent development (or pathways) as examined by longitudinal studies of youth who have been followed up into adulthood; and secondly, expected exposure to risk and protective factors based on the observation of such factors in older populations of youth. Examples of “new” risk factors that individuals may be exposed to during adolescence include: gang membership, violent P P 3452 victimization, and alcohol intoxication. In summary, we propose that developmental models should benefit from knowledge of pathways and exposure to risk and protective factors based on past studies which can then provide a framework in which to place the development of specific individuals. In that sense, population data can describe both the stages in pathways to serious delinquency (the latter being the outer, more severe boundary) and the gradual accumulation of risk and protective factors that can maximally take place in populations (another instance of an outer boundary). Knowledge of these two types of outer boundaries will make it possible to describe the past history of an individual’s antisocial and delinquent behavior, his/her past exposure to risk and protective factors, and possible future exposure to ongoing or new risk and protective factors. One of the key advantages of such a model is that, in contrast to current statistical models, it is likely to provide valuable information about choices and targets of intervention. This is very much in line with contemporary principles of prevention and intervention, with its focus on behavioral development and an emphasis on reducing exposure to risk factors while at the same time increasing exposure to protective factors (Pollard et al. 1999). We argue that the complex of factors described above is easier to understand by policy makers, informed lay-persons, and practitioners when visualized in a model of a three-, rather than a two-dimensional space or model specified as a multivariate formulae. To construct such a visual model, it is necessary to review five key topics: (1) pathways representing individuals’ escalation toward serious property offenses and violence; (2) differences between individuals in their exposure to risk and protective factors at birth (called start-up factors) and subsequently during childhood, adolescence, and early adulthood; (3) developmental accumulation of risk and protective factors over time; (4) the existence of a dose–response relationship between the number of risk/protective factors and later serious delinquency and violence; and (5) additive and compensatory effects of protective and risk Pathways to Delinquency factors. Finally, we integrate these five aspects into a single, three-dimensional cumulative, developmental model. Escalation and the Formulation of Developmental Pathways Youth who commit acts of violence or serious theft rarely do so de novo. Instead, many criminologists, child psychologists, and psychiatrists agree that the majority of youth who commit acts of violence or serious theft practiced less serious forms of delinquency earlier in life (e.g., Le Blanc 2002; Warr 2002). Thus, the onset of violence is usually preceded by a history of escalation in the severity of aggression, which often, but not always, starts in childhood (Moffitt 1993). The findings of several studies focus on a single escalation pathway. However Loeber et al. (1993) challenged this and tested a triple pathway model (Fig. 1), which better fitted the data. The three pathways are as follows: (a) An Authority Conflict Pathway prior to the age of 12, that starts with stubborn behavior, and has defiance as a second stage, and authority avoidance (e.g., truancy) as a third stage; (b) A Covert Pathway prior to age 15 which starts with minor covert acts, has property damage as a second stage, and moderate to serious delinquency as a third stage; and (c) An Overt Pathway that starts with minor aggression, has physical fighting as a second stage, and more severe violence as a third stage. It is possible that within this last stage, homicide constitutes a separate, most serious component (Loeber et al. 1993). Recent longitudinal research on the Pittsburgh Youth Study (Loeber et al. 2011) indicates that 94 % of later homicide offenders have displayed violence earlier in life. The pathways are hierarchical in that those who have advanced to the most serious behavior in each of the pathways have usually displayed persistent problem behavior characteristics at the earlier stages in each pathway. By a process of selection, increasingly smaller groups of youth become at risk for the more serious behaviors. The pathways are also related to neighborhoods. For example, a higher Pathways to Delinquency 3453 AGE OF ONSET: LATE %BOYS: FEW VIOLENCE (rape, attack, strong-arm) SERIOUS DELINQUENCY (auto theft,burglary) PHYSICAL FIGHTING (physical fighting, gang fighting) MINOR AGGRESSION (bullying, annoying others) OVERT PATHWAY EARLY P MODERATELY SERIOUS DELINQUENCY (fraud, pick-pocketing) AUTHORITY AVOIDANCE (truancy, running away, staying out late) PROPERTY DAMAGE (vandalism, fire-setting) MINOR COVERT BEHAVIOR (shoplifting, frequent lying) Defiance/Disobedience COVERT PATHWAY (before age 15) Stubborn Behavior MANY AUTHORITY CONFLICT PATHWAY (before age 12) Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 1 Developmental pathways to serious delinquency and violence (Loeber et al. 1993) percentage of youth in the most disadvantaged neighborhoods escalates from minor aggression to violence than youth living in more advantaged neighborhoods (Loeber and Wikstro¨m 1993). The three-pathway model has been subsequently replicated across two other samples in the Pittsburgh Youth Study. In addition, several other studies have replicated the pathways model (Loeber et al. 1999; Tolan et al. 2000). Risk Factors The majority of theories about the causes of crime and antisocial behavior are generally based on risk factors alone, although different terms for such factors have been used (e.g., Gottfredson and Hirshi 1990; Moffitt 1993). Risk factors can be distinguished according to the different domains and contexts in which they operate. Overall, researchers and theoreticians agree (with some variation) to distinguish risk factors in the following domains: individual, family, and peer group. In addition, some risk factors are associated with children’s exposure to risk factors in specific contexts, including characteristics of the school attended and the neighborhood in which the children reside or spend their time (Howell 2003; Loeber and Farrington 1998; Wikstro¨m and Loeber 2000). Data from prediction studies indicate that risk factors from each of the domains (individual, family, peers, schools, and neighborhoods) contributes to the explanation of why some individuals and not others progress from minor problem behavior such as bullying, to physical fighting, to violence (e.g., Farrington 1997; Loeber et al. 2011). Individuals’ exposure to an accumulation of risk factors in multiple domains rather than in a single domain heightens the probability of P P 3454 later adverse outcomes. For example, DeaterDeckard et al. (1998) find that each of four domains (child characteristics, sociocultural, parent, and peer experiences) contributes to the prediction of externalizing problems. Many researchers have been relatively silent about the developmental saliency and priority of different domains of risk factors (individual, family, peer, etc.), other than noting that children’s exposure to family factors usually precedes their exposure to peer factors. As children develop, the configuration of problem behaviors changes, with children becoming more mobile and becoming also more active in selecting settings with their own risk and protective factors, when children become exposed to risk and protective factors of peers, school, and, eventually, work. Thus, with development, there is a reconfiguration of risk domains with new domains and new risk factors being introduced over time. Developmentally graded Risk Factors. Among the risk factors, some are thought to be present at birth or become manifest shortly afterward, while other risk factors emerge later in individuals’ lives. Before discussing each category of risk factors, our overall strategy is to view risk factors from a developmental angle in that children’s exposure to different risk factors is gradual, that with development, children’s exposure to different risk domains increases, and that many risk factors persist over time and, consequently, are “stacked” over time. It would be clearly untenable to insist that all the risk and protective factors mentioned in the preceding section are present in juveniles’ lives from a very young age onward. Instead, it is much more likely that selection processes operate in which certain categories of children and youth are incrementally exposed to certain risk and protective factors as they grow into adults (see below). Loeber et al. (2006) reviewed the emergence of risk factors during childhood and adolescence, starting with risk factors present at birth, and those emerging during the following periods: preschool, elementary school, middle/high school, and early adulthood. Emergence is defined as the probable earliest exposure of children to risk factors. Systematic knowledge in this Pathways to Delinquency respect is still wanting, and as a result, we have made estimates (knowing that some of the onset of risk factors, such as in the case of poor executive functioning, partly depends on the state of measurement in that area). Note that emergence should not be taken too literally and may apply differently from one child to another. However, we maintain that an accumulation of risk factors may take place over many years, and that risk factors at birth (e.g., low IQ, negative emotional temperament) may be followed by exposure to “new” risk factors emerging during early childhood, such as language problems, which in turn may be followed by other novel risk factors emerging during middle to late childhood, such as poor social skills, or poor academic achievement. During adolescence, novel risk factors may consist of heavy substance use or delinquent victimization. These examples are risk factors in the individual domain, but a similar accumulation of new risk factors may occur in other domains as well, such as the family, peers, schools, and neighborhood (including work). It should be noted that, to some extent, risk factors emerging in one life period may persist across another life period and that even when they are time-limited (e.g., child abuse), they may influence the probability of serious delinquency in a cumulative manner. Loeber et al. (2006) concluded that the total number of risk factors associated with antisocial behavior and delinquency to which children can be exposed is about equally divided at or close to birth (15), emerging in the preschool years (12), and emerging in the elementary school age years (18). Much lower numbers of risk factors probably first appear during the middle and high school years (5). Thus, the most salient risk window of children’s exposure to risk factors is prior to adolescence. This must be true for early-onset cases of antisocial behavior and delinquency. Even within the category of early-onset cases, the model is flexible in that we assume that none of the early risk factors are necessary (i.e., absolutely required) for the emergence of antisocial behavior and delinquency. In that sense, there can be some substitution of risk factors that apply to some and not to other early-onset Pathways to Delinquency 3455 cases. In summary, the evidence suggests that individual risk factors continue to increase in numbers and in different configurations after childhood and constitute a substantial proportion of all known risk factors after early childhood. Dose–Response Relationship Between Risk Factors and Delinquency Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 2 Proportion of boys committing violent offenses for different levels of risk (Based on Loeber et al. 2005) Percentage Commiting Violence Studies agree that the higher the number of risk factors, the greater the likelihood that individuals will be affected by a negative outcome or other deviant behavior such as serious delinquency. This association is usually called a dose–response relationship and has been demonstrated for the full range of indicators of antisocial behavior: sociopathy, externalizing problems (DeaterDeckard et al. 1998), conduct problems (Fergusson and Woodward 2000), serious delinquency (Smith et al. 1995), and violence (Loeber et al. 2011). As an example (Fig. 2), a prediction index in the Pittsburgh Youth Study was constructed on the basis of the 11 strongest predictors of violence (Loeber et al. 1993): truancy, low school motivation, onset of delinquency before age ten, cruelty to people, depressed mood, physical aggression, and callous/unemotional behavior, low family SES, family on welfare, high parental stress, and bad (i.e., disadvantaged) neighborhood (parent report). Figure 2 also shows that the dose–response relationship applies to the number of predictors and the probability of later violence (Odds Ratio (OR) ¼ 6.0 for four or more risk P factors). Remarkably, the range of probabilities in the Pittsburgh data is from 3 % at zero risk factors to 100 % at 11 or more risk factors. In summary, these results (and those of several other studies) indicate a robust association between the number of risk factors and the probability of later violence. Remarkably, the association holds even when slightly different risk factors are measured from study to study. Stability. Implied is that some risk factors may persist over time. Investigations of risk factors often ignore the fact that such factors, similar to the outcomes that they purportedly predict, may vary in their temporal stability over time. Yet few studies have addressed the issue of stability of risk factors. An exception is Sameroff et al. (1998), who found that environmental risk factors correlate .77 over a 5-year period (ages 13–18), which is about the same level of stability as intelligence. Loeber et al. (2000) found that the year-to-year stability coefficients for the interactions between parents and their boys between ages 6 and 18 average.66 for bad parent–child relationship,.70 for poor parent–child communication, and lower for poor supervision (.56) and physical punishment (.46). Examination of absolute stability reveals that this is higher for bad relationships and poor communication, but decreases with age for poor supervision and physical punishment. It should be noted, however, that despite level changes in risk factors with development, many of the known risk factors continue to predict later negative outcomes, including delinquency, at different ages of children (e.g., Loeber and Farrington 1998; Loeber et al. 2008). 100% 75% 50% 25% 0% Base Rate 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 Number of Violence Risk Factors 7 8 9+ P P 3456 It is plausible that the presence of some risk factors set in motion a cascade of other risk factors. For example, the toxic teratogenic effect of maternal smoking may increase the probability of several other risk factors in the offspring, including poor executive functioning, poor academic achievement in school, low motivation to attend school, truancy, and, subsequently, delinquency. As another example, the presence of several risk factors (e.g., parents’ exposure to enduring stress and parents’ substance abuse) may increase the chance of antisocial behavior in the offspring at home, which in turn, may set the scene for heightened risk of problem behavior outside of the home. Yet, as Howell (2003) points out, it remains to be seen when and how risk factors operate in a “sequential causal chain” (p. 110). It is clearer that the prevalence of different risk factors is higher in disadvantaged compared to advantaged neighborhoods (Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2002; Wikstro¨m and Loeber 2000). Protective Factors Most criminology and psychopathology studies with a public health slant have routinely neglected the study of protective factors (Lo¨sel and Bender 2003). Protective factors are associated with the likelihood of reduced antisocial behavior/delinquency and/or increased positive outcomes, including positive adjustment and positive mental health. Developmentally graded Protective Factors. There is an increasing body of research on protective factors (see review by Lo¨sel and Bender 2003), but that body is still miniscule in comparison to the number of publications on risk factors pertaining to antisocial behavior and delinquency. In particular, we know very little about the developmental aspects of the accumulation of protective factors through the life-course. However, the framework proposed by Hawkins and colleagues (Catalano and Hawkins 1996) and ourselves (Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2002) is unusual in criminology because each postulates changes within protective factors to explain individual differences in the development of offending. At the Pathways to Delinquency risk of being speculative, we postulate that some protective factors, like risk factors, may be present at birth, but that other factors emerge during the first decades of life. Loeber et al. (2006) shows protective factors mentioned in the research literature (or factors that are probably protective according to our view) as being relevant to antisocial behavior and delinquency (based on Loeber and Farrington in press; Lo¨sel and Bender 2003; Pollard et al. 1999; Sampson and Laub 1990; Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2002, 2004). Most of the protective factors are the inverse of risk factors, in that many, but not all, of the protective factors represent the other pole of risk factors. However, we do not advocate that protective factors are the complete inverse of risk factors (see Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2004 for details). Research shows that there are several protective factors that do not have a risk factor equivalent (Loeber et al. 2008). Examples of these unique protective factors are low Attention-Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder symptoms, and low anxiety. As with the development of risk factors, we assume that there is a developmentally graded emergence of protective factors (Loeber et al. 2006). Some of the protective factors are thought to be present at birth (e.g., moderate to high intelligence, absence of prenatal exposure to toxins), while other factors become manifest later. It is also thought that there is a high degree of temporal stability of protective factors, although the data on this have not yet been reported. In the Pittsburgh Youth Study (Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2004), accountability, perceived likelihood of getting caught for delinquent acts, and low physical punishment are recurring factors that are associated with desistance in persistent serious delinquency at different ages. Relatively little is known about increases in protective factors with development. Stouthamer-Loeber (2002) found that the proportion of significant associations between protective factors and delinquency increases with age. This conclusion, however, is limited by the reason that the age comparisons are based on different cohorts, and, therefore, require replication to be proven. It is likely that protective factors, such as risk factors, are correlated, in that one protective Pathways to Delinquency factor may set the scene for another protective factor to emerge. For instance, association with prosocial peers may generate new prosocial behavior, which, once adopted by an individual child, may further decrease the probability that that child will engage in delinquent acts. Hawkins and his colleagues (2003) are among the few who have specified prosocial pathways in the delinquency research that can be conceptualized as a string of protective factors. They postulate that opportunities for prosocial behavior set the scene for interpersonal involvement, which in turn produces rewards, improving bonding to others and promoting belief in a moral order. Research shows that the prevalence of different protective factors is highest in the most advantaged neighborhoods (Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2002; Wikstro¨m and Loeber 2000). Inverse Dose–Response Relationship Between Protective Factors and Delinquency Is there an inverse dose–response relationship between the number of protective factors and later deviance (the higher the number of protective factors, the lower the probability of deviance)? There are very few research studies addressing this question. Outside the area of delinquency, Sameroff et al. (1998) found that the higher the number of protective factors, the lower is the probability of behavior problems, with the results mirroring the results of the risk factors: “The more risk factors, the worse the outcomes; the more protective factors, the better the outcomes” (p. 172). Similar results have been reported by Wikstro¨m and Loeber (2000), thus lending support to the notion that the accumulation of protective factors in juveniles’ lives counters the likelihood of later delinquent involvement. Do Protective Factors Offset the Impact of Risk Factors? What is the evidence that protective factors buffer the risk for later antisocial behavior and 3457 P delinquency? Stouthamer-Loeber et al. (2002) showed that even at the level of the number of risk or protective domains (child behaviors, child attitudes, school, peers, family, demographic characteristics), the sum of risk and protective domains (where the number of protective domains is deducted from the risk domains) linearly predicts persistent serious delinquency (Fig. 3). The higher the number of risk domains to which a youth is exposed and the lower his/her exposure to protective domains, the greater the likelihood of later persistent delinquency. Conversely, the higher the number of protective domains and the lower the number of risk domains, the smaller the likelihood of later persistent serious delinquency. This was replicated for the youngest and oldest samples; for different degrees of neighborhood advantage and disadvantage, for specific risk and protective factors, and for early and late onset forms of delinquency (Loeber et al. 2008; Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2002; Wikstro¨m and Loeber 2000). Not all researchers, however, have found that the relationship between risk and protective factors is linear. For example, Pollard et al. (1999), studying such diverse outcomes as substance use, arrest, and attack to hurt, found a nonlinear effect with the effect of risk factors greater as the level of risk increased. However, it is plausible that once neighborhood context is taken into account, nonlinear associations occur. For example, Wikstro¨m and Loeber (2000) report that, “the overwhelming majority of boys with a high risk score were involved in serious offending regardless of the socioeconomic context of their neighbourhood” (p. 1130). However, neighborhood matters greatly for those with a balanced score of risk and protective factors. Toward a Three-Dimensional Model of Developmental Pathways and Developmentally Graded Risk and Protective Factors To summarize firstly, we have reviewed developmental pathways from minor to serious delinquent behavior. Secondly, we have discussed P 3458 Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 3 The higher the number of risk domains (and the lower the number of protective domains), the higher the risk of later persistent serious delinquency (Stouthamer-Loeber et al. 2002) Pathways to Delinquency * * 100 % Persistent Serious Delinquents P 80 60 40 20 0 * * –6 –5 –4 –3 –2 –1 0 1 2 Protective 4 5 6 Risk High/Medium SES developmentally graded, cumulative onset of risk factors and developmentally graded, cumulative onset of protective factors (Loeber et al. 2006). Thirdly, we have seen that there are dose–response relationships between the number of risk factors and the probability of later delinquency and violence, and an inverse dose–response relationship between the number of protective factors and the reduced probability of later delinquency and violence. Finally, we have seen that knowledge of the proportion of risk and protective factors is more important than knowledge of either. The question then is how to bring these different strands of evidence together? At this point, we want to take a rather unconventional route. In science, the verification of models is usually accomplished by mathematical formulae. We are not aware of formulae that describe the different aspects that we have stressed. An alternative or rather a step toward such a composite model is to display the above interrelationships visually in a three-dimensional model. Before discussing this model, we will present each component. Figure 4 shows a version of two of the pathways depicted in Fig. 1, which has been reoriented into the horizontal plane. These two pathways are overt and covert behavior (leaving aside for the moment the authority conflict pathway), with the overt pathway triangle superimposed on the covert pathway triangle. Figure 5 represents the developmentally graded, 3 Low SES *N<5 Top: most serious forms of delinquency Covert Pathway Overt Pathway Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 4 Pathway model flipped horizontally (overt pathway on the top and the cover pathway underneath) cumulative onset of risk factors into a number of vertical panels, each of the same shape, but with ribs of different sizes, representing different degrees of individuals’ exposure to risk factors, so that they would fit on the horizontal pathway picture (Fig. 4). In the central and highest risk rib, the number of risk factors present at birth is thought to be higher than in the adjoining ribs, the accumulation of risk factors is highest, and the length of the rib is shown to be longest to represent the higher degree of severity of delinquency. In contrast, the adjoining smaller ribs represent fewer risk factors at birth and a smaller accumulation of later risk factors. Figure 6 represents the distribution of “start-up” risk factors at birth in the form of a long triangle. Pathways to Delinquency 3459 P Risk factor planes Promotive factor planes Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 5 Accumulation of risk factors at different levels of accumulation Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 7 Accumulation of promotive factors at different levels of accumulation Start-up Protective factors Start-up Risk factors Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 6 Distribution of risk factors at birth Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 8 Distribution of promotive factors at birth (start-up promotive factors) The central top of that triangle indicates a category of children with the highest number of risk factors at birth and at the extremes are those with the fewest number of risk factors at that time. Figure 6 represents developmental rather than chronological time. Figure 7 represents ribs of the accumulation of protective factors in an inverse way to the risk factors. However, the central rib is the least tall because those who advance to the most serious acts are usually exposed to the lowest number of protective factors. In contrast, individuals who do not advance to serious delinquency outcomes tend to start out in life with and accumulate more protective factors than those in the central rib. Figure 8, in the form of half a butterfly, may clarify the “start-up” protective factors which are thought to be lowest in the center and highest at the extremes. Finally, Fig. 9 shows how each of the above elements is put together. Individuals who advance to the most serious delinquent acts on the horizontal pathways (the flat, double triangle) are thought to be exposed to the highest number of risk factors over time and the lowest number of protective factors over time. At birth, they also tend to have the highest number of risk factors (see the start-up risk panel) and the lowest number of protective factors (see the start-up protective factors). To clarify this cumulative, developmental model, Fig. 10 shows how it looks from the front, while Fig. 11 shows how it looks from underneath. Relevance of the Model for Assessments and Interventions What is the relevance of the cumulative, developmental model for assessment and the evaluation of preventive and remedial interventions? Assessments. Advances have been made in the past decades in the area of more precise assessment of juveniles’ problem behavior in terms of P P 3460 Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 9 The full model of developmental pathways as a function of the accumulation of risk and promotive factors (shown from above) Pathways to Delinquency Risk factor planes Start-up Risk factors Start-up Protective factors Pathways to Serious Delinquency Promotive factor planes Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 10 The full model of developmental pathways as a function of the accumulation of risk and promotive factors (shown from the front) the types of behavior, their severity, and prognostic validity. In addition, screening instruments are now available to go beyond the range of problem behaviors of juveniles that also include the past history of risk factors to which juveniles have been exposed. Based on the information provided in this entry, we argue however that assessments can probably benefit from two other components: (a) an appraisal of current and past protective factors to which juveniles are exposed, because it is the mixture of risk and protective effects that appears most crucial in determining the future risk of serious offending as well as the probability of full desistance or lower-level offending. We also argue that the next generation of risk assessment devices could potentially also benefit from (b) an appraisal of juveniles’ expected future exposure to risk and protective factors based on knowledge from longitudinal survey studies. Specifically, assessments of developmentally graded exposure to risk factors, based on longitudinal survey studies, could be employed to calculate the probability that juveniles will be exposed in the future to risk and protective factors typically emerging for that age-group. One might argue that cross-sectional studies contain such information. There are several reasons why this is not the case. Firstly, in contrast to cross-sectional studies, longitudinal studies have Pathways to Delinquency Pathways to Delinquency, Fig. 11 The full model of developmental pathways as a function of the accumulation of risk and promotive factors (shown from the bottom) the power to specify selection processes determining which groups of youth are most likely to be exposed to future risk and protective factors. The second reason has to do with protective factors associated with stable nonoffending or a deescalation from serious to minor or offendingnonoffending. Since juveniles’ engagement in delinquency varies from year to year, it is important to establish which protective factors are associated with persistent nonoffending or, alternatively, with a stable de-escalation in the severity of offending. Longitudinal studies, rather than cross-sectional studies, are the best methods by which to identify protective factors. Preventive and Remedial Interventions. We agree with Howell (2003) that a developmental approach to offending needs a reconceptualization of when interventions, preventive or remedial, can best take place. He has been a primary proponent of the influential Comprehensive Strategy that addresses the full continuum of antisocial development with two foci for implementing change: prevention and early intervention, and graduated sanctions. We believe that this orientation, which is based on knowledge of risk and protective factors (called protective factors in this case), can also greatly benefit from the assessment of future risk through developmentally graded expectations of exposure to risk and protective factors. We argue that this is especially important because of the fact that even 3461 P the most effective interventions still do not reduce the risk of recidivism by more than 40 % (Lipsey and Wilson 1998) and that the reoffending rate of high-risk populations of youth still remains extraordinary high (Loeber and Farrington 1998). It should be understood that knowledge of risk and protective factors (Loeber et al. 2006) does not mean that we have available the tools to change each of them, and of course some are not malleable (e.g., single parenthood). However, we hope that our list of the risk and protective factors and our model will stimulate the development of other forms of interventions that can augment the overall efficacy of interventions currently available. It is our impression that most treatment programs lack components that focus on increasing or strengthening protective factors. We foresee that interventions that mobilize or enhance protective factors (together with the reduction of risk factors) eventually are likely to improve treatment efficacy and, possibly, the maintenance of treatment effects. We agree, however, with Pollard et al. (1999) that a sole focus on interventions enhancing protective factors only, because of the compensatory function of risk and protective factors, is likely to be inadequate. Another possible beneficial result of our model specification is the further individualization of interventions tailored to an individual’s past, present, and possible future exposure to risk and protective factors. Finally, we should stress that our design of a three-dimensional model of antisocial behavior has certain limitations. Firstly, we are mostly focusing on the cumulative processes of risk and protective factors rather than the specifics of mediation and moderation within and between risk and protective factors. Also, we do not focus on possible reciprocal processes between risk and protective factors and negative or positive child behaviors, or the fact that as children’s mobility in the community increases with age, they become more able to select settings and situations in which novel risk and protective factors may present themselves. We are also aware that our model may have different components depending on the subject population of study P P 3462 (girls vs. boys, different ethnic groups), but we think it is generic enough to serve as a model to explain a range of forms of maladjustment other than serious delinquency. Moreover, the model depicts escalation in the severity of antisocial behavior better than de-escalation to lower severity levels, but de-escalation could perhaps be incorporated in the next iteration of the model. Also, there is a need to transfer the basic mathematical properties of our model into future model testing. It is clear that many tasks await, and we hope that this text will inspire others to improve on where we are at this point. Related Entries ▶ Age-Crime Curve ▶ Career Criminals and Criminological Theory ▶ Desistance from Crime ▶ Identification Issues in Life Course Criminology ▶ Longitudinal Studies in Criminology ▶ Optimizing Longitudinal Studies in Offending ▶ Risk Assessment, Classification, and Prediction Recommended Reading and References Catalano RF, Hawkins JD (1996) The social development model: a theory of antisocial behavior. In: Hawkins JD (ed) Delinquency and crime: current theories. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 149–197 Deater-Deckard K, Dodge KA, Bates JE, Pettit GS (1998) Multiple risk factors in the development of externalizing behavior problems: group and individual differences. Dev Psychopathol 10:469–493 Farrington DP (1997) Early prediction of violent and nonviolent youthful offending. Eur J Crim Policy Res 5:51–66 Farrington DP (2005) Integrated developmental and lifecourse theories of offending, vol 14, Advances in criminological theory. Transaction, New Brunswick Fergusson DM, Woodward LJ (2000) Educational, psychosocial, and sexual outcomes of girls with conduct problems in early adolescence. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 41:779–792 Gottfredson MR, Hirshi T (1990) A general theory of crime. Stanford University Press, Stanford Hawkins JD, Smith BH, Hill KG, Kosterman R, Catalano RF, Abbott RD (2003) Understanding and preventing Pathways to Delinquency crime and violence: findings from the Seattle social development project. In: Thornberry TP, Krohn MD (eds) Taking stock of delinquency: an overview of findings from contemporary longitudinal studies. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York, pp 255–312 Howell JC (2003) Preventing and reducing juvenile delinquency, a comprehensive framework. Sage Publications, Inc., Thousand Oaks Lahey BB, Moffitt TE, Caspi A (2003) Causes of conduct disorder and juvenile delinquency. Guilford, New York Le Blanc M (2002) The offending cycle, escalation and de-escalation in delinquent behavior: a challenge for criminology. Intern J Comp Appl Crim Justice 26:53–83 Lipsey MW, Wilson DB (1998) Effective intervention for serious juvenile offenders: a synthesis of research. In: Loeber R, Farrington DP (eds) Serious and violent juvenile offenders: risk factors and successful interventions. Sage Publications, Thousand Oaks, pp 313–346 Loeber R, Drinkwater M, Yin Y, Anderson SJ, Schmidt LC, Crawford A (2000) Stability of family interactions from ages 6 to 18. J Abnormal Child Psychol 28:353– 369 Loeber R, Farrington DP (1998) Serious and violent juvenile offenders: risk factors and successful interventions. Sage, Thousand Oaks Loeber R, Farrington DP, Stouthamer-Loeber M, White HR (2008) Violence and serious theft: development and prediction from childhood to adulthood. New York: Routledge Loeber R, Farrington DP (in press) Protective and risk factors pertaining to violence in four longitudinal studies. Am J Prev Med 43:S24–S27. Loeber R, Wikstro¨m PO (1993) Individual pathways to crime in different types of neighborhood. In: Farrington DP, Sampson RJ, Wikstro¨m PO (eds) Integrating individual and ecological aspects of crime. Liber Forlag, Stockholm, pp 169–204 Loeber R, Keenan K, Lahey BB, Green SM, Thomas C (1993) Evidence for developmentally based diagnoses of oppositional defiant disorder and conduct disorder. J Abnorm Child Psychol 21:377–410 Loeber R, Keenan K, Zhang Q (1997) Boys’ experimentation and persistence in developmental pathways toward serious delinquency. J Child Fam Stud 6:321–357 Loeber R, Wei E, Stouthamer-Loeber M, Huizinga D, Thornberry T (1999) Behavioral antecedents to serious and violent juvenile offending: joint analyses from the Denver youth survey, Pittsburgh youth study, and the Rochester development study. Stud Crime Crime Prev 8:245–263 Loeber R, Slot NW, Stouthamer-Loeber M (2006) A three-dimensional, cumulative developmental model of serious delinquency. In: Wikstro¨m POH, Sampson R (eds) The explanation of crime: contexts and mechanisms. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 153–194 Penal Abolitionism Loeber R, Farrington DP, Stallings R (2011) The Pittsburgh youth study. In: Loeber R, Farrington DP (eds) Young homicide offenders and victims. SpringerVerlag, New York, pp 19–36 Lo¨sel F, Bender D (2003) Protective factors and resilence. In: Farrington DP, Coid J (eds) Early prevention of adult anti-social behaviour. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Loeber R, Wung P, Keenan K, Giroux B, StouthamerLoeber M, Van Kammen WB, Maughan B (1993) Developmental pathways in disruptive child behavior. Dev Psychopathol 5:101–132 Moffitt TE (1993) Adolescence-limited and life-cyclepersistent antisocial behavior: a developmental taxonomy. Psychol Rev 100:674–701 Pollard JA, Hawkins JD, Arthur MW (1999) Risk and protection: are both necessary to understand diverse behavioral outcomes in adolescence? Soc Work Res 23:145–158 Sameroff AJ, Bartko WT, Baldwin A, Baldwin C, Seifer R (1998) Family and social influences on the development of child competence. In: Lewis M, Feiring C (eds) Families, risk, and competence. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, pp 161–185 Sampson RJ, Laub JH (1990) Crime and deviance over the life course: the salience of adult social bonds. Am Sociol Rev 55:609–627 Smith C, Lizotte AJ, Thornberry TP, Krohn MD (1995) Resilient youth: identifying factors that prevent high risk youth from engaging in delinquency and drug use. In: Hagan J (ed) Current perspectives on aging and the life cycle, vol 4, Delinquency and disrepute in the life course. JAI, Greenwich, pp 217–247 Stouthamer-Loeber M, Loeber R, Wei E, Farrington DP, Wikstro¨m PO (2002) Risk and protective effects in the explanation of persistent serious delinquency in boys. J Consult Clin Psychol 70:111–123 Stouthamer-Loeber M, Wei E, Loeber R, Masten AF (2004) Desistance from persistent serious delinquency in the transition to adulthood. Dev Psychopathol 16:897–918 Thornberry TP, Krohn MD (2003) Taking stock of delinquency: an overview of findings from contemporary longitudinal studies. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York Tolan PH, Gorman-Smith D, Loeber R (2000) Developmental timing of onsets of disruptive behaviors and later delinquency of inner-city youth. J Child Fam Stud 9:203–230 Warr M (2002) Companions in crime: the social aspects of criminal conduct. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK West DJ (1982) Delinquency: its roots, careers and prospects. Heinemann, London Wikstro¨m PO, Loeber R (2000) Do disadvantaged neighborhoods cause well-adjusted children to become adolescent delinquents? A study of male juvenile serious offending, risk and protective factors, and neighborhood context. Criminology 38:1109–1141 3463 P Patrol ▶ Preventive Patrol Patterns in Youthful Offending ▶ Specialization in Juvenile Offending Peer Effects ▶ Network Analysis in Criminology Penal Abolitionism Vincenzo Ruggiero School of Law, Middlesex University, London, UK Overview Abolitionism is not only a strategy or a set of demands aimed at the reduction (or suppression) of custody, it is also a perspective, a philosophy, an approach. Penal abolitionism challenges conventional definitions of crime and the law, while defying official views of the meanings and effects of punishment. This entry examines the origin, philosophy, and achievements of penal abolitionism, collecting and discussing the key arguments and views expressed by its leading proponents. It sets off with reference to Tocqueville’s view that prisoners lose their right to humanity and Foucault’s remarks, during his visit to Attica, about the “consumption and elimination” of the excluded enacted by prison institutions. It then discusses the degree to which the abolitionist stance can be deemed utopian and presents the classic arguments which constitute the components of that stance. Three areas are addressed: crime, the law, and punishment, namely, the key P P 3464 areas in which abolitionism elaborates its own philosophy while distancing itself from conventional sensibilities and, at the same time, responding to its mainstream critics. Introduction Abolitionism fights against the “curious mechanism of circular elimination” identified by Foucault during his visit to Attica, where he noted that society excludes certain specific types of its members, and by sending them to prison, it breaks them up, crushes them, physically eliminates them. Then The prison eliminates them by “freeing” them and sending them back to society; the state in which they come out insures that society will eliminate them once again, sending them to prison. Attica is a machine for elimination, a form of prodigious stomach, a kidney that consumes, destroys, breaks up and then rejects, and that consumes in order to eliminate what it has already eliminated. (Simon 1991, p. 27) Similarly, observing the American prison system, de Tocqueville (1956) noted that offenders released from custody remained among humans, but they lost their rights to humanity; people fled them as impure, and even those who believed in their innocence abandoned them. Once released, they could go in peace, with their live generously left to them, but a life worse than death. Against this strategy of elimination, the primary challenge for penal abolitionists is “to construct a political language and theoretical discourse that disarticulates crime from punishment” (Davis 2008, p. 3). However, such strategy is accompanied by alternative conceptualizations of crime, critical analyses of law, and radical thinking around the very nature, function and philosophy of punishment. According to one of the most representative figures of this multifaceted school of thought, abolitionism is a manifestation of the general human urge to do away with and to struggle against those phenomena or institutions of a social, political or religious nature that at a given time are considered to be unjust, wrong or unfair. (Bianchi 1991, p. 9) Penal Abolitionism The “general human urge” in the definition provided by Bianchi is the same urge that gave strength to the ancestors of contemporary abolitionists, namely, the women and men who fought against slavery, and later the campaigners who battled, and continue to do so, for the abolition of the death penalty. But the battle also continues on other fronts. Abolitionism posits that the criminal justice system as a whole constitutes a social problem in itself. Some forms of abolitionism, however, are already in place. Surely, there is an abolitionist stance in the proposition that the state-centralized administration of penal justice should be replaced by decentralized forms of autonomous conflict regulation. Echoes of abolitionism are also heard when critics warn that, if we want to reform the penal system, we have to start a process of collective conversion away from the traditional and conventional grammar that characterizes it. It should be reiterated, therefore, that abolitionism does not advocate the immediate suppression of all custodial institutions, a program which, on the other hand, would enjoy the support of many a critic who find the conditions of imprisonment all over the world shameful. Abolitionism t is not a “program,” but an approach, a perspective, a methodology, and most of all a way of seeing. By observing the concepts and the cultural matrix which give shape to abolitionism, one may discover that this school of thought sits very comfortably within Western popular culture, which guides the conduct of many and which many could mobilize to justify their conduct. Utopia? If the activist ancestors of abolitionism are the men and women who fought against slavery and the death penalty, their philosophical ancestors are harder to identify with precision. But let us start with a general, preliminary characterization. Abolitionism, I would submit, is grounded in a variety of social philosophies which are primarily concerned with discussing processes of social development that can be viewed as pathological or as “misdevelopments” (Honneth 2007). Penal Abolitionism Among these philosophies are those expressing the view that societies should support a rich plurality of activities, each valuable in its own right, and that each person should be treated as an end, not as a mere means to the ends of others. This Aristotelian view would deny “that a society can be flourishing as a whole when some members are doing extremely badly” (Nussbaum 2000, p. 106). There is nothing utopian in attempts to redress “remediable injustices”: abolitionists do not pursue perfect justice, rather, they aim at enhancing justice. Their focus on social interactions rather than institutions, on precise settings in which people live rather than official norms and extraneous professionals, locates them in a specific political and philosophical tradition. According to a distinction suggested by Amartya Sen (2009), there are contractarian approaches and comparative approaches to the idea of justice. The former establish general, universal, principles of justice and are concerned with setting up “just institutions.” For such institutions to function, total compliance of people’s behavior is required. The latter assess the different ways in which people lead their lives, actually behave and interact. A contractarian approach is described by Sen as “transcendental institutionalism,” in that it searches for the ideal institutions capable of forging a perfectly just society. By contrast, a comparative approach is led by the search for social arrangements that satisfy people in their concrete collective life. When people across the world agitate for more global justice – and I emphasise here the comparative word “more” – they are not clamouring for some kind of “minimal humanitarianism”. Nor are they agitating for a “perfectly just” world society, but merely for the elimination of some outrageously unjust arrangements to enhance global justice. (Sen 2009, p. 26) Comparison entails information, which in turn presupposes proximity to the actors involved in the process of forging ideas of justice. Abolitionists propend for this type of approach. Some forms of human suffering may be unavoidable, and perhaps cannot be remedied in some particular place or at some particular time. Correspondingly, however, there are forms of 3465 P suffering that are needless at particular times and places. According to Gouldner (1975), it is the sociologist’s job to give special attention to the latter. Penal suffering is avoidable, particularly if its ineffectiveness can be proven, and the prisoners’ standpoint deserves to be heard not because they have any special virtue and not because they alone live in a world of suffering. A sociology of the underdog is justified because, and to the extent that, his suffering is less likely to be known and because – by the very reason of his being underdog – the extent and character of his suffering are likely to contain much that is avoidable. (Gouldner 1975, p. 37) Similarly, Nils Christie often reminds us that all he wants to do is to reduce the amount of suffering in the world: “I have never known someone who wants to increase it” (personal communication). Christie may have been particularly fortunate in his encounters, but his views and those of other abolitionists sit comfortably with a variety of insights found in sociology, politics, and philosophy. Problematic Acts Are crimes exceptional events? Louk Hulsman’s reply to this rhetorical question takes the form of an excursus into the criminal justice system as a “special” set of procedures addressed to a “not so special” category of individuals. We are accustomed, he argues, to regarding the criminal justice system as a rational apparatus specifically devised to respond to crime and to control or neutralize its effects. We are also accustomed to interpreting crimes as exceptional events, “events which differ to an important extent from other events which are not defined as criminal” (Hulsman 1986, p. 63). In conventional perceptions, criminal conduct is at odds with the average conduct in that it deviates from the type of interactions supposedly established by the majority. Such deviation, statistically exceptional, is thus deemed to trigger the special responses offered by official institutions: special events justify the special nature of the reaction against them. P P 3466 According to abolitionist analysis, conducts classified as criminal are only a small proportion of a variety of similar conducts which escape criminalization. On the one hand, therefore, only certain types of events are selected as specific, undeniable, self-evident, representatives of what we understand as crime. On the other hand, the events selected are brought together in a discreet category, as if they constituted a homogenous group of conducts. “Within the concept of criminality a broad range of situations are linked together. Most of these, however, have separate properties and no common denominator” (Hulsman 1986, p. 65). What do violence within the family and street violence have in common? Do shoplifting, drug selling, and armed robbery belong to the same rubric of behavior? What makes dangerous driving similar to fencing? And political violence to pollution? Neither the motivation of those involved nor the techniques required, let alone the consequences of those specific conducts, displays a precise set of common components. If we are led to analyze them by referring such conducts to a common logical and moral framework, it is because the framework we adopt is inspired by the criminal justice system: “All these events have in common is that the criminal justice system is authorised to take action against them” (Hulsman 1986, p. 65). This is not denying that human interactions may cause considerable degrees of suffering to those involved: abolitionism would only question why some types of suffering mobilize the intervention of institutional agencies while others do not. Moreover, in an imaginary scale of personal hardship, the distress caused by some interactions of a criminal nature would not score particularly high when compared to those of a quotidian, apparently prosaic, nature. “Matrimonial difficulties, difficulties between parents and children, serious difficulties at work and housing problems will, as a rule, be experienced as more serious.” In brief, there is nothing that intrinsically distinguishes, for those directly involved, criminal events from a variety of other unpleasant events. Most episodes causing hardship are normally dealt with informally by the individuals affected, at times with the mediatory Penal Abolitionism participation of people or groups belonging to the community in which such episodes occur. Many conducts that generate serious harm do not elicit responses from the criminal justice system, while those involved in problematic situations mostly attempt to find solutions within the context in which they arise: the family, the group of friends or neighbors, and the work place. All this means, Hulsman concludes, “that there is no ‘ontological reality’ of crime” (Hulsman 1986, p. 66). Some examples may provide support to this conclusion. A murder occurs in a town inhabited by some 300,000 people, and the alleged murderer is a university lecturer. A few days earlier, the lecturer had delivered a public speech and no one in the audience noticed anything unusual in the speech and in the speaker. The event is incomprehensible and the investigators feel the necessity to entrust a team of psychiatrists with the explanation of the mystery. Let us now imagine another murder occurring 200 years before in a small town. If we had lived in that small town at that time, we would probably have found it ridiculous to call in an expert of the mind to explain why the killer had killed. Ridiculous because we all knew why he killed. After all, we would not have been surprised, and we would have agreed among friends that this was exactly what we all might have expected all along, (Nils Christie, personal communication) The difference between the experience and perception of the two murders resides in the nature and amount of information the residents share about one another. So many people live in a middle-sized modern town that it is impossible to know them all. In addition, life is organized in ways that only allow us to hold a superficial or segmented knowledge of other beings. We have a narrow basis for predicting behavior outside the specific group to which we belong. Another example comes from the Norwegian valleys, where the traditional institutional figure of the lensmann is still operative. A local sheriff of sort, the lensmann performs a variety of civil tasks and his/her ability to function is dependent upon the support received by fellow citizens. The lensmann may direct auctions, help mothers get money from absent fathers, and deal with crime. When Christie interviewed one such institutional Penal Abolitionism figure, he was told that there was no crime in the district. But during the course of the interview, several things happened that testified to the contrary. The telephone rang, a lady had lost her purse: the lensmann asked his assistant to drive down to the close-by cafe´; the purse was found and brought back to the lady. So was the young man who was using the purse. He happened to be the lady’s son. A report came in on breaking and entering into a store of weapons. The lensmann jumped into his car, drove far up into the mountains in the direction of the store, met a car high up there, stopped the car, found Ole drunk as usual, with a carload of guns he had stolen just to irritate his farther. He brought Ole home and took the guns to a safer depot. What a cliff-hanger story lost for the massmedia! Helicopters and anti-terrorist police might have been engaged in the crime-hunt of the century. Now, it was Ole. An old story of misery and family quarrels. (Christie 1982, pp. 73–74) These cases and the one following show that definitions of crime are based on “ignorance” or lack of familiarity with the events at hand. A man administers some drugs to his wife and causes her death by suffocation. He then writes to the police, saying that he has committed murder and that he is going to drown himself. The letter reaches the police 2 days after the man’s suicide. The flat where the coupled lived is visited by the officers, who find the dead woman. She had Alzheimer’s and, before killing her, the man had looked after her with deep love. “To some this is a story of Romeo and Juliet. To others, it is one of plain murder” (Christie 2004, p. 1). From numerous stories and situations such as this, abolitionists derive the argument that crime is a shallow concept, too imprecise to allow the subtle distinctions and understandings we need. The alternative concept of “trouble” may be a better starting point, trouble being something which is widely experienced and simultaneously caused by people interacting. Moreover, trouble requires responses, solutions, lest it causes harm and suffering. “The danger is too hastily to define troubles as crime.” The next step is, therefore, to examine in detail which acts are beneficial and which harmful. Then follows an analysis of these acts perceived as bad – a classificatory scheme with categories as irritation, unpleasantness, disgust, sin - and then, 3467 P but only as one among so many alternatives – crime. When crime is the last concept in the line, it is easier to raise the analytical question: What are the social conditions for acts to be designated as crimes? Crime does not exist. Only acts exist, acts often given different meanings within various social frameworks. (Christie 2004, pp. 2–3) Let us take a final example of how social frameworks determine the meaning of acts. A man carrying a bag-load of beer cans arrives in a park. He starts drinking one can after the other, and because he acts “funny,” he attracts the attention of the children playing nearby who surround him and enjoy the show. Suddenly, the man goes behind a bush with the intention of relieving himself and the children, who are carried away by the entertaining situation, follow him. It is summer, and many people are enjoying the sun from their windows or balconies in two adjacent blocks of flats. Christie names the two buildings as, respectively, The House of Perfection and The House of Turbulence. The former was built by an efficient and reliable company, the tenants moved in smoothly, on the agreed day, and to their satisfaction they found everything they expected perfectly in place. The latter was built by a company that went bankrupt, causing delays and distress among buyers, who organized themselves with the aim of claiming some form of compensation. The inhabitants of The House of Turbulence, in other words, knew each other fairly well, had experienced some form of collective action, and identified some common understanding of their needs. Now, a situation in which a man relieving himself while surrounded by children lends itself to highly different interpretations. For the inhabitants of the House of Turbulence, the case was clear. The man is Peter, son of Anna. He had an accident when he was little, behaves generally a bit strangely, but is as kind as the midsummer night is long. When he drinks too much, it is just to phone his family and someone comes to take him home. (Christie 2004, p. 5) On the contrary, in The House of Perfection nobody knows Peter: he is just a man urinating in front of children. The police must be called, because this is a case of indecent exposure. In Christie’s analysis, the inhabitants of this house P P 3468 never had a chance to get to know each other, nor were they ever forced to establish forms of cooperation with their neighbors. In conclusion, a “limited amount of knowledge inside a social system opens the possibility of giving an act the meaning of crime.” (Christie 2004, p. 5). Substantial Law Moving on to the abolitionist analysis of the law, it is necessary to start from a general, conventional premise. Juridical equality may be described as everybody’s right to mobilize state institutions for the protection and safeguard of their wellbeing. In this perspective, it is, therefore, the right to mutual coercion. Disrespect for the liberty of others amounts to the denial of their freedom. The state intervenes to deny that denial and restore the initial situation. Coercion is therefore legitimate in that it denies an act which has denied the freedom of others. Abolitionists would retort that such arguments might only be suitable for societies in which equal access to the law is complemented with equal access to resources. Their critique of the law and the criminal justice system is addressed to the iniquitous societies in which we live, while critical responses are also provided to other key assumptions, namely, that the law addresses individual rather than collective actors, and that liability and non-liability can be scientifically assessed. Institutional intervention into problematic situations aims to obliterate an ethics of shared responsibility for conduct while affirming an ethics of individual responsibility. In this way, institutions can establish their monopoly over the power to punish or pardon, namely, their right to destroy or “repair” the individual responsible. The weakening of any networks contesting this right, be they neighborhood, religious, political, or cultural aggregations of people claiming their own right to deal with problematic situations and responsibility, is crucial for that monopoly to be accomplished. When the official power to punish or pardon solidifies, penal sanctions as chief characteristics of the criminal law emerge. Penal Abolitionism It is only then that crime – as defined by the state itself – becomes possible. It is only then that the continuity of crime in some form becomes fundamental to the very existence of the state. And this form is determined by what the state chooses to sanction penally. (Kennedy 1976, p. 63) The abolitionist stance, here, echoes some aspects of conflict theory. Conflict theorists propose that law in the books and law in action favor the interests of special groups, and that, therefore, rather than being concerned with the explanation of crime, theory should engage in explaining the function of criminal law (Vold 1958; Chambliss 1969, 1975; Turk 1969; Quinney 1974; Akers 1997). Similarly, abolitionists do not ask why some people commit crime, but rather why some acts are defined as criminal? As succinctly stated by Quinney (1970, p. 18): “criminal definitions describe behaviour that conflicts with the interests of the segments of society that have the power to shape public policy.” From another, though adjacent, perspective, the criminal law itself is described as devoid of rationality and replete with conflicting principles, as its central features derive from struggles taking place in previous epochs. Such features took shape amid social and political conflicts and, inevitably, bear the mark of previous historical events: “The central principles of the law are the site of struggle and contradiction. . . The fate of law as a rationalising enterprise is tied up with the nature of law as a social, historical force” (Norrie 1993, p. 9). Elements of Marxist analysis are detectable in these formulations, and in general in all conceptions of law as expression of group conflicts. The law, according to Marx, allows states to deal with “social imperfections” as if they were “evil dispositions of the poor” rather than products of specific economic and political arrangements. Marx, however, defines the law as the form in which the individuals of a certain ruling class assert their common interests. Abolitionist analysis, however, develops some central tenets of conflict theory in an original manner. Where conflict theorists seem to limit themselves to the critique of the criminal justice system as an expression of antagonistic values and interests operating from above, abolitionists Penal Abolitionism reappropriate the very notion of “conflict” and turn it into a critical tool to be utilized from below. Nils Christie (1977, p. 1), for instance, remarks that conflicts are hijacked by the criminal justice system and that criminology lends a helpful hand in the process: “conflicts have been taken away from the parties directly involved and thereby have either disappeared or become other people’s property.” Law specialists are not the only ones to “steal” conflicts; conflict theorists in criminology, in effect, do the same, though in a different fashion: they turn interpersonal conflicts into class conflicts, thus again taking them away from those directly involved. Comparing two opposite scenes, an adjudication case in a small village in Tanzania and a case dealt with in a juvenile court in England, Christie provides the following description. In the former, the contending parties, a man and a woman, occupy the center of the judicial scene, they make their claims, while their respective friends and relatives take part without “taking over,” and the audience intervenes with questions, information, and jokes. In the latter, the predominance of professionals is visible, while the young defendant appears to be confused by those surrounding him, whose role he does not understand and who do not take any notice of him. “The truth is that, for the most part, the business of the criminal courts is dull, commonplace, ordinary and after a while downright tedious” (Christie 1977, p. 2). Christie (1998, p. 19) provides two pictures of how rules are created. In the first, Moses descends from the mountains carrying the rules engraved in granite. “Moses was only a messenger, the people – the populus – were the receivers, controlled from far above.” The other picture sees a group of women gathering at the fountain, around the well, or along a river, who while fetching water exchange information and evaluations. The point of departure of their conversation will often be concrete acts and situations. These are described, compared to similar occurrences in the past or somewhere else, and evaluated – right or wrong, beautiful or ugly, strong or weak. Slowly, some common understanding of the occurrences might emerge. This is a process whereby norms are created. It is a classical case of horizontal or equalitarian justice. (Christie 1998, p. 119) 3469 P The act whereby conflicts are hijacked by professionals entails a specific construction of reality hinging on an incident, narrowly defined in time and space, whereby the individual is separated from the context in which the action takes place. According to the abolitionist critique of legal professionalism, those who act, in this way, are isolated from the very incident involving them, from the environment in which it occurs, from their “friends, family, and the material substratum of their life world” (Hulsman 1991, p. 23). Also, they become separated from those people who, in that specific situation, feel victimized by certain acts. Hulsman focuses on the culture and the organizational make up that extrude people from their social context and artificially sets them against one another: “In this sense the cultural organisation of criminal justice creates ‘fictitious individuals’, and a ‘fictitious’ interaction between them” (Hulsman 1991). The core function of such an organization is the apportioning of blame, whereby events are assembled and sanctions catalogued on the basis of seriousness and gravity, respectively. A hierarchy is, therefore, postulated and patterns of acts and institutional responses to them are artificially established. Events, in their turn, are chosen among a limited range of conducts and interactions, namely, those which the criminal justice organization feels more comfortable in explaining and evaluating. “No comparison is made with events and behaviours outside that range.” Patterns and hierarchies are drawn in a universe which is far removed from the context in which events took place, so that what appears to be consistent within the criminal justice profession is experienced as inconsistent by those who constitute the objects of that profession. Hulsman remarks, in this respect, that “values and perceptions in society are not uniform.” And in this way he echoes conflict theorists such as Sellin (1939), who emphasizes “culture conflicts,” that is the differences between social groups, their aspirations and behavioral models, leading to acts defined as crime. But he adds that the “program” for blame allocation typifying the criminal justice system is a true copy of the doctrines of “the last judgment” and “purgatory” P P 3470 developed in certain varieties of Western Christian theology. The criminal justice system, in his view, maintains the features of “centrality and totalitarianism which belong to those theological doctrines. Naturally, those origins – this ‘old’ rationality – are hidden behind new words: ‘God’ is replaced by the ‘law’ and the consensus of the people” (Hulsman 1991, p. 24). The notions of separateness and isolation, applied by abolitionism to the offender, the victim, and the problematic situation characterizing their interaction, are also mobilized by conflict theorists, when their analyses focus on the law as the realm of individualist philosophies and as the reflection of egoistic interest. Abolitionism enriches this approach with detailed descriptions of contexts and events, suggesting that these are subjected to a process of abstraction or outright obliteration. It is the very cultural organization of the criminal law that fosters this process, a process whose “frame of reference,” as Hulsman terms it, gives no room “for active participation and guidance for the parties involved.” When the police operate within a criminal justice frame they tend not to be directed by the wishes and desires of the complainant, but by the requirements of the legal procedure which they are preparing. The complainant becomes a guide for their activities as “witness”. A witness is mainly a tool to bring legal proceedings to a successful end. In a comparable way the frame of court proceedings precludes – or makes it anyway specially difficult – for the victims to express freely their view on the situation or to enter in an interaction with the person who is standing as a supposed offender before the court. (Hulsman 1991, p. 24) If classical conflict theory would mainly examine structures and agencies while omitting to look in any detail into their specific social composition, abolitionism devotes particular attention to such composition, particularly to the increasing separate specialization characterizing it. In brief, it is argued that each institutional agency develops its own criteria for action, its own ideology and culture which may lead it to collide with other agencies. Agencies are bureaucracies pursuing internal goals, such as expand, attenuate internal problems, monitor the wellbeing of their members, and ultimately Penal Abolitionism ensure their own survival. “The process of bureaucratisation and professionalisation within the criminal justice system makes it a soulless machinery” (Hulsman 1982, pp. 56–57). Limits to Pain Among the most critical traits characterizing abolitionist theories and practices are those concerned with the nature, function, and philosophy of punishment. The infliction of punishment might be justified if it contributed to the maximization of happiness rather than the maximization of pain. Hence the need for any theorizing on punishment to consider its social consequences. Those who defend institutional coercion in the form of punishment may advocate rehabilitative treatment, may value its general or individual deterrent effect or its function of incapacitation aimed at prolific offenders. Abolitionists argue against such philosophies and their practical outcomes. In Mathiesen’s (1990) view, by contrast, prison has no defense whatsoever, particularly when inspired by penal retribution, whereby offenses are said to possess a “punishment value” that can be translated into a specific amount of “time.” Mathiesen argues that time is only measurable subjectively, and that the perception of its entity depends on one’s proximity to those serving a prison sentence. After crossing almost four centuries, Mathiesen (1990, p. 33) identifies four major components in the rehabilitative ideology which have been remarkably constant through time. “Work, school, morality and discipline have run through the centuries as main pillars of thinking.” While the emphasis may constantly shift from one to the other component, rehabilitation itself, understood as “return to competence” is rarely achieved. Evidence of this failure is found by Mathiesen in a variety of studies grouped in three main areas. First, he refers to prison treatment studies, which yield largely uniform findings: the effects of treatment, in terms of preventing recidivism, and regardless of strategy or intensity, are generally poor. He then considers the notion of treatment in relation to the actual Penal Abolitionism environment in which it is expected to be carried out. The organization of prison life, the authoritarian principles governing it, along with the bureaucratic arrangement stifling creative projects, provide a setting which is conducive to everything but treatment. Moreover, prisons are usually “overcrowded, run-down, and more or less dangerous places to those who inhabit them,” and if anything, they exacerbate the conducts of those they purport to treat (Mathiesen 1990, p. 41). Finally, he looks at a range of studies devoted to prison as a social organization or focused on prisoners’ communities, arguing that inmates become soon “prisonized,” that is they internalize the values and rules of a violent and coercive environment and adopt a culture which is impervious to change (Clemmer 1940). Such culture, which protects the inmates from the very setting that they inhabit, makes prison perform the function of a crime school, and prisoners more or less immune to treatment or readjustment programs. Moving on to the discussion of deterrence as general prevention, Mathiesen (1990) suggests that the failure of this alleged function of imprisonment should prompt a dramatic reduction of the use of imprisonment as a whole. Research into the actual effectiveness of general prevention is so inconclusive that, when seen against the harmful outcomes of custodial punishment, it would be wise to limit the use of custody altogether, until its effectiveness is soundly proven. General deterrence consists of a message addressed to the general population, but it would appear that something goes horrendously wrong in the communicating process: “general prevention functions in relation to those who do not ‘need’ it. In relation to those who ‘need’ it, it does not function” (Mathiesen 1990, p. 69). It is for moral reasons, therefore, and due to lacking evidence of the actual working of general deterrence, that the use of imprisonment should be reduced to a minimum. There is, however, a supplementary argument that would strengthen Mathiesen’s reductionist stance, namely, that deterrence makes no difference between guilty and innocent individuals, in the sense that if non-offenders were punished its goal would still 3471 P be achieved. By punishing people at random, irrespective of whether or not they have committed crimes, one may well assume that the general population is discouraged from violating the law. But, although acceptable from a utilitarian perspective, punishing the innocent would run counter the Kantian moral principle whereby individuals must not be treated as mere instruments for the achievement of a social good: all individuals should be treated as ends in themselves, in accord with their dignity and worth as persons. Considering how ideas of general deterrence have increasingly replaced notions of treatment, Christie (1982, p. 29) notes that at least the latter “had a formally clear target: those receiving treatment.” The former, instead, chooses as a target a vague entity described as the general population, which is composed of people who, if deterred from one type of offense may resort to another type; people who, in the face of a punitive message launched in one country, may decide to move to another country; or finally, people who might find it hard to receive the punitive message altogether. “Conceptually, as well as empirically, ideas of general prevention or deterrence are thus more cumbersome to handle than ideas of treatment” (Christie 1982, p. 29). As for individual deterrence, the belief that imprisonment amounts to a form of training for criminal activities to come is persuasive enough, in the abolitionist view, to discard this specific official function of prison as inappropriate. Schools of crime teach resentment and hostility rather than respect for norms and others. In addition, it could be stressed that deterrent effects are notoriously difficult to establish, “since they involve counterfactuals: would these individuals have acted differently had the threat of criminal penalties been other than it was?” (Duff and Garland 1994, p. 25). The history of punishment may be interpreted as an evolutionary process leading to distinct stages characterized by increasing leniency. Some commentators may describe the development occurring as one bringing a gradual decrease in pain, a progressive shift from brutality to sweetness. Of course, there is difference P P 3472 between gruesome public executions and incarceration, between suffocating reclusion and custody in a single room, with cold and hot water and a TV set. But does this indicate an objective reduction of the pain caused by imprisonment? I just do not know. Each form would have to be evaluated according to its own time, by those receiving the pain, in the framework of their usual life and other people’s life, and in the light of what they saw as their sins. I do not see how a scale could be established. (Christie 1982, p. 9) Law texts establish when punishments have to be inflicted, while judges decide how long they should last; neither examines their effects on bodies and minds, the suffering produced, how it feels. The belief in slow progressive humanization accounts for the lack of this type of information (Hulsman 1986). Criticizing the humanization thesis, Hulsman (1986) notes that the overall amount of punishment does not tend to decline, as the number of convicted people per 100,000 of population shows a strong cyclic movement. The trend of convictions, in many countries in the industrialized world, has in fact for some time moved upward. Hulsman finds the assessment of the qualitative aspects of punishment more difficult. It is true that the application of the death penalty has been greatly reduced in recent centuries, and in normal times has been abolished in many countries. The same can be said, he adds, of many forms of corporal punishment. It may also be true that some progress has been made in improving the regime in prison systems. He, nevertheless, suggests caution when judging qualitative amelioration and humanization. The amount of suffering incorporated in legal penalties cannot be measured on a scale of absolute values. “To a large extent it consists of the difference between the normal living situation of people and that which is created by the intervention of the criminal justice system.” Hulsman is alluding to the concept of less-eligibility whereby the conditions in prison must be worse than the worst social condition of people in liberty. Because the prison system “has always drawn its clientele mainly from the most disadvantaged sections of the population,” conditions in prison will reflect the Penal Abolitionism lowest standard of living experienced by this social sector. Now, as “the living standards of those same sections have in Europe improved considerably in recent years,” one may presume that prison conditions have improved accordingly, but the reality is that “improvement inside prisons during the last 30 years do not appear to have kept pace.” The conclusion is that “if this supposition is correct, then the degree of suffering from the penal sanction has in a sense increased” (Hulsman 1986, pp. 64–65). The “evolution” of pain, moreover, is alleged to have rendered physical punishment obsolete, which is far from reality. Prison still entails forms of corporal affliction: it degrades the body, it deprives of air and light, it imposes humiliating sanitary conditions, it causes diseases, and it produces sterile suffering. Not all suffering is bad; some is beneficial, in that it makes our consciousness develop while opening up new existential paths, making us better humans and getting us closer to the others. Imprisonment is a type of suffering that does not create anything, that does not generate any meaning. (Hulsman 1982, p. 59) There are, finally, problems caused by institutional intervention per se: custodial and non-custodial measures alike erect. obstacles to the development of social solidarity and respect for differences that manifest themselves in “lived life”. . . Rather than alternatives to custody we should devise alternative approaches by which information is collected about the needs of those involved in problematic situations. (Hulsman 1982) Intellectual Biographies As remarked above, abolitionism does not possess one single theoretical or political source of inspiration, but a composite backdrop from which, wittingly or otherwise, it draws its arguments and proposals for action (Ruggiero 2010, 2011). The intellectual biography of Louk Hulsman, for example, should be related to some crucial passages in the Bible where mercy is advocated while judgment and retribution are rejected. The Gospels of Mark, Luke, and Paul Penal Abolitionism seem to provide an apposite theological underpinning for Hulsman’s abolitionism, which can also be assimilated to Saint Francis’ ecumenism and his view that thieves are not those who steal, but those who do not give enough to the needy. Radical theology or the theology of liberation also provide significant sources of inspiration. With Bakunin’s anarchism, Hulsman shares the belief that the realization of freedom requires that political action be conducted religiously. In some pages of Marx, Engels, Tolstoy, and Hugo an echo is felt of Hulsman’s concepts of redemption of punishment, self-government, mercy, and pietas. Hulsman’s system of thought, in brief, is shown to display a high degree of syncretism. An equal if not a higher degree of syncretism shows the intellectual trajectory of Thomas Mathiesen, whose materialist approach is punctuated by arguments for a pluralistic, interdisciplinary, sociology of law. The writings of Marx and Engels constitute an ideal background for an understanding of Mathiesen’s work, which on the other hand draws on a number of other theoretical sources. The focus on offenders and prisons, and on social movements traditionally excluded from orthodox notions of class struggle, makes Mathiesen’s stance an implicit critique of classical Marxism. What constitutes the originality of Mathiesen’s work is the coalescence of research, action, and theorizing that characterizes his entire career, as an academic as well as an activist. Action is inherent in the research method adopted, and those researched are the prime subjects involved in research as well as in action. His radical analysis, therefore, is a tool which constantly translates knowledge about conflict into collective praxis for those producing it. In his work, Nils Christie stands in favor of simplicity and intelligibility. He says that when we write we should keep our favorite aunt in mind, like Kropotkin said that anarchist literature had to keep in mind the workers to whom it was addressed. Christie’s system of thought echoes anarchist theories of law and authority. His critique of legal professionalism is akin to libertarian arguments against the proliferation of laws, while his appreciation of conflict as a resource 3473 P brings to mind the anarchist idea that problems within communities can only been resolved if those involved possess sufficient autonomous resources to do so. One of Christie’s arguments is that communities and groups, irrespective of their dimension, may find abolitionist experimentation possible only if the interactions within them are highly frequent and intense. In this sense, he expresses the purest of anarchist notions, namely, that a better social life is experienced when communities develop social feelings and, particularly, a collective sense of justice that grows until it becomes a habit. Conclusion On the nature and concept of crime abolitionism engages in a debate that our ancestors Plato, Aristotle, and Spinoza saw as the distinction between good and evil. Far from exhausted, such debate continues in an array of disciplines ranging from theology to psychology, from political philosophy to social theory. The abolitionist critique of the law contains some Kantian moral principles, in that existing law is seen as using people as an instrument, a chance to signal the strength of transcendental and worldly authority. Abolitionists hold the view that the law performs a transferral of vendetta from the sacred into the judicial system of the state, and that it is mainly addressed to scapegoats, chosen violators among many, who are at the same time “evil” and “sacred,” in that they reproduce social life through sacrifice. In abolitionist analysis, issues such as the designation of what constitutes crime, the intervention of the law, and the infliction of penalties that take place in institutional settings, which are distant from the situations, are addressed. Within such settings, punishment is the outcome of a cognitive process whereby the institutions make sense of events and claim that their response is based on the knowledge of such events. Abolitionists, instead, claim that knowledge is mainly achieved within precise contexts in which problematic situations arise, and it is for those involved to “repair” such situations through the development of restorative collective capabilities. P P 3474 Related Entries ▶ Juvenile Diversion ▶ Monitoring and Evaluation of Restorative Justice ▶ Restorative Justice ▶ Restorative Justice and Practice Recommended Reading and References Akers RL (1997) Criminological theories: introduction and evaluation. Roxbury Publishing Company, Los Angeles Bianchi H (1991) Abolitionism in the past, present and future. In: Lasocik Z, Platek M, Rzeplinska I (eds) Abolitionism in history: on another way of thinking. Institute of Social Prevention and Resocialisation, University of Warsaw, Warsaw Chambliss W (1969) Crime and the legal process. McGraw-Hill, New York Chambliss W (1975) Criminal law in action. Hamilton, Santa Barbara Christie N (1977) Conflicts as property. Br J Criminol 17:1–15 Christie N (1982) Limits to pain. Martin Robertson, Oxford Christie N (1998) Between civility and state. In: Ruggiero V, South N, Taylor I (eds) The new European criminology: crime and social order in Europe. Routledge, London Christie N (2004) A suitable amount of crime. Routledge, London/New York Clemmer D (1940) The prison community. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York Davis AY (2008) History is a weapon. The challenge of prison abolition: a conversation between Angela Y. Davis and Dylan Rodriguez. http://www. historyasweapon.com/defcon/davisinterview.html de Tocqueville A (1956) Democracy in America. Mentor Books, New York Duff RA, Garland D (eds) (1994) A reader on punishment. Oxford University Press, Oxford Gouldner AW (1975) For sociology: renewal and critique in sociology today. Penguin, Harmondsworth Honneth A (2007) Disrespect: the normative foundations of critical theory. Polity, Cambridge Hulsman L (1982) Peines perdues: le syste`me pe´nal en question. Le Centurion, Paris (interview with J. Bernat de Ce´lis) Hulsman L (1986) Critical criminology and the concept of crime. Contemp Crises 10(1):63–80 Hulsman L (1991) Alternatives to criminal justice: decriminalization and depenalization. In: Lasocik Z, Platek M, Rzeplinska I (eds) Abolitionism in history: on another way of thinking. Institute of Social Prevention and Resocialization, Warsaw Penal Justice and Social Injustice Kennedy MC (1976) Beyond incrimination: some neglected facets of the theory of punishment. In: Chambliss W, Mankoff M (eds) Whose law? What order? A conflict approach to criminology. Wiley, New York Mathiesen T (1990) Prison on trial. Sage, London Norrie A (1993) Crime, reason and history: a critical introduction to criminal law. Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London Nussbaum M (2000) Women and human development: the capabilities approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Quinney R (1970) The social reality of crime. Little, Brown, Boston Quinney R (1974) Critique of the legal order. Little, Brown, Boston Ruggiero V (2010) Penal abolitionism. Oxford University Press, Oxford Ruggiero V (2011) An abolitionist view of restorative Justice. Int J Law Crime Justice 39(2):100–110 Sellin T (1939) Culture, conflict and crime. Social Science Research Council, New York Sen A (2009) The idea of justice. Allen Lane, London Simon JK (1991) Michel Foucault on Attica: an interview. Soc Justice 18(3):23–37 Turk A (1969) Criminality and the legal order. Rand-McNally, Chicago Vold GB (1958) Theoretical criminology. Oxford University Press, New York Penal Justice and Social Injustice Matt Matravers Morrell Centre for Toleration, University of York, York, UK Overview The connections between retributive justice, broadly conceived, and distributive or social (in) justice have long troubled criminologists, moral and legal philosophers, and criminal justice practitioners. One reason for this is that the economically deprived make up a disproportionate number of criminal offenders (and victims), a fact made even more striking in many places when overlaid with statistics about race. Another is that inequalities within liberal democratic societies have risen since the 1970s; dramatically in some places such the USA and UK. This rise has accompanied a dramatic rise in punishment and Penal Justice and Social Injustice incarceration. Assuming inequality is a proxy for distributive injustice, then, the world is becoming less just and, in some places, more punitive. These facts compel our attention in (at least) two ways. First, there is a practical public policy question. If crime rates are correlated to poverty and/or inequality, then one way to address crime is through social justice and the redistribution of income, wealth, and opportunities. This is no doubt sensible, but it is not the subject of discussion here. Rather, second, juxtaposing criminal and distributive justice brings into focus a normative question of whether social justice is a precondition of legitimate criminal justice, or more minimally, whether – and if so in what ways – social injustice renders the imposition of criminal liability and sanctions morally problematic. It is this normative issue that is discussed below. Certainly, some philosophers concerned with the justification of punishment have held that conditions of social injustice – such as those prevalent in much of the developed world – render punishment at best problematic and at worst morally impermissible. Thus, Antony Duff (1986, p. 294) argues that punishment “will not be justifiable unless and until we have brought about deep and far-reaching social, political, legal, and moral changes in ourselves and our society”. Similarly, Jeffrie Murphy (1973) claims that existing social injustice fatally undermines the only successful theory through which punishment can be made permissible. And David Bazelon (1976, p. 385) that “there can be no truly just criminal law in the absence of social justice.” This entry will consider the arguments for the proposition that social injustice renders the imposition of criminal liability and sanctions morally problematic. It does not deal with the question of whether lesser punishments are merited by those who are disadvantaged by injustice, but rather with the moral legitimacy of punishment as a whole in circumstances of distributive injustice. The first set of arguments focuses on theories of punishment; the second on the responsibility of the offender; the third on whether an unjust society has the standing to call offenders to account. 3475 P In all cases, it is assumed that the background is one in which the law is not egregiously unjust. That is, the discussion does not encompass societies in which, for example, the law formally discriminates against non-white persons with respect to political and property rights. Such societies clearly raise issues about whether obedience is owed by those against whom discrimination is practiced and about the moral and legal liability of those who break the law. However, the assumption here is that the system has no such formal rules, but that the social and economic distribution of goods is unequal and unjust (which will have implications for the value of the formal rights enjoyed by all). In short, the focus is on societies such as the USA and UK, not on those such as South Africa in the era of Apartheid. Ideal Theories and Actual Practices There are many theories that purport to justify or render permissible state punishment. Such theories tend to be ideal; that is, they develop philosophical accounts of the justification of punishment assuming certain ideal conditions. The question then arises as to whether those theories remain compelling when applied to the actual world. It is not possible to discuss each and every such theory here, but consider some general approaches and how they might be affected by social injustice. Consequentialist Theories Consequentialist theories justify punishment by appeal to its good consequences. A system of punishment is justified if it brings about better overall consequences than any alternative system including the option of doing nothing. In general, consequentialists claim that punishment is justified because it secures good consequences through individual and general deterrence, rehabilitation, and incapacitation. These are empirical claims. If punishment were to fail to realize good consequences, or fail to realize as good a set of consequences as could be attained by an alternative policy, then it is not justified on this basis. P P 3476 Clearly issues of social justice will as a matter of fact have an effect on any such empirical claims. It may be best to divert resources away from criminal justice and toward social justice if that will be more effective in reducing crime (or realize other good consequences that outweigh any resulting bad consequences). It may be that rehabilitation is better realized by providing social and economic opportunities rather than by punishment, and so on. These matters can only be settled by empirical enquiry, not by philosophical armchair reflection. Varieties of Desert According to one variety of desert-based retributive justice, punishment is justified if and only if it restores the fair balance of benefits and burdens that the original crime disturbed. This so-called fair-play theory was pioneered by Herbert Morris (1968) and Jeffrie Murphy (1973). In Murphy’s formulation, the argument relied on a hypothetical social contract. In return for security and assurance, self-interested persons would accept an authority whose purpose was to ensure those goods by upholding and enforcing the agreed rules. That is, the citizen benefits from the rule of law and all that comes with it and in return undertakes to maintain society’s rules through his obedience to them. Failure to abide by the rules is a form of “free-riding”; the offender gains the advantages of the system without having to “pay” for them through his own self-restraint. In being punished – in (hypothetically) agreeing to the system of punishment under which he is now made to suffer – the offender pays a different price, one designed to remove the extra benefit he has attained and thus restore the status quo ante. However, as Murphy was quick to point out, the contract here is reciprocal. The authority of the law – and so the duty of obedience on the part of the citizens – stems from its being part of a system of rules to which reasonable selfinterested persons could agree. Thus, if the system of rules is unjust – if, for example, it enforces fundamentally unjust distributive arrangements or discrimination between persons on the basis of their skin color – then citizens no longer have Penal Justice and Social Injustice a duty of obedience and the state no longer has the moral authority to punish breaches of the rules. This account of punishment has been subject to criticism and few (even among its early adherents) continue to adhere to it (for a sympathetic contemporary account, see Dagger 1993; for a summary of the main criticisms, see Matravers 2000, pp. 52–72), but the contractualist worry is a genuine one. To the degree that society is conceived of as a cooperative endeavor in which reciprocally agreed rules are enforced and obeyed, there is a concern that the state’s failing to keep its side of the bargain, so to speak, renders illegitimate its enforcing of those rules. A different, but related worry, affects the censure account of retributive punishment that replaced the “fair-play” account as the leading desert theory in the literature. According to Antony Duff and others, the justification of punishment lies wholly, or in part, in its calling the alleged offender to account and, should the alleged offender prove to have performed the wrongful act without excuse or justification, in its expressing censure of the offender on behalf of the polity. In imposing a penal sanction, the polity provides a vehicle for this censure and a potential vehicle for the offender’s penitential response. In his early work (1986, pp. 291–299), Duff is clear that social injustice renders this account inapplicable to the real world. Such injustice is a symptom, and cause, of the absence of a genuine moral community on whose behalf, and in whose name, the offender is called to account. If there are no shared values, then the offender cannot be censured in their name and cannot in turn use punishment to restore herself to those values and so to the community. Like Murphy, Duff argues that the gap between the ideal and the actual is so great as to render the ideal unusable. However, in later writings, Duff becomes less pessimistic although he still poses the question of whether those who have been systematically excluded from their fair shares of society’s goods can be thought to be bound by the laws of that society, a question he thinks likely to be answered in the negative for many offenders (2001, pp. 183–184). This motivates a different Penal Justice and Social Injustice worry, considered below, which is that social injustice undermines the standing of the society to call the offender to account. Consequentialist, fair-play, and censure-based theories of punishment, then, are each in their own way threatened by conditions of social injustice. In all these cases, the fact of injustice threatens the viability or applicability of the philosophical theory that purports to justify punishment in the real world. However, desert theorists (in particular) also have a different worry about social injustice; this is not that it renders the theory – that punishment is justified because and to the degree that it is deserved – inapplicable, but that it undermines the deservingness of individual offenders; it renders previously unjustly treated citizens less blameworthy and so less deserving of punishment. Blameworthiness and Distributive Injustice The arguments of the section above suggest that social injustice might challenge the legitimacy of the law, the account of political obligation, or the justification of the system of punishment as a whole. A (perhaps) more familiar worry is that in some way or other, defendants from indigent, or unjustly disadvantaged, backgrounds are less to blame than are others. This section considers this worry in relation to cases of excuse and of justification. Rotten Social Background Perhaps the most famous debate in relation to doing penal justice in conditions of social injustice arose out of a 1973 case, US v Alexander. Two black defendants were charged with the murder of two white victims. The defendants had shot the victims following an altercation at a fast-food restaurant during which the victims had called the defendants “God-damned niggers.” On behalf of one of the defendants, who was not mentally ill according to any recognized diagnostic categories, a psychiatrist nevertheless testified that the defendant suffered from an “emotional illness” that was rooted in his 3477 P upbringing in a very poor and deprived neighborhood. This upbringing had left the defendant with an acute sensitivity to racial discrimination such that when he had been subject to racist abuse, he had felt “an irresistible impulse to shoot” (for useful accounts of the issues here, see Green 2011; Heffernan 2000). The judge allowed the jury to consider the mental capacity of the defendant, but mindful of the possibility that the jury might be moved by pity or sympathy for the defendant given his upbringing, the judge went on to say to the jury that it ought not to be concerned “with the question of whether a man had a rotten social background.” The defendants were convicted. The court of appeals upheld the conviction, but one of its judges, David Bazelon, in part dissented. He argued that there was a relevant causal claim linking the defendant’s rotten social background and the defendant having no “meaningful choice when the racial insult triggered” his response in the restaurant (United States v Alexander, 471 F.2d 923: 960). The truth of such a causal claim would need to be considered by the jury, but Bazelon wrote confidently of the social science evidence in its support and of the need to consider what to do with such defendants should they prove innocent, but dangerous (holding out the options of therapy or preventive detention). The idea of a defense of rotten social background was taken up by Richard Delgado (1985). Delgado argued that the law should recognize a new excuse based on extreme poverty and deprivation. As an excuse, the claim would not be that the conduct was justified. Rather, the defendant would have to prove that at the time of acting, her conduct was the result of behaviors shaped by her background such that she met (an extended understanding of) normal excusing conditions: For example, she was unable accurately to understand the nature and consequences of her conduct; she was suffering from involuntary rage; or was otherwise unable to control her conduct. It is important to note that neither Bazelon nor Delgado argues that the fact of an (unusual) causal history to the agent’s conduct is enough P P 3478 to excuse. All actions have causes, some are more unusual than others and some evoke sympathy, but as Stephen Morse insists (2000, p. 130), “causation is neither an excuse per se nor the equivalent of hard choice (so-called compulsion), which is an excusing condition.” Rather, the argument is that the particular background of deprivation is such as to render some defendants excused at the time of their conduct because it interferes with those ordinary capacities on which the law depends when holding persons responsible. In this, a defense of rotten social background would come close to the defense of “battered woman syndrome,” in which it is argued that a history of violent abuse can render a woman incapable of (legally) responsible behavior even at some later point when her conduct seems otherwise to be chosen. Justification Proponents of the excuse of rotten social background accept that the defendant’s conduct was wrongful; they merely argue that it may be excused. However, another response to social injustice is to regard some conduct performed by the disadvantaged as justified. Consider a case imagined by Jeremy Waldron (2000, pp. 104–105). A homeless, unemployed, destitute man in a society with little or no welfare assistance scavenges in a park. He comes across a half-eaten hamburger and begins to eat it. However, the person who had bought the hamburger, having eaten half, was planning to feed the rest to the birds. He complains to the police and the destitute man is arrested and charged with theft. The defendant claims the justification of necessity. Before considering this, it is worth noting how this differs from the claim of excuse in rotten social background. In the case of excuses, the conduct is wrong, but excused. In the case of justification, the conduct itself is not wrongful. Thus, in rotten social background cases, there is no obvious restriction on the possible conduct to which the excuse might attach or on the range of victims of the conduct. As is clear from the Alexander case, the excuse potentially covers serious wrongs such as homicide and it would have made no difference to the case Penal Justice and Social Injustice whether the victim was poor or rich. In the justification case under discussion, it is clear that the conduct that is justified is severely restricted. The defendant might claim justification for picking up the hamburger, but he could not do so for killing the owner so as to get the hamburger (no matter how hungry he was). Similarly, the agent could not claim justification for taking the last morsel of food from a similarly situated indigent victim. These differences, of course, reflect the different structures of excuses and justifications. Although Waldron is clear that there is a moral case for the justifiability of the destitute man’s actions, he is confident that any legal system dedicated to the protection of property rights will reject the necessity defense in this instance. To establish necessity in the common law tradition, the defendant must show imminent threat; that the conduct would be effective in ameliorating that threat; that no alternative legal means to do the same was available; that the conduct was less harmful than the harm threatened; and that the circumstances that gave rise to the threat are not attributable to her. The threshold for the use of the necessity defense is very high. To rebut it, the prosecution would only have to show that the indigent eater of the hamburger was not in danger of death or serious injury, or that he could have gone from the park to the local charitable shelter, or that his condition was due to his culpable failure to find work. In short, necessity and long-term poverty do not map easily onto each other. Moreover, as Waldron insists, systems of law protect the orderly and predictable governance of property, an order that cannot be subject to disruption whenever someone feels the need to appropriate something of someone else’s. The arguments in this section demonstrate the difficulties in matching concerns about social justice with issues in criminal justice. In one way, this is right; not all poor people commit crimes (and not all crimes are committed by the poor) and it would be demeaning to large sections of the population to pretend otherwise. If poverty or disadvantage is to be relevant to judgments of the offender’s liability, then it has to be shown either that the offender’s background relevantly Penal Justice and Social Injustice impaired him at the time of acting, or that his actions were legally justified. It is likely that these hurdles will not in fact be often cleared. However, this seems to leave the issue unresolved. It does matter that society is distributively unjust and it does trouble us that those who systematically suffer most from injustice also disproportionately appear in the criminal justice system as victims and offenders. The State’s Standing to Hold the Offender to Account The focus has so far been on the applicability of theories of punishment to the real world and on the offender. Social injustice raises genuine questions for the first, but the focus on the blameworthiness of the offender seems either to lead in directions covered by the existing criminal law (with respect to excuses and justifications) or to risk widening the scope of the enquiry in ways that potentially demean the poor and disadvantaged. Returning to the original issue, however, suggests an alternative approach in which the focus is not on the offender, but on the state. Assume – reasonably enough in most cases – that the offender acts culpably. The law prohibiting the conduct is reasonable, the offense is wrongful, and the offender is blameworthy for it. To take an example, a disadvantaged offender defrauds the state by claiming unemployment benefits while working on the black market for cash. In response to cases like this, Antony Duff asks not whether the offender is responsible, but to whom he is responsible. That is, criminal responsibility is a relational concept; an alleged offender is responsible for some conduct to someone or some institution. Thus, a teacher is responsible for marking her students’ essays and that responsibility is owed to her students. Moreover, the teacher can call her students to account for failing to submit their essays, and so on. In short, with respect to essays (and no doubt other things), the teacher has standing. The question Duff poses is whether a state’s maintaining of chronic and systematic injustice removes its standing to call offenders to account. 3479 P As the paper of one of his papers suggests – “‘I Might Be Guilty, But You Can’t Try Me’: Estoppel and Other Bars to Trial” (2003), Duff is skeptical that unjust societies retain the standing to call to account those whom they have treated unjustly. This is an attractive response to the issues. It does not deny the responsibility of indigent offenders, and it surely captures a plausible intuition (and mirrors many real life situations in which persons may think, “I may be wrong, but who are you to criticize?”). There is surely something wrong in being held to account by an institution that is itself in violation of the values to which it appeals in its calling the alleged offender to answer for her actions (cf Sykes and Matza 1957 on “The Condemnation of the Condemners”). However, as stated, the account is underdeveloped. Two questions arise: First, does the unjust state lose the standing to judge all offenders and offenses (even those unrelated to the injustice)? Second, does the unjust or immoral state lose all standing across all dimensions? To see this, first contrast the unemployed offender mentioned above who defrauds the state by cheating on his social security payments and the same person who beats his wife. It may be thought that the state lacks the standing to call him to account for fraud, given a background of systemic injustice, but why should this affect its standing to call him to account for assault? Second, consider the standing of the UK state to call a well-off defendant to account for insurance fraud, given recent revelations that the same state had deliberately misled its citizens in the run-up to the second Iraq war and had, when fighting terrorists in Northern Ireland in the 1970s, connived in the extrajudicial execution of (at least one) political agitator (for a summary of these criticisms, see Matravers 2006). In short, the argument from standing seems to do too much. It is in that sense reminiscent of Murphy’s argument that legitimate punishment is impossible in a real world in which distributive injustice is prevalent. Yet, it undeniably captures something of the worry that many people have when confronted by the facts of distributive and P P 3480 retributive justice and, if nothing else, it should evoke in all citizens what Duff (2003, p. 259) calls “a properly humble and cautious spirit which recognizes how far from clean our collective hands and consciences are” with respect to penal justice. Conclusion Not all the poor suffer from the same injustices, not all of them commit crimes, and not all of those who commit crimes do so in similar circumstances (for a nuanced discussion of a “caseby-case” approach to social injustice in relation to the criminal law, see Green 2011, pp. 364–373). Nevertheless, the poor and disadvantaged are more likely to be victimized by crime, they are more likely to engage in criminal activity, and they appear disproportionately among those arrested and convicted (Green 2011, pp. 354–355; Western 2006). If one were to visit any prison throughout much of the world, one would be confronted with populations predominantly made up of young men from poor and disadvantaged backgrounds (in the USA, young black men from the same) (Wacquant 2009). At the same time across much of the developed world, the inequalities between the richest and the poorest in societies are growing. These facts compel attention not just in themselves, but because in punishing the poor, “we run the risk of compounding the sins of socio-economic injustice with those of retributive injustice” (Green 2011, p. 376). The purpose of the arguments above is to show that confronting this possible double injustice from within the existing structures of the criminal law is deeply problematic. Some disadvantaged offenders will suffer from “abnormality of mind” (or similar) consequent upon their disadvantage, but this will be a small minority and, even among those, difficult to establish in court. Few, if any, will be able to claim a justification such as necessity. Ideal theories of punishment may not apply to the world we confront, but absent some other form of social organization, the necessity to punish will persist. Penal Justice and Social Injustice Perhaps the route out of these difficulties is to look beyond the resources of the criminal law and of philosophies of punishment and to political philosophy more generally. Much contemporary discussion of justice revolves around the question of how we might distinguish between those things – actions, omissions, character features, and so on – for which the agent is responsible and on the basis of which he might legitimately claim the benefits or be made to bear the burdens and those things that are merely chance or circumstance – things that, so to speak, simply happen to her – on the basis of which she may deserve assistance or compensation. Of course, while in many cases, poverty and injustice simply happen to people, the decision to commit an offense may fall into the category of choice rather than chance. Nevertheless, asking “when is it fair to make people bear the burdens or enjoy the benefits of their conduct?” may open up avenues of enquiry that might inform the criminal law and, if not that, at least our attitudes to those who fall liable to it (for an initial development of such a strategy, see Matravers 2007: Chap. 3; Scanlon 1998: Chap. 6). That said, given the extent of disagreement among political philosophers as to the answers to these questions, criminal law issues such as those discussed above remain both alive and worthy of attention. Recommended Reading and References Bazelon D (1976) The morality of the criminal law. South Calif Law Rev 49:385–405 Dagger R (1993) Playing fair with punishment. Ethics 103:473–488 Delgado R (1985) “Rotten Social Background”: should the criminal law recognize a defense of severe environmental deprivation?. Law Inequal 39:12–23 Duff RA (1986) Trials & punishments. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Duff RA (2001) Punishment, communication, and community. Oxford University Press, Oxford Duff RA (2003) “I Might Be Guilty, But You Can’t Try Me”: Estoppel and other bars to trial Ohio State. J Crim Law 1:245–259 Green S (2011) Just deserts in unjust societies. In: Duff RA, Green S (eds) Philosophical foundations of the criminal law. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 352–376 Penal Paradigms: Past and Present Heffernan WC (2000) Social justice/criminal justice. In: Heffernan WC, Kleinig J (eds) From social justice to criminal justice: poverty and the administration of criminal law. Oxford University Press, New York/ Oxford, pp 47–83 Matravers M (2000) Justice and punishment: the rationale of coercion. Oxford University Press, Oxford Matravers M (2006) ‘Who’s Still Standing?’ A comment on Antony Duff’s preconditions of criminal liability. J Moral Philos 3(3):320–330 Matravers M (2007) Responsibility and justice. Polity Press, Cambridge Morris H (1968) Persons and punishment. Monist 52:475–501 Morse SJ (2000) Deprivation and desert. In: Heffernan WC, Kleinig J (eds) From social justice to criminal justice: poverty and the administration of criminal law, Practical and professional ethics series. Oxford University Press, New York/Oxford, pp 114–160 Murphy J (1973) Marxism and retribution. Philos Public Aff 22:17–43 Scanlon TM (1998) What we owe to each other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Sykes GM, Matza D (1957) Techniques of neutralization: a theory of delinquency. Am Sociol Rev 22(6):664–670 Wacquant LJD (2009) Punishing the poor: the neoliberal government of social insecurity. Duke University Press, Durham Waldron J (2000) Why indigence is not a justification. In: Heffernan WC, Kleinig J (eds) From social justice to criminal justice: poverty and the administration of criminal law. Oxford University Press, New York/ Oxford, pp 98–113 Western B (2006) Punishment and inequality in America. R. Sage Foundation, New York Penal Paradigms: Past and Present Leslie Sebba Institute of Criminology, Faculty of Law, The Hebrew University, Mt. Scopus, Jerusalem, Israel Overview Accounts, critiques, and theoretical conceptualizations of penal systems reveal that the characteristics of these systems may vary in very significant ways. Penological histories show how the “classical school” of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries (epitomized in the famous essay of Cesare Beccaria’s Of Crimes and Punishments) 3481 P believed that the primary rationale for the penal system was general deterrence and advocated that this should be reflected in sentences proportionate to the seriousness of the offence. They then describe how this ideology was in the latter half of the nineteenth century replaced by individualized sentencing – which in turn gave way a century later to a “just deserts” philosophy (again proportionate). These successive approaches are sometimes referred to as paradigms. A focus on the discourses prevalent in the literature on contemporary criminal justice, however, indicates that in fact a variety of competing models are identified or advocated – perhaps most famously illustrated by Herbert Packer’s seminal article outlining two apparently alternative models – “due process” and “crime control.” This entry will attempt to provide an introductory overview of these developments – both the historical and the contemporary. The usefulness of these approaches will be considered, as well as confusions arising from the terminology employed, given that neither the terms “paradigm” nor “model” are always used consistently. Introduction While penal systems, whether formal or informal, appear to constitute an integral part of every society (and thus presumably, as argued by Durkheim, fulfill some significant social function), they differ from each other in almost every conceivable aspect: the forms of conduct punished, the procedures for determining guilt, the aims of punishment, its modalities, and its severity. Moreover, individual penal systems fluctuate and indeed undergo radical changes over time. In elaborating on these characteristics, traditional penological texts (e.g., Barnes and Teeters 1959) presented largely descriptive accounts of the historical development of penal systems, mainly in Europe and the Americas – while there has also been a fascination with ancient and “primitive” systems (Diamond 1971). Social theorists since Durkheim have offered generalized theoretical explanations for the form and severity of punitive practices – a development analyzed by P P 3482 Garland in Punishment and Modern Society and applied to contemporary society in his Culture of Control (Garland 1990, 2001). More recently, there has been a wave of research endeavoring to explain the wide differences among nations in the severity of their sanctioning policies (Tonry 2007). What many of both the descriptive accounts of penal systems and the more critical analyses share in common is that they tend to view the penal system as – indeed – a “system” with a coherent purpose and philosophy, thereby implying a degree of interconnectedness and compatibility among its different component elements and shared values among the various actors. It is also common to identify somewhat dramatic ideologically driven policy transformations believed to have taken place at certain periods of time. Thus, historical accounts will invariably refer to the eighteenth century as the era of classical criminology (and in particular penology), the late nineteenth and most of the twentieth century as the era of positivism, with the 1970s onward as being dominated by the “just deserts” model. The penal systems identified under these different headings are shown to diverge in fundamental ways, in particular having different sentencing rationales, thereby giving rise to their designation as alternative “penal paradigms.” One purpose of this entry will be to elaborate on and evaluate such historical presentations. It is suggested here that such analyses may be viewed as being complemented by contemporary discourses relating to the characteristics and ideologies of the present-day criminal justice system, which sometimes echo the typification of past ideologies but with a tendency to describe a multiplicity of trends or ideologies operating simultaneously or in competition. Such a connection between past and present is indeed made by Jock Young in his much-cited essays “Thinking Seriously about Crime” and “Incessant Chatter: Recent Paradigms in Criminology” (Young 1981, 1994) which incorporate critiques of the traditional presentation of the historical paradigms while using this concept to analyze a number of more recent theoretical approaches. However, Young also uses the term Penal Paradigms: Past and Present “model” in this context, and this is the term more frequently adopted in current penological discourse when referring to alternative penal options. Much of the discourse relating to criminal justice models, however, seems to have been inspired by the dichotomy developed by Herbert Packer (1964) in his well-known law review article “Two Models of the Criminal Process,” and indeed the relevant literature frequently acknowledges such a debt. This entry will provide a brief survey both of the historic “paradigms” and of the contemporary “models,” followed by some reflections on the nature of their contribution and related conceptual issues. The survey will be preceded, however, by a discussion of the terminology employed here and elsewhere in the literature in this field. Paradigms and Models in a Criminological-Penological Context The term paradigm was developed in the context of the hard sciences to denote the prevailing understanding or interpretation of natural phenomena. It was popularized by Thomas Kuhn in his Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Kuhn 2012) when analyzing how changes come about in such understandings on the part of the scientific community and came to be applied also to the social sciences. While Kuhn’s analysis is essentially restricted in its application to phenomena which may be studied empirically and is thus not applicable to many concepts and ideas pertaining to punishment, it has now a more widespread usage, connoting “a cluster of concepts such as assumptions, values, practices and methodologies shared by a community of researchers in a given discipline” (New World Encyclopedia, online). There may, however, be competing paradigms at any given time, where the evidence is equivocal and/or the scientific community divided in their views and interpretations. In this context it should be noted that while paradigms relate to “scientific findings” and are thus closely linked to positivist conceptions, each paradigm is rather a social construct, describing the collective understandings of a given community as Penal Paradigms: Past and Present perceived by an observer (or participant). In the social sciences where “evidence” tends to be less hard than in the natural sciences (and the role of values more salient), it is probable that there will be less consensuality, thereby increasing the possibility of “competing paradigms.” The term “model” has similarly acquired a wider usage than its original meaning of a (usually small-scale) replication of a product for the purposes of demonstrating or testing its operation, or “providing insight into the consequences of a decision” (Chaiken et al. 1975: v). It is simply used to describe the main features and mode of operation of a system – whether existing or proposed. Both the expressions “paradigm” and “model” implicitly refer to a system or framework which comprises a number of components operating as a cohesive whole – and, where relevant, sharing the same values and ideology. Only the paradigm, however, has a connotation of exclusivity – although also that such exclusivity may be ephemeral. Other related terms used in the penological context include penal strategies (Garland 1985) and styles of social control (Black 1976). Young (1981) not only used both the terms “models” and “paradigms” but also Weber’s concept of ideal types, which suggests an idealized account of the institution in question which is unlikely to be found in that form in real life. Recent analyses of Packer’s models have considered their relationship with Weber’s ideal types (see below). It should also be noted that the first two paradigms to be discussed here, the “classical” and the “positivist” paradigms, have generally been described in the literature as schools. Finally, certain distinct perspectives on criminological issues today may be referred to as criminologies, such as “feminist criminology” and “green (environmentalist) criminology.” The relative significance and usefulness of these terms has yet to be fully explored. Historic Paradigms The three historical paradigms to be considered here are set in somewhat different theoretical 3483 P frameworks. While the classical school, at least as reflected by its most notable representative, Cesare Beccaria, focuses almost exclusively on the formal institutions of the criminal justice system (in this respect resembling the contemporary models to be considered later in this entry), the positivist school is much wider in its concerns, being equally – or indeed primarily – concerned with the etiology of crime. By contrast, the third of our historical paradigms, just deserts, has the narrowest focus, being concerned exclusively with the purposes and procedures of sentencing. The Classical Paradigm This paradigm is identified with the European enlightenment movement and the emergence of the ideas which were to become identified with liberal theory and English constitutionalism (Young 1981) as an antidote to the monarchical despotism prevailing in much of continental Europe. Building on Montesquieu’s doctrine of the separation of powers and Rousseau’s social contract theory, Beccaria (1764/1995) in his seminal essay advocated a strict separation of powers and equality before the law in order to counter the arbitrary practices prevalent in certain contemporary European regimes which occurred as a result of executive intervention in trials and sentencing. Beccaria advocated uniform penalties, proportional to the seriousness of the offence, which would strengthen their deterrent power: rational persons would refrain from committing crimes attracting high penalties, especially if law enforcement was systematic, certain, and immediate. The attribution of free will and rationality to potential offenders and correspondingly the importance of deterrence as the primary aim of punishment are thus perceived as identifying characteristics of the classical paradigm. This paradigm may also be seen to be linked to the development of the modern prison. While Beccaria was advocating the prison as a more effective deterrent than the death penalty, his contemporary John Howard was documenting the practices of the then local prisons, which led the way to the enactment in 1779 of the Penitentiary Houses Act in order to establish a new and rationalized form of prison – the penitentiary. P P 3484 As is well known, this system, based upon uniform treatment in identical cells which it was assumed would lead to penitence and reform, was ultimately pioneered in the United States a few decades later. Another key figure identified with this paradigm was Jeremy Bentham, also famous for developing his own “rational” model of prison development – the Panopticon (Semple 1993). The Positivist Paradigm Concepts of equality and uniformity in penal policy were challenged during the second half of the nineteenth century by the rise of the social sciences and the claim of Auguste Comte that in the course of human development “metaphysical” or abstract thinking was to be replaced by the “positivist” stage – and the application of purportedly scientific methodology and empiricism. One outcome of this was Lombroso’s theory of delinquent man. The focus on human differences resulted in a penchant among positivist criminologists and their disciples in the field for the classification of offenders for treatment purposes. Such techniques derived encouragement from the mid-century experiments with the “progressive stage system” (pioneered in Ireland) whereby prisoners advanced through the prison system and into the community in the light of their conduct. Under the influence of positivism, the reformation of the offender became the declared purpose of punishment rather than deterrence, and the ideal of standardized penalties proportional to the seriousness of the offence as posited by Beccaria came to be replaced by the individualization of punishment, as expounded in the treatise bearing this name written by Raymond Saleilles (1911). The new approach to sentencing was epitomized by the principle of the indeterminate sentence widely adopted in the USA whereby terms of imprisonment imposed by the courts were open-ended, the actual duration of the sentence to be determined by a parole board in the light of the prisoner’s progress. This “individual treatment model” of sentencing, as it developed towards the end of the nineteenth century and throughout much of the twentieth century, was characterized by the Penal Paradigms: Past and Present creation of specialized penal and judicial institutions ostensibly adapted to the needs of the offenders in question, such as reformatories and juvenile courts for younger offenders and institutions for dangerous psychopaths, the involvement of behavioral experts such as psychiatrists and probation officers in decision-making, and the increasing recognition of the helping professions as agents of offender rehabilitation in both closed institutions and in the community. Moreover, while the determinist conceptualization of human behavior and the focus on the individual led to the application of more flexible criteria of criminal responsibility, some versions of the Social Defense ideology (a branch of the positivist movement which focused on penological issues) proposed also to dispense with the legal requirement of a “guilty mind” (cf. Ancel 1965). The threshold requirement for treatment would be the personality of the alleged offender – the main criterion being his or her dangerousness. The Just Deserts Paradigm The positivist ideology with its emphasis on rehabilitation meshed well with the welfarist ethos that was widely supported during the period following the Second World War. However, if the individualized treatment paradigm was most widely accepted (at least in the prevailing rhetoric) in the USA, it was there too that it was the most forcefully rejected during the 1970s. Critiques of this model focused on the inequality and arbitrariness of the system, in particular in the context of parole decision-making (American Friends Service Committee 1971). Critics included not only radicals and liberals but also conservatives (cf. Blomberg and Lucken 2000). Adding fuel to the fire was the critique of sentencing disparities deriving from the wide discretionary powers held by the judges (Frankel 1973), and – perhaps most influential of all – the empirical claim that the effectiveness of the treatment methods on which the system was based was unproven (Martinson 1974). The structure which was to take account of these critiques, as formulated most articulately in Doing Justice, the report published by Andrew von Hirsch (1976), was a return to fixed and Penal Paradigms: Past and Present proportional sentencing. While outwardly this bore some resemblance to the system advocated by the Classical School (see above), its underlying philosophy was not deterrence, or indeed any other consequentialist purpose – as none had been shown to be effective by the empirical evaluations, but desert, a contemporary version of the historic aim of retribution. According to this doctrine, the penalty would match the seriousness of the offence as measured by the harm inflicted and the culpability of the offender – and thus become standardized. The mechanism whereby this was to be achieved was the establishment of a sentencing commission which would issue detailed guidelines to the sentencing judges, whose discretion would be severely curtailed. Since sentences were to be for fixed terms, the discretionary power of the parole boards would be abolished. Support for such reforms in the USA was such that they were adopted in principle by the federal system and around half of the states – as well as some overseas countries, as documented in other entries. The concept of “structured sentencing,” whether by guidelines or otherwise, attracted even wider support. The “individual treatment model” as the foundation of the penal system had in general been rejected. Historical Paradigms: A Critique The preceding overview suggests that in the context of this entry, the term “paradigm” is most appropriately (or least inappropriately) used in the context of the positivist school, since the policies advocated in accordance with this approach were the most rooted in the empirical understanding on the part of its adherents of the world about them. It was indeed this characteristic that ultimately contributed to the demise of this paradigm when research findings suggested that the ability of decision-makers to make accurate prognoses and identify successful treatments was very limited. There are, however, other problems with what Young has described as the typical textbook presentation of a linear development of a succession of paradigms. Young is correct in pointing out that despite the enormous impact of 3485 P positivist thinking on the twentieth century penological discourse, criminal justice structures – particularly in European countries – remained throughout the twentieth century strongly influenced by the tenets of eighteenth century classicism. The nature and seriousness of the offence remained the primary consideration in determining the sentence, with the characteristics of the offender (other than past convictions) playing a secondary role. Contemporaries therefore referred to the model adhered to in Europe during the course of the twentieth century Europe as “neoclassical.” Today too it is hard to identify a dominant paradigm. As noted above, the parameters of the third of the paradigms referred to, the desert paradigm, were somewhat narrowly drawn (being confined to sentencing practices), and in any case, most contemporary western systems have been strongly influenced by consequentialist ideologies – incapacitation, deterrence and even rehabilitation. It should also be recalled that the concept of the paradigm refers in principle not directly to the practices of the actors in the field (in this case the criminal justice agencies) but to the perception of these practices – or perhaps of the ideologies which are thought to motivate them – on the part of the relevant disciplinary group. Thus, radical criminologists such as Young, who perceive the criminal justice system primarily in terms of control, if not exploitation, of the powerless by the powerful, have since the 1960s been offering alternative paradigms to explain its operation. It may always have been the case that it was more problematic to identify monolithic trends (such as are implicit in the concept of the paradigm) in one’s own era, when different views or nuances will be more apparent than when looking back in history. However, this problem has surely been aggravated by the dichotomization of social scientists into positivists and social constructivists, further compounded by the fragmentation caused by postmodern developments – leading Garland and Sparks (2000) to opine that further paradigms in the (consensual) Kuhnian sense can no longer be anticipated. These authors point to the salience of crime in the contemporary politics P P 3486 of neoliberal societies. This has had the effect of reducing the relevance of the prevailing views of academia and the professions, which have perhaps themselves become more fragmented and politicized. Criminal Justice Models The Legacy of Herbert Packer Unlike the paradigm, the concept of a model does not imply consensus and exclusivity but rather variation and experimentation. While criminologists have sometimes used them in the context of empirically oriented work (e.g., Feeley 1973; Chaiken et al. 1975), much of the modern discourse on criminal justice models has been devoted to normative and/or ideological issues, having been inspired, as noted above, by Herbert Packer’s seminal article “Two Models of the Criminal Process” (Packer 1964 – subsequently expanded into a book – Packer 1968). The article followed a period of activism in the area of civil rights and criminal justice on the part of the US Supreme Court headed by Chief Justice Warren, but Packer was doubtless concerned by the minority dissenting views which were to become the majority in the era of Chief Justice Burger. It seemed to Packer that the Court and indeed other criminal justice agencies were being required to choose (or at least prioritize) between two alternative types of process which he identified as due process and crime control, respectively, representing alternative sets of values and priorities. A system based upon due process he perceived as being analogous to an obstacle course, in that it sought to ensure protection of the rights of the innocent (and to risk the acquittal of the guilty) by imposing restraints on the prosecution. Under the crime control model, on the other hand, the system was comparable to an assembly line in a factory – designed to maximize the numbers who would be processed through the system to conviction and punishment in minimum time. This was to be achieved by focusing on the investigation stage and offering plea bargains to the “factually guilty.” Although Packer did not Penal Paradigms: Past and Present perceive these models as mutually exclusive, his dichotomization has penetrated deeply into (at least) the academic criminal justice culture. Critiques of Packer’s Models Packer’s Models have been the brunt of a number of critiques, some trenchant, with Griffiths (1970) being a notable early example, and most recently and comprehensively by Macdonald (2008). These critiques have focused on three main aspects of Packer’s work: (a) his conceptualization of the model, (b) the validity of the due process and the crime control models and the relationship between them, and (c) the need for additional models having (in the view of their proponents) greater validity or irrelevance. (a) Conceptualization The lack of precision in the concept of the model in the contemporary literature of the social sciences – on one view its “indiscriminate use” (Macdonald 2008) – has already been referred to. Zedner (2004: 116) has observed that “It is often difficult to determine whether models are intended as analytical devices or as normative statements of ideals to which the process should aspire” – an ambivalence conveyed by Packer too. In the wake of Damaska’s discussion as to whether Packer’s models are consistent with Weber’s ideal types, Macdonald notes that Weber distinguished between ideal types and ideals, the former constituting an analytical construct based upon accentuated tendencies which was in his view how Packer conceptualized his models, without fully developing them. (Whether in fact the models were quite unconnected with value judgments, as Weber described his ideal types, is another question). Macdonald sought, as the title of his article indicates, to “learn from Packer’s mistakes” and to “succeed. . . where Packer failed” (Macdonald 2008: 269), for which purpose he found necessary to differentiate between the investigative and the trial stages of the process, while arguing the need for a multidimensional model. On similar grounds Ashworth and Redmayne (2005: 38ff.) Penal Paradigms: Past and Present reject the “models” approach as an unsatisfactory basis for the evaluation of the criminal process. These writers find models based on simple dichotomies to be too crude – tending “to reduce the world to black and white” (Zedner 2004: 119–120). Additional conceptual issues arise in the context of the evaluation of the two models as outlined by Packer, and the relationship between them. (b) The Two Models and the Relationship Between Them A number of criticisms have been directed at the specific models described by Packer, as well as suggesting that the dichotomy may be a false one (see, e.g., Macdonald 2008: 264ff.). Both Damaska (1973) and Smith (1997) find fault with due process as an objective (in Damaska’s words “obstacles without a course”), rather than a principle imposing restraints on the pursuit of other objectives. In this context Macdonald (2008: 289) refers to the work of the Swedish jurist Jareborg who differentiated between a “defensive model” and an “offensive approach” to criminal policy. Zedner (2004: 118) has pointed out that speed and efficiency – characteristics attributed by Packer to the crime control model – are also important for due process and protection of the defendant’s liberty. McBarnet (1981), echoing the literature of radical criminology, has argued that rather than constituting an alternative approach, due process serves to legitimize the goals of (repressive) crime control, thus giving rise to “due process. . . for crime control.” (c) Additional Models With Packer’s dichotomy as a “given,” other writers have proffered additional (often designated “third”) models. Griffiths’ “family model” (which clearly falls into Zedner’s normative category) was a proposal for a more therapeutic procedure. This, too, has been the direction of at least some of the recent writings seeking to accommodate a role in the system for the victim. Thus, while Beloof (1999) has proposed 3487 P a Victim Participation Model within a due process framework, Roach (1999) has portrayed the alternatives of a punitive and a non-punitive model of victims’ rights, and it is the latter – designated a “Circle Model” and based upon restorative justice – which he seeks to promote. A unique attempt to incorporate a broader model approach into an empirical analysis of the criminal justice system was undertaken some years ago by King (1981). King identified six alternative models of the system for which accounts could be found – whether by name or implicit – in the criminological or criminal justice literature. To Packer’s duo (due process and crime control), King added: the medical (or treatment) model, and three further models deriving from criminological research or sociological critiques – the bureaucratic model, the status passage model, and the power model. He then identified the “features of the court” which one would expect to find under each model. The validity of these models could then be tested (in the instant case, in his study of English magistrates’ courts) by observing to what extent these features were actually found in the courts. “As in the physical and social sciences, the term model is used here to denote a hypothetical but coherent scheme for testing the evidence” (p. 12). There is no doubt that the integration of a multi-model approach into a field study served to enrich this discourse. However, there is a measure of disjuncture here in the construction of the models in that the first three, which King calls “participant” models, reflect the idealized expectations of a certain category of participant (thus, again, falling into the category of normative models), while the other three which he refers to as “social” models are based on academic critiques of the existing system. On the other hand, the attribution to each model of a “social function” bestows upon the models a unifying ideology or rationale such as generally characterized the paradigms discussed in the first part of this entry. P P 3488 It should be noted that the “penal process” to which the literature reviewed in this section relates is that of common law jurisdictions (primarily the USA). Models relating to other systems will be very different, but some “Packer scholars” have dwelt on the relationship between the common law and developments in continental Europe’s “inquisitorial system”: see, e.g., Damaska (1973). Special Categories of Offender Variations in the manner in which criminal justice systems operate tend to be augmented when dealing with offenders with distinctive traits or pathologies – or whose offences are perceived as particularly threatening or distinctive in some other way. Examples would be sex offenders, offenders against state security laws (“terrorists”), offences related to drug use, minors, or the mentally unstable. In such cases different paradigms or models may be identified. Thus, the modification of human rights protections when dealing with security offences (including punishment without trials) may be such that the “war” model is arguably the most appropriate metaphor to attach in this case. By contrast, purportedly softer alternatives to the prevailing model(s) may be adopted when dealing with minors. Identifying the optimal policy for his purpose, however, has been the subject of intense debate over the past century. It was in relation to juvenile offenders that the treatment model of the positivist school assumed its most comprehensive application, in particular via the vehicle of the juvenile court, first established (in Chicago) in 1899. The treatment of juvenile offenders became virtually indistinguishable from “welfare” cases such as children in need of care and supervision. They were thus deprived of the guarantees provided under the US Constitution’s Bill of Rights. Juvenile courts in other common law jurisdictions, however, retained somewhat more of a rights framework – while the US Supreme Court case Re Gault in 1967 (387 U.S. 1) reversed the welfarist trend in the American system. If for some decades the juvenile justice system has seen these two approaches – the “welfare” model and the “justice” or “legal” model – in combat (or fusion), recent decades have seen Penal Paradigms: Past and Present strong claims, particularly in the antipodes, for their replacement by a system of restorative justice. Three distinct approaches to juvenile justice have thus emerged. As observed by Borowski and O’Connor (1997: 229): “Unlike other aspects of the criminal justice system, it is possible to identify coherent theoretical positions reflected in legislation, policy and practice.” O’Connor’s review of these models considers how each model responds to such underlying questions as follows: What is the cause of crime? How should it be viewed? How should it be defined in law? How should the state respond? What is the relationship between the individual and the state? What is the purpose of the sanction? O’Connor’s models arguably present both an analytical and a normative framework for the comparison of these three ideologies, while his approach bears a resemblance to Young’s analysis of criminological paradigms referred to in the Introduction. Conclusions This entry has analyzed the use made of two concepts – the paradigm and the model – in the course of the history of the criminal justice system. It seems to the present writer that the paradigm has been used primarily to describe changes in the main orientation of the system at different periods, while the model has been more extensively used in contemporary settings. Both terms have had a usage somewhat different from their original meaning (in the case of the model, a multiplicity of usages), and partly for this reason, the discourses in which they have been incorporated have been challenged. The departure point for this entry was the concept of the paradigm – perhaps the more interesting concept because of the connotations conveyed by this term in a penological context of (a) being unequivocally linked to an ideology, (b) indicating an interpretation uniquely accepted by the relevant disciplinary group, and (c) having played a key role in the history of penology and the penal system. Yet while the brief historical overview presented at the beginning of this entry Penal Paradigms: Past and Present may have been sufficient to indicate the dramatic contrast between the main historic paradigms (in particular classicism and positivism), Young is almost certainly correct in denying the occurrence of a “paradigm shift” as a momentary historical event, the reality having been considerably more complex. Further, the idea that the “community of [criminology] scholars” will identify with a common vision of penal policy has become increasingly unlikely from generation to generation. Even less likely is the prospect of shared perceptions between the “criminology community” and policy-makers, such as Garland suggests may have occurred in the era of “penal welfarism” and “government criminology.” As observed by Garland and Sparks (2000), in an era of ideological fragmentation and politicization, paradigms – like cultures – are likely to be multiple. The relatively fluid concept of the model is free from such connotations, but its conceptual ambiguities have given rise to much confusion. This confusion came to the fore in the aftermath of the publication of Herbert Packer’s famous two models of the criminal process – the crime control model and the due process model, and the numerous critiques thereof. Nevertheless, Packer’s models have become an inseparable part of the discourse of criminal justice. Indeed, the two concepts considered in this entry are likely to survive and enhance both critical analyses and normative debates on the many facets of penality – while methodological inquiries as to their validity and applicability may serve to clarify underlying epistemological issues. Acknowledgement The author would like to thank Prof. Lucia Zedner for her helpful comments on a previous draft. Related Entries ▶ Historical Criminology ▶ History of Corrections ▶ History of Juvenile Justice ▶ Legal Control of the Police ▶ Problem-Solving Courts ▶ Prosecution and Wrongful Convictions 3489 P Recommended Reading and References American Friends Service Committee (1971) The struggle for justice. Hill & Wang, New York Ancel M (1965) Social defence. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London Ashworth A, Redmayne M (2005) The criminal process, 3rd edn. OUP, Oxford Barnes HE, Teeters NK (1959) New horizons in criminology, 3rd edn. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs Beccaria C (1764/1995) On crimes and punishments and other writings (trans ed: Bellamy R). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Beloof DE (1999) The third model of criminal process: the victim participation model. Utah Law Rev 2:289 Black D (1976) The behavior of law. Academic, New York Blomberg T, Lucken K (2000) American penology: a history of control. Aldine de Gruyter, New York Borowski A, O’Connor I (1997) Models of juvenile justice. In: O’Connor I, Borowski A (eds) Juvenile crime, justice and corrections. Addison Wesley Longman, Melbourne (Chap 12) Chaiken J et al (1975) Criminal justice models: an overview. Rand, Santa Monica Damaska M (1973) Evidentiary barriers to conviction and two models of criminal procedure: a comparative study. Univ Pa Law Rev 121:506 Diamond AS (1971) Primitive law: past & present. Methuen, London Feeley M (1973) Two models of the criminal justice system – an organizational perspective. Law Soc Rev 7:403 Frankel ME (1973) Criminal sentences: law without order. Hill & Wang, New York Garland D (1985) Punishment and welfare. Gower, Aldershot Garland D (1990) Punishment and modern society. Clarendon, Oxford Garland D (2001) The culture of control. OUP, Oxford Garland D, Sparks R (2000) Criminology, social theory, and the challenge of our times. In: Garland D, Sparks R (eds) Criminology and social theory 1. Clarendon, Oxford Griffiths J (1970) Ideology in criminal procedure or a ‘third model’ of the criminal process. Yale Law J 79:359 http://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/entry/Paradigm. Accessed 22 Jan 2013 King M (1981) The framework of criminal justice. Croom Helm, London Kuhn T (2012) The structure of scientific revolutions. 4th edn, University of Chicago Press, Chicago MacDonald S (2008) Constructing a framework for criminal justice research: learning from Packer’s mistakes. New Crim Law Rev 11:257 Martinson R (1974) What works? Questions and answers about prison reform. Pub Interes 35:22 McBarnet DJ (1981) Conviction: law, the state and the construction of justice. Macmillan, London P P 3490 Packer H (1964) Two models of the criminal process. Univ Pa Law Rev 113:1 Packer H (1968) The limits of the criminal sanction. Stanford University Press, Stanford Roach K (1999) Four models of the criminal process. J Crim Law Criminol 89:671 Saleilles R (1911) The individualisation of punishment. Little, Brown, Boston Semple J (1993) Bentham’s prison: a study of the panopticon penitentiary. Clarendon, Oxford Smith DJ (1997) Case construction and the goals of criminal justice. Br J Criminol 37:319 Tonry M (ed) (2007) Crime, punishment and politics in comparative perspective. U of Chicago Press, Chicago von Hirsch A (1976) Doing justice: the choice of punishments, Hill & Wang, New York Young J (1981) Thinking seriously about crime: some models of criminology. In: Fitzgerald M (ed) Crime and society: readings in history and theory. Routledge, London Young J (1994) Incessant chatter: recent paradigms in criminology. In: Maguire M et al (eds) The Oxford handbook of criminology. Clarendon, Oxford, p 69 Zedner L (2004) Criminal justice. OUP, Oxford Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory Matt Matravers Morrell Centre for Toleration University of York, York, UK Overview Many penal philosophers think that offering a justification of the state’s right to punish is particularly urgent (and difficult) precisely because punishment involves doing things to people that would, outside the practice of punishment, be gross rights violations. That is, punishment typically involves imposing some deprivation – for example, the removal of property or freedoms – on a person for committing an offense and this stands in need of justification. Yet, despite this motivation, many theories of the justification of punishment say surprisingly little about the detail of sentencing and penalties. This entry considers the various rationales for sentencing with a view to showing both how different justifications of punishment have different Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory implications for sentencing theory and practice and how reflecting on sentencing matters can shed light on the justification of punishment. The entry considers first consequentialist theories – that is, theories that justify punishment by reference to the net benefits that accrue through punishment in comparison with any other form of social control (or doing nothing) – and then desert-based, retributive, theories. Finally, it considers some questions of the relationship between theory and practice. Punishment and Sentencing Punishment Punishment – or at least state punishment – involves the intentional infliction on an offender by a proper authority of “pain or other consequences normally considered unpleasant” for an offense against legal rules (Hart 1968, pp. 4–5). In addition, it involves the expression of moral condemnation or censure (Duff 2007; Feinberg 1970). When a court passes sentence, it gives shape to the particular consequence to be visited on the offender. In practice, the options available to the court may be limited by guidelines or statute and the court may not be explicit in justifying the use of one penalty rather than another. However, the use of punishment in general, and of particular penalties, requires justification and those justifications tend to fall into two broad categories: consequentialist and retributive. For consequentialists, punishment is justified because its consequences – specifically, having the system of punishment with its associated penalties – can be expected to yield higher net benefits than having an alternative system of social control or having no such system. This may be because punishment reduces future instances of criminal behavior through deterrence, rehabilitation, or incapacitation. For retributivists, punishment is justified because it is deserved by the offender for his offense. It may be that good consequences also follow, but the justification of punishment does not appeal to these consequences. What, then, do these broad theories of punishment imply Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory for sentencing theory (insofar as we can distinguish sentencing theory and penal philosophy) and practice? Deterrence Deterrence is typically split into “special” and “general.” Special deterrence is aimed at the particular offender and is sometimes discussed in relation to the giving of more substantial punishments to repeat offenders. However, it is not advanced as a general theory of sentencing. This is perhaps a reflection of the lack of empirical evidence when it comes to special deterrence and of the fact that a sentencing scheme that was genuinely tied to special deterrence would have to allow specific, individualized sentences for each offender in relation to his particular likelihood of reoffending. Such a sentencing scheme would lack all consistency and would, in any case, be unworkable. General deterrence addresses not the particular offender in court, but potential offenders throughout the population. If the general justifying aim of punishment is to secure good consequences by reducing criminal behavior, then it is argued that the mechanism by which it does that is general deterrence. The origins of the modern approach are most often associated with the great utilitarian philosopher Jeremy Bentham. Bentham thought the infliction of pain was, other things equal, an evil, but the threat – and where that threat failed, the infliction – of pain could be justified if it secured better future consequences than would be achieved by any alternative action or policy. Assuming that the addressees of the system (that is, ordinary citizens) were motivated by the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain, Bentham argued that criminal sanctions should be set at just that level required to change the outcome of the “hedonic calculus” for each individual in favor of what would be conducive to the maximization of the general good. Moreover, Bentham went on, penalties should be such as to “induce a man to choose always the least mischievous of two offenses” by ensuring that “where two offenses come into competition, the 3491 P punishment for the greater offense must be sufficient to induce a man to prefer the less” (Bentham 1970, pp. 168). That is, he developed an account of penalty scales (Bentham 1843). In thinking of people as rational calculators set on maximizing their own interests and susceptible to changes in the payoffs of different actions, Bentham’s theory has much in common with contemporary proponents of the economic theory of law such as Richard Posner (Posner 1985). However, critics of the position have pointed to flaws both in the empirical claims made on behalf of general deterrence and in its normative foundations. Empirical Questions Around General Deterrence Empirical questions around general deterrence revolve around the overall claim that the threat of legal punishment reduces offending and the claim that marginal changes in the severity of sanctions has an effect on rates of offending. The difficulty with the first of these claims is in establishing that it is the threat of punishment rather than anything else that stops people from breaking the law. Moreover, insofar as the theory posits an effect that happens because people reason about what to do as rational, self-interested calculators, the account may explain some people’s behavior and not that of others. It may simply not be true that certain kinds of offenders do accurately balance the factors for and against their offending in advance (even when they know, for example, what penalty they are likely to be given and the likelihood of being caught). In short, general deterrence may be at best a selective explanation of law-abiding behavior because many offenders do not think as Bentham and modern economists believe they think (Doob and Webster 2003). A similar problem arises with the empirical evidence in relation to the effects of marginal changes in sentencing severity or probability of conviction. In a review of research, Andrew von Hirsch and his coauthors identified the factors that would need to be true for such marginal changes to have an effect on a potential offender’s behavior. That offender, they argued, P P 3492 would need to know about the change; he would need to include the increased or decreased risks of suffering punishment in his decision as to whether to offend; he would need to believe in a realistic possibility that he might be caught and that the penalty would be applied to him; and he would need to be willing to adapt his behavior in the light of these new considerations (von Hirsch 1999). The conclusion of the study is that while there is some evidence of a link between offending and the certainty of punishment, there is far less evidence of a link between offending and the severity of punishment (see also Bottoms and von Hirsch 2011). Normative Questions Around General Deterrence Insofar as deterrence theories are embedded in, and result from, consequentialist accounts of punishment, they are subject to the moral criticisms that are often leveled at those accounts. The problem is a general one: Consequentialist accounts value the aggregate (sometimes the average) good achieved in the future. We are to do what will, in Bentham’s famous phrase, achieve “the greatest happiness of the greatest number.” But, in being concerned for the greatest happiness (or utility), the theory leaves out questions of the distribution of utility; it fails to pay attention to what John Rawls (1971, p. 27) calls, “the distinction between persons.” For this reason, it is alleged, if the calculation dictates it, it may be not merely morally permissible, but morally obligatory, to frame and punish an innocent person (McCloskey 1968) or to punish an offender far in excess of what is usual to make an example of him. Consequentialist writers have responded to this kind of criticism by insisting that the theory is best thought of as addressing rules and institutions and not individual actions (Goodin 1995; Rawls 1955/1999). In that case, they argue the system of rules in relation to criminal justice and the range and type of penalties that best promote long-term good will be much the same as is found in current liberal systems. That is, the rule “only punish those (believed to be) guilty and not the innocent” will better promote the good than a rule Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory that allows the innocent to be sacrificed each and every time that particular act will have better long-term consequences than any alternative. However, few have been convinced by this argument in part because of doubts about the claim that the usual procedural rights and protections of (suspected) offenders will ensure long-term utility, and in part because even if it delivers the right answer (not to hang the innocent man), it does so for the wrong reasons. The innocent man deserves to be spared because it would be wrong to kill him, not because a rule against hanging innocents secures better consequences than its opposite (Matravers 2000, pp. 17–23). The idea that the justification of punishment and of the penalties it imposed must be grounded in the requirement “to preserve and increase the welfare of the state” (Michael and Adler 1933, p. 340) was prevalent for much of the century prior to the 1960s (Tonry 2011b, pp. 14–18). It seemed to some writers to be the only “rational” basis for sentencing (Walker 1969). However, from the 1970s onward, the theory came under sustained criticism. In moral theory from neoKantian writers including, and inspired by, John Rawls and in penal theory by the “Just Deserts” movement. Yet, we continue to believe – and to find evidence for – the claim that the whole criminal justice system must surely have something to do with reducing future crime rates and that taken as a whole, it does deter crime (Robinson and Darley 2003, 2004). Moreover, statutes and judges continue to refer to deterrence at the point of sentencing. So, whatever its philosophical difficulties, it is clear that deterrence is not yet moribund in practice. Incapacitation and Rehabilitation At the high point of utilitarian welfarist thinking about punishment (in roughly the middle of the Twentieth Century), it seemed obvious to writers on the criminal law that a rational approach to punishment would eschew retributivism as “fallacious” (Michael and Adler 1933, p. 341) and barbaric. Instead, it seemed clear that if the welfare of the state was to be increased, then Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory antisocial behavior, and those who committed it, needed to be dealt with “scientifically.” Offenders would be “treated” under the careful eye of experts and until “cured” would generally be held away from the general population. For the influential social and legal thinker, Barbara Wootton, the criminal law was irrational in its concern with intentions and mental states prior to conviction. Rather, mens rea considerations mattered only “after a breach of law has been proved” because of “the light which they throw on the likelihood of [the offender] offending again, and upon the most hopeful way of dealing with him” (Wootton 1978, p. 224). Sentences should be indeterminate and offenders released when, or if, their individualized treatment plans proved successful. There were individual voices of dissent. For example, CS Lewis’s (1949) “The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment” offered the argument that the treatment model reduced persons from choosing agents to manipulable things. By the late 1960s, those voices had increased and by the 1970s become a clamor (Frankel 1972; Kleinig 1973; Morris 1974; von Hirsch and Committee for the Study of Incarceration 1976). The charge was normative in that utilitarianism treated people as mere objects to be manipulated; political in that indeterminate sentences were racially biased and unfair; and empirical in that increasing doubts were expressed about the efficacy of treatment. Remnants of both incapacitation and rehabilitation nevertheless remain in contemporary penal philosophy and sentencing theory. With respect to incapacitation, governments (of all persuasions) have responded to the risks created by so-called dangerous persons – often sex offenders – by allowing incapacitative sentences or post-sentence restrictions such as sex-offender registers. However, the policy has largely drifted free of any theoretical foundation in a theory of punishment. Rather, it exists as a bolt-on public policy that philosophers have approached as a discrete problem. The question is, can – and if so, how should – a liberal society restrict the freedoms of some for purely or primarily preventive reasons? The best answer to that is that any 3493 P such policy is justifiable only if: (1) the potential harm was sufficiently grave; (2) the prediction technology was sufficiently accurate; (3) the preventive response was maximally humane and minimally intrusive under the circumstances; and (4) if the preventive action was preceded by adequate due process (Morse 1999, p. 297). For many critics, condition (2) is seldom met given the unreliability of current predictive judgments (Monahan 2004). Similarly, rehabilitation is not regarded by most contemporary penal philosophers as providing an overall theory of punishment or criminal justice, but that is not to say that it is redundant in sentencing decisions. Two different motivations have sustained rehabilitative programs: first, a humanitarian desire to help those in incarceration many of whom have mental health issues, drug issues, and basic training needs; second, increased frustration with rates of recidivism that spawned the “What Works?” movement – a political movement keen to subject policy to evidence-based evaluation – which revitalized interest in techniques for anger control, the use of cognitive behavioral therapy, and other techniques of behavioral modification. This focus on the “good done” by legal processes (including arrest, trial, and punishment) has developed into a small but significant movement under the title of “therapeutic jurisprudence”, which (as the name suggest) aims to assess criminal justice institutions against a standard of therapeutic usefulness (Wexler 2008; Winick 1997). In short, incapacitation and rehabilitation remain important parts of public policy and sentencing practice. But, they do so largely as discrete elements and not as the result of an overall theory of punishment in which the welfare of society is the only desideratum. Retributive Theories Retributive theories of punishment go back (at least) to the great German philosophers Immanuel Kant and Georg Hegel (see ▶ Traditional Retributivism). Following the assault on indeterminate sentencing in the 1970s, and the more P P 3494 general philosophical critique of consequentialist thinking at around the same time, retributivism came back into fashion for the rest of the century. Retributivists hold that punishment is justified when, and because, it is deserved (although the exact sense of desert is contested (Matravers 2011)). More precisely, the argument is that those who culpably commit criminal offenses deserve censure and that censure should take the form of a penal sanction – so-called hard treatment. Most importantly for the development of a retributive sentencing scheme, that hard treatment must be proportionate both in the sense of cardinal proportionality (the penalty should be fitting or commensurate with the wrong) and of ordinal proportionality (crimes of comparable seriousness ought to receive penalties of comparable severity). The precise way in which retributivists defend their theories varies. For Michael Moore (Moore 1987, 1997), punishment is good when and because it is deserved and this judgment and the associated penalties are a matter of what is dictated by a correct account of morality. For Antony Duff, it is censure that is deserved and hard treatment is merely the vehicle through which that censure is communicated and through which the offender can show penance (Duff 1986, 2007). For Andrew von Hirsch and Andrew Ashworth, retributivism is a mixed theory in which censure addresses us as moral beings and hard treatment offers a “prudential supplement” encouraging us to keep to the law (von Hirsch 1993; von Hirsch and Ashworth 2005). Proportionality The principle of proportionality is very attractive. If punishment is an exercise in blaming, then the penalties must reflect this in the sense both that the penalty must be at an appropriate level and that more serious wrongs deserve more blame and so more severe punishment. This also captures a very important commitment to equality and justice often glossed as “treat like cases alike and different cases differently.” That is, if two offenders commit crimes of equal seriousness with equal culpability, then they should be punished equally. Moreover, once an account Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory can be given of the anchoring points of the scales (the least and most serious offenses and the least and most severe penalties), it appears to offer a workable translation of a theory of punishment into a sentencing scheme. However, the proportionality account of punishment is not without its critics. For “pure” censure-based theorists, the addition of hard treatment as a prudential supplement treats citizens as things to be coerced rather than agents to be reasoned with, and threatens to “drown out” the moral message of the law (see the exchange between Duff and von Hirsch in Matravers 1999). However, even those who accept the necessity of hard treatment as a legitimate part of punishment have queried the usefulness of proportionality as a guiding principle. The criticisms in part focus on the theory’s workability and in part on its implications for sentencing practice. A punishment scheme based on proportionality presumes that we can accurately measure offense seriousness and culpability, and that we can then match that to a point on a penalty severity scale. These things pose a significant challenge to proportionality theorists. In relation to offense seriousness, what is needed is a way to put together on one scale crimes such as assault by an individual and commercial pollution. In relation to culpability, in principle, the theory needs to assess the subjective state of the offender, but in practice may have to rely on objective measures such as the absence or presence of previous convictions. Proportionality theorists are aware of these (and other challenges) and have tried to meet them (Ashworth 2010; von Hirsch and Ashworth 2005), but not everyone is convinced that they have been successful (for a helpful summary of the criticisms, see Tonry 2011b, pp. 224–34). Perhaps even more significant is the need to anchor the scale of penalty severity. The bottom anchoring point – the penalty to be associated with the least serious offense – may be reasonably easy to fix in that many jurisdictions may have something like a police caution. However, what of the upper anchoring point? Should this be capital punishment (or worse), life imprisonment without the possibility of parole, 21 years, or less? Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory Without an answer to this question, the scheme is inadequate. Proportionality theorists have reached for a variety of principled, and socially contingent, ways of fixing the upper anchoring point. As noted above, one might worry, for example, that too severe punishments will “drown out” the moral message conveyed by the law. The problem the account faces is that insofar as the penalty conveys proportionate blame, different societies, with different histories and practices, will think different overall levels of suffering needed to do this accurately. Parsimony In contrast to the equality and proportionality required by the proportionality account, Norval Morris (1974) and others have argued for a principle of parsimony. By “parsimony” it is meant that punishment levels ought in general to be set such as that offenders receive “the least severe sentence consistent with the governing purposes of sentencing” (Tonry 1992, p. 81). In developing this account, Morris and others have come to think of desert as a “limiting” principle (Frase 2004) such that offenders should receive the least severe “not undeserved” sanction from a range in which the upper point is consistent with proportionality, but the lower bounds allow for individualization of sentences and parsimony. Such an account is still hostage to a theory of cardinal desert, but its relative vagueness would, its proponents suggest, at least allow greater justice to be done to each particular offender; justice that would be sacrificed by the fetishizing of proportionality. Exactly that discretion, though, is what bothers proponents of proportionality (perhaps mindful of the way it was used to disadvantage minority groups in the past). Theory and Practice Following the breakdown of the consequentialist consensus in the final third of the twentieth century, broadly retributive theories of punishment took center stage and, by-and-large, remain there (although see the essays in Tonry 2011a). 3495 P The associated “just deserts” movement, and its various political analogues like the campaign for “truth-in-sentencing,” was dominant, but for a shorter period and not without challenge. Throughout the same period, and in particular after the mid-1980s, many sentencing policies that explicitly violated proportionality were passed. Mandatory minimum sentences for drugs offenses, sexual offenses (particularly against children), and possession offenses (particularly of child pornography) have meant that these crimes attract penalties far above those given for what might be thought of as roughly equally serious violent crimes. Another example is California’s notorious three-strikes law, which means that relatively trivial third offenses could attract very severe penalties, and there are many others. As noted above, other less retributive policies – grounded in therapeutic jurisprudence or restorative justice – also flourished in corners of the criminal justice system often because they were perceived to “work”; in particular to reduce recidivism. Very few of these policies can be said to flow directly from a fully worked-out philosophical position on the justification of punishment. Yet, it would be absurd to say that “theory does not matter.” Policies do change as a result of theoretical reflections and will no doubt continue to do so. However, sentencing – perhaps more than any other part of the criminal justice system – is political and pluralistic. It is political in that it is a highly visible and politically controversial. To be “soft on crime” is, in many political systems, to court political disaster (Lacey 2008). It is pluralistic in that, at the point of sentencing, judges in systems where there is discretion will often call upon many considerations (an intuitive notion of desert, the need to express the community’s blame, deterrence, the risk posed by the offender, the offender’s potential for reform, and so on). Such pluralism can sit ill with philosophers of punishment who seek solutions which are logically consistent and morally coherent and defensible. That said, precisely because crime is a politically sensitive issue, and because in P P 3496 many jurisdictions, judges are limited in their discretion by mandatory sentences or restrictive sentencing guidelines, it is vital that moral and penal philosophers continue to subject sentencing rationales to critical analysis. And, in doing so, they will inevitably call on overall accounts of the general purpose, and justification, of punishment even if those accounts do not always translate easily into particular sentencing outcomes. Recommended Reading and References Ashworth A (2010) Sentencing and criminal justice, 5th edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Bentham J (1843) Principles of penal law. In: Bowring J (ed) The works of Jeremy Bentham, 1st edn. William Tait, Edinburgh Bentham J (1970) In: Fred R, Philip S (eds) An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Oxford University Press, Oxford Bottoms A, von Hirsch A (2011) The crime preventive impact of penal sanctions. In: Cane P, Kritzer H (eds) The Oxford handbook of empirical legal research. Oxford University Press, Oxford Doob AN, Webster CM (2003) Sentence severity and crime: accepting the null hypothesis. Crime Justice 30:143–195 (ArticleType: research-article/Full publication date: 2003/Copyright # 2003 The University of Chicago Press) Duff RA (1986) Trials and punishments. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Duff RF (2007) Answering for crime: responsibility and liability in the criminal law. Hart Publishing, Oxford Feinberg J (1970) The expressive function of punishment. In: Doing and deserving: essays in the theory of responsibility. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 95–118 Frankel ME (1972) Criminal sentences: law without order. Hill and Wang, New York Frase R (2004) Limiting retributivism. In: Tonry M (ed) The future of imprisonment. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 83–120 Goodin R (1995) Utilitarianism as a public philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Hart HLA (1968) Punishment and responsibility: essays in the philosophy of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford Kleinig J (1973) Punishment and desert. Springer, New York Lacey N (2008) The prisoners’ dilemma: political economy and punishment in contemporary democracies. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Lewis CS (1949) The humanitarian theory of punishment. 20 Century Aust Q Rev 3(3):5–12 Penal Philosophy and Sentencing Theory Matravers M (1999) Punishment and political theory. Hart Publishing, Oxford Matravers M (2000) Justice and punishment: the rationale of coercion. Oxford University Press, Oxford Matravers M (2011) Is twenty-first century punishment post-desert? In: Tonry M (ed) Retributivism has a past: has it a future? Oxford University Press, New York McCloskey H (1968) A non-utilitarian apporach to punishment. In: Bayles M (ed) Contemporary utilitarianism. Doubleday, New York, pp 239–259 Michael J, Adler M (1933) Crime, law and social science. Harcourt, Brace, New York Monahan J (2004) The future of violence risk management. In: Tonry M (ed) The future of imprisonment. Oxford University Press, New York Moore M (1987) The moral worth of retribution. In: Schoemann F (ed) Responsibility, character and the emotions. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 179–219 Moore M (1997) Placing blame: a general theory of the criminal law. Oxford University Press, Oxford Morris N (1974) The future of imprisonment. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Morse SJ (1999) Neither desert nor disease. Legal Theory 5:265–309 Posner RA (1985) An economic theory of criminal law. Columbia Law Rev 85:1193–1195 Rawls J (1955/1999) Two concepts of rules. In: Rawls J, Freeman SR (eds) Collected papers. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 20–46 Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Robinson P, Darley J (2003) The role of deterrence in the formulation of criminal law rules: at its worst when doing its best. Georgetown Law J 91:949 Robinson P, Darley J (2004) Does criminal law deter? A behavioural science investigation. Oxf J Legal Stud 24:173–205 Tonry M (1992) Proportionality, parsimony, and interchangeability of punishments. In: Duff A et al (eds) Penal theory and penal practice. Manchester University Press, Manchester Tonry M (2011a) Retributivism has a past: has it a future? Oxford University Press, New York Tonry M (ed) (2011b) Why punish? How much?: a reader on punishment. Oxford University Press, New York von Hirsch A (1993) Censure and sanctions. Clarendon Press, Oxford von Hirsch A (1999) Criminal deterrence and sentence severity : an analysis of recent research. Hart, Oxford/Portland von Hirsch A, Ashworth A (2005) Proportionate sentencing : exploring the principles. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York von Hirsch A, Committee for the Study of Incarceration (1976) Doing justice: the choice of punishments: report of the Committee for the Study of Incarceration, 1st edn. Hill and Wang, New York Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Walker N (1969) Sentencing in a rational society. Allen Lane/The Penguin Press, London Wexler DB (2008) Rehabilitating lawyers: principles of therapeutic jurisprudence for criminal law practice. Carolina Academic Press, Durham Winick B (1997) The jurisprudence of therapeutic jurisprudence. Psychol Public Policy Law 3(1):184–206 Wootton B (1978) Crime and penal policy: reflections on fifty years’ experience. George Allen & Unwin, London 3497 P Personal Control: Criminal Behavior, Social Control, Self-Control, Models, Constraints ▶ Control Theory Personalized Policing ▶ Community Policing Penalties ▶ Sentencing Research Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Perceptions of Risk ▶ Rational Choice, Deterrence, and Crime: Sociological Contributions Camilla Hald Danish National Police, Research & Development, Copenhagen, Denmark Overview Perceptual Updating ▶ Bayesian Updating and Crime Performance Management ▶ Judicial Leadership and Performance Perpetrator Characteristics ▶ Estimator Identification Variables and Eyewitness Persistent Offenders ▶ Career Criminals and Criminological Theory In recent years controversies have arisen over the definition and demarcation of science in relation to forensic science. These controversies are among other expressed in debates following a report from the National Academy of Sciences in the US, questioning the scientific status of forensics and its interpretations of evidence before courts of law. The controversies highlight an apparent incommensurability of the two fields of knowledge straddled by the forensic process: science and law. These controversies are however as old as science and law, respectively, and can be traced in the major philosophical principles’ underpinning, shaping, and informing the origins and the characteristics of the forensic process. The philosophical basis of the forensic process consists of a meshwork of ideas. It originates from and is influenced by a range of different disciplines, models of inquiry, and forms of validating truth claims, which have been decisive in bringing the P P 3498 discipline about. Some major ones runs from divination, classical rhetoric, theology, law, philology, philosophy, history and the arts, over the model of Galilean science, medicine, psychotherapy, art connoisseurship, the infant social science and statistics, to natural sciences such as biology and chemistry, and, new philosophies of science born from these disciplines. Following the trajectories of thought illuminates how there is a philosophical basis to the controversies. The forensic process is informed by ideas from two different models of science. One is a model of science based on identifying and interpreting “signs”, the other is one based on observation and verification of general facts. Each model plays a significant part in the workings of the forensic process. The lack of acknowledgement of the contributions from each, however, plays a major part in the controversies. Hence the way forward may prove to be related to attaining a more nuanced understanding of the philosophical roots of the forensic process as well as in incorporating each model equally into the theoretical and operational framework of the discipline. Key Issues/Controversies The forensic process is the process of inquiry belonging to forensic science. Forensic science is most often defined as an applied science, whose raison d’eˆtre is to provide scientific analysis of evidence in the service of law. The forensic process is part of the investigative inquiry carried out within the legal process which is oriented toward providing answers to questions essential to the legal deliberation and arbitration of cases. This however is not a straightforward business, since the questions asked and the methods of supplying answers differ markedly between law and science. Put crudely, the ultimate goal of legal inquiries is to establish “what happened” (how, when, where, and why) and “who did it” in a given case under scrutiny. The goal of inquiry of the sciences is however rather to establish “what a given phenomenon is” and “how it works.” Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Also the methods of inquiry, and for validating “truth” differ between law and science. Legal inquiry makes use of qualitative methods, testimonial evidence, and a judgment of and deliberation between, probable arguments derived here from, whereas the sciences use observation and experiments, favoring the quantifiable, reproducible, and empirically verifiable. Differences between law and science are grounded in a difference between the object and goal of inquiry of each discipline. The legal process deals with questions of a social, moral, and cultural kind and in the deliberation of individual cases in which truth is of an approximate kind as versed in the dictum “beyond reasonable doubt.” Natural science (with which forensic science is most commonly associated and from which the most influential forensic techniques and forms of analysis originates: physics, molecular biology, chemistry, etc.) deals with questions about nature, its laws, and general characteristics to the point of establishing the truth about it in a more absolute sense. The knowledge sought by science is one which may be reproduced independent of the particular researcher or situation, and from which it is possible to predict results based on true premises. Thus for law the goal of inquiry is the most reasonable explanation for particular events, while the goal of scientific inquiry is the universal truth about “what is.” These two fields of knowledge is straddled by the forensic process, in which legal questions must be translated into scientific questions in order to provide scientific answers which may inform legal argumentation and deliberation (see Fig. 1). Forensic science and its role in legal deliberation is in other words a matter of using science in the service of law and legal deliberation, to help establish “matters of fact” which may aid the process of deliberating between “probable arguments”. Evidence produced through the forensic process is thus also submitted to different forms of validation in different contexts and phases of the process. Within the laboratory, evidence is evaluated according to the soundness of analysis and integrity of the process of analysis (an uncompromised chain of custody and accuracy Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process 3499 P LAW RECONSTRUCTIVE (his)’STORY’ of the CASE presented before competent tribunal According to the 6Ws: “WHO”, “WHAT”, “WHERE”, “HOW”, “WHEN”, “WHY” Investigative inquiry into ‘matters of fact’ FORENSIC SCIENCE TESTIMONIAL EVIDENCE REAL EVIDENCE to ‘facts’ of case ‘Story’/testimony of the ‘thing’ Refinement phase Examination of exhibit EXHIBIT recovered from scene SCENE INVESTIGATION Testing phase Investigative phase ‘Thing’ at scene Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process, Fig. 1 The forensic process – science in service of law (From Tilstone et al. 2012) of instruments and methods applied) in order to assure the scientific “rigor” of the results through recognized methods of analysis and scientific procedures for testing. Within the legal process, the evidence is in addition to the assurance of the integrity of analysis and evidence, evaluated for their meaning in relation to the legal argumentation presented before a court of law. The former demands that what is infered from the evidence is verifiable and stand up to tests in accordance with scientifically acknowledged theories and methods. The latter demands that evidence is seen in the context of the case and the circumstances surrounding the actions or event in question and is based on evaluation of possible or probable causes or sources of particular forms of evidence. The evidential value of the information provided through scientific analysis and the professional judgment of the analyst is, in other words, ultimately decided in the context of the case and the legal process of deliberating between the arguments presented by the advocates of prosecution and defense. This fundamental condition of the forensic process has resulted in intense debates about the role of the forensic scientist in providing service to law by analyzing and interpreting physical evidence. Questions such as: How this is done; where the boundaries of professional judgments in interpreting the evidence, are set and how far the forensic analyst may stretch in order to help answer the questions of the legal process – and how the authority and integrity of the scientist should be assessed – are however subject to different interpretations. Within forensic science itself, tensions are evident in the way that different schools have arisen, especially within criminalistics, each school emphasizing the role of the forensic analyst differently, as well as the degree to which criminalistics should be defined by the needs and methods of law versus those of the pure sciences (Inman and Rudin 2001). These inherent tensions have become more obvious in the United States, in the wake of a report from the National Academy of Sciences: Strengthening Forensic Science in the United States: A Path Forward (2009), evaluating the P P 3500 field of forensic science. The report raises many issues and questions echoing debates, which have a long history – both within forensic science disciplines and beyond. These are issues such as: that the current forensic science system is not based on science; that the analysis is frequently subjective; and that the same technique used by different analysts can lead to different results, just as the same technique used by the same analyst on the same sample at different points in time and in different contexts can lead to a different result, and that anecdotal information, phrased like “In my training, knowledge, and experience.. . .” makes its way into the courtroom. Reactions to the NAS report have been swift and all across the board from those that deny that there is anything wrong, to those who have adopted the NAS report and endeavored to suggest new modes of operation to improve on the lack of scientific rigor and culture of forensics, especially within criminalistics (e.g., Mnookin et al. 2011). The report does however not deal with the fundamental philosophical basis of the forensic process, Therefore there is no recognition of the philosophical roots of this debate, and the fact that the issues have existed in different forms since well before the development of the different disciplines of forensic science. In order to understand the controversies a proper historical and theoretical context is needed. The purpose of the entry is therefore to explore the major philosophical principles that have inspired and shaped the forensic process. Given that the word “forensic” in contemporary use has two meanings: (a) as a form of legal evidence and (b) as a short term for forensic science or criminalistics (forensics), this entry will inspect the philosophical history along two trajectories. Firstly, through a visitation of the history of legal rhetoric – the predecessor of modern law – secondly, through the history of the growth of science and the scientific method and the philosophical “goods” being, respectively, embraced and discarded in the process. Ultimately, it is in the combined history of these two trajectories of thought that the philosophical basis of the forensic process is to be found. Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Fundamentals of Legal History The Art of Rhetoric: The Foundation of Modern Law Etymology is a proper place to start when digging for the roots and the philosophical basis of the forensic process. The word “forensic” originates from the Latin adjective forensis, meaning “of or before the forum.” In Roman times, a criminal charge meant presenting the case before a group of public individuals in the forum. Both the person accused of the crime and the accuser would be represented by an advocate giving speeches on their behalf, presenting their side of the matter. The individual with the best argument and delivery would succeed. This origin is the source of the modern usage of the word “forensic” to denote a form of legal evidence (forensic evidence) and as a short representation of “forensic science,” that is, science related to and of relevance to courts (forensics). Historically, courts of law (forums or public assemblies) were intimately connected to rhetoric. In classical Greece, rhetoric was taught to citizens so that they could defend themselves in the court and deliberate in the assembly. In Rome, advocates (called logographs) used oratory to plead on behalf of their clients before the forum. Law, as a subject of its own, did not emerge until the twelfth century (Schoeck 1983), and law students continued to be educated in rhetoric well into the Early Modern period (Balkin 1996). A key element of the art of rhetoric was how to find and present arguments in a case to be presented before a court of peers. To guide the search for arguments and proofs to their fact, which would persuade the court to find the case presented by the rhetorician the most believable and worthy of support, the Ancient Greeks developed a meticulous system or inventory of possible forms and modes of argument to this end, also known as topoi or in English “topics.” The following presents a brief history of the origins of the topics and their incorporation into modern legal procedure and the forensic process of which the topics form the backbone. The Topics of Classical Rhetoric The first attempts at setting out guidelines for those who were to investigate and present cases Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process before a tribunal of decision makers seems to be dated back to one of the deemed founders of the modern art of rhetoric, Hermagoras of Temnos (300 BC). Hermagoras divided the materials of rhetoric into two parts: thesis and hypothesis. A thesis involves an abstract, general question, whereas a hypothesis involves a question concerning concrete particulars. Hermagoras provided a list of circumstances which needed to be addressed in order to form hypotheses and to be able to demonstrate their truth-value, in the form of a list of questions. He contended that no hypothetical question or questions involving particular persons and acts can arise without reference to these circumstances, and no demonstration of such a question can be made without using them. The questions defining Hermagoras’ circumstances are known only in Latin because they arose as part of the theological writings of St. Augustine recognizing Hermagoras as the original source. St. Augustine quoted Hermagoras’ questions in Latin as follows: quis, quid, quando, ubi, cur, quem ad modum, quibus adminiculis (who, what, when, where, why, how, in what way, and by what means/which aids) (Robertson 1946). Hermagoras’ list of questions for producing hypothesis and proof is a mnemonic device intended to provide a systematic methodology to the task of producing rhetorical evidence (proof). This form of mnemonic belongs to a part of the methodology of the discipline of rhetoric, derived from Aristotle, known as topoi – or “the topics” – of which he was the first to write systematically about. The word “topic” originates from the Greek word topos (pl. topoi), meaning “place,” and refers to the “places” (on the mind’s horizon) where one can go to look for and discover the relevant arguments (i.e., get ideas for argumentation). In Latin, the topics are referred to as loci (places) or loci communes – meaning the “common places.” The use of the word topos/topoi may refer to the ancient mnemonic principle of using “spatial locations” or “activities” by which to remember even complex or huge amounts of information. One may for instance remember a long list of dinner guests by 3501 P imagining them around the table. Generally, the word “topics” is commonly used to refer both to the actual “places” where one can go to find material for arguments and to the methodology of the process of searching these places. The topics have since their very conception in classical rhetorical theory been a very confused concept, not easily defined and incorporating a bewildering diversity of meanings. Initially, “Topics” is the title of a treatise of Aristotle on the art of dialectic – the invention and discovery of arguments in which the propositions rest upon commonly held opinion or what he termed endoxa (Aristotle 384–322 BC). These commonly held beliefs, the topoi or “topics,” are not merely popular notions held by any given individual in a city or culture about any and all subjects. Rather, they are elements of reason upon which those who conscientiously dispute agree in principle, i.e., that which is firmly embedded within opinion or belief among those who engage in disputation. The topics belong according to Aristotle to the art of rhetoric, in which they inform the invention and discovery of arguments (Aristotle and LawsonTancred 1991). Aristotle’s theory of the topics emphasized a particular aspect of evidence related to forming and proving hypotheses. Hypotheses was thought to belong to the form of inference pertaining to “practical knowledge” (techne´ and phronesis) which was opposed to “theoretical knowledge” (episteme). Aristotle contended that when lacking the certainty and necessity of the true premises described in the syllogism and logic, one needed to take point of departure in commonly held beliefs which could be viewed as “law-like” in nature because of their general acceptance as “true.” The concept of topics to Aristotle was thus both (a) a minutely devised inventory or system of cases, in which one might profitably take point of departure when devising the argument and providing for them and (b) the theory of hypothesis building and testing within the area of rhetoric, to which they pertained. Thus when a “belief” is considered of a high level of generality, i.e., being “common sense”, it belongs to the topoi. P P 3502 The Philosophical History of the Topics The ideas of rhetoric conceived by the Ancient Greeks were spread and became known to the rest of the European continent up through the Middle Ages and during the Renaissance. They were distributed through the works of Roman advocates and orators and the treatises they drafted in the language of church and scholars: Latin. A key figure in the history of European rhetoric and philosophy, linking Classical philosophy and Medieval and Renaissance thinking, was the Latin rhetorician Cicero (106–43 BC) and his works Topica, De Oratore and De Inventione. Cicero divides his work on the circumstances into two parts: attributes of the person (personae) and attributes of the act (factum). As attributes of the person, he lists nomen, naturam, victum, fortunam, habitum, affectionem, studia, consilia, facta, casus and rationes as the topics to consider in building a credible statement of the case, but more importantly, to develop the arguments which should make the main body of the text or speech, and according to which the logical arguments of the case should be elaborated. Attributes of the action are of three kinds: those concerning the performance of the action itself, those related to the action, and those consequent upon the action; only the first of these reflects the system of Hermagoras. In relation to the action itself, Cicero names locus, tempus, modus, occasio and facultas (Robertson 1946). The most important discussion of the topics, considering their relation to legal rhetoric, is made by Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius (ca. 480–524 AD) in the early Middle Ages. Boethius, in his influential writings De differentiis topicus, makes the seven topics (or circumstances) fundamental to the arts of prosecution and defense. The loci proper to rhetoric are confined to the attributes of the person who is called for judgment and those of the act or statement for which he is to be judged. All arguments, either in the defense of the person or for his prosecution, must be taken from these materials. Thus, Boethius associated the topics with the process of determining the extent of guilt of a person accused of violating legal rules or customs, which may be significant to the adoption of Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process these by papal forums and priests in their work with ascertaining as accurately as possible the magnitude of each sin confessed to them. The topics arise in a new guise in the pastoral and theoretical theology in the thirteenth century, as Mnemonic verses consisting of variations of Hermagoras questions. This is evident in the 21st canon of the Fourth Lateral Council arranged by Pope Innocent III, which stipulated that confessors should diligently seek out et peccatoris circumstantias et peccati (the circumstances of the sin and of the sinner) – resembling to no small extent Cicero’s person and act personis et negotiis – in order that they might justly weigh the sins confessed to them and administer suitable remedies. This appropriation of the topics to theological matters and theological inquisitorial processes can be attributed the theological writings of St. Augustine (Augustine of Hippo) and Thomas Aquinas. Verses made of the questions in different variations, afforded a flexible instrument for interrogation. It allowed the priest to associate conventional theological divisions of the sins with the questions so that they afforded a frame of reference against which to place his theological knowledge. In this way they provided a practical device for spontaneous and quick analysis (Robertson 1946, pp. 6–7). The topics were then revived by Renaissance rhetoricians, such as Thomas Wilson, The Art of Rhetorique, who made an English verse of them: “Who, what, and where, by what helps, and by whose: Why how, and when, doe many things disclose” (cit. in Robertson 1946, p. 14). A principle of such fundamental importance to both rhetoric and theology soon spread to other areas of literary work and studies. Italian writers adapted them to historiography. One of the important figures in Renaissance rhetoric Giambattista Vico (1668–1744), trained in jurisprudence, but widely read in Classics, philology, and philosophy, all of which informed his highly original views on history, historiography, and culture, revisited the topics in his mature work: Scienza Nuova (or The New Science). In this work he argued for a central role of the topics in all disciplines including the sciences – even mathematics. Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Vico’s point was that “topics” is not to be learned from a book but is more akin to a disposition whereby one has analogies and arguments at one’s hand. Thus for the doctor the topics provide ready mental access to the stock of medical precedents that have historically enabled successful diagnosis and treatment, and to the mathematician pressing the boundaries of knowledge further, the topics consist of the accepted theories preceding the development of new hypotheses. Vico found that the principle described in the use of the topics was to be considered a necessary part of making judgments about everyday life in general, and that their cultivation is required for creative discovery and quick action in all disciplines, from physics to law. In his own time, Vico was relatively unknown, but from the nineteenth century onward where the methodology and philosophical content of rhetorics and linguistics converged with other developments in the history of ideas giving rise to new critical theories in the philosophy of science, his views found a wider audience. Today his influence is widespread in the humanities as well as in the social sciences. Before delineating this turn, tying the knot between the two histories of ideas by describing how they inform the growth of forensic science and the philosophical basis of the forensic process as it looks today, a brief history of the fundamentals in the development of science is called for. Fundamentals of the Philosophical History of Forensic Science Science and the Conjectural Model: The Foundation of Forensic Science Forensic science is intimately related to investigative inquiry through the forensic process. Investigation comes from Latin investigationem meaning “a searching into, a searching for.” The noun stems from investigare “to trace out, search after” which again is composited from in “in, into” and vestigare “to track, trace” from vestigium “footprint, track.” The etymology of the word “investigate” carries the seed to 3503 P an understanding of the philosophical roots of crime investigations and the forensic process, by referring to “tracks and traces” and “footprints,” since the roots of science and of medical, legal, and forecasting sciences in particular, may well be rooted in the first efforts of interpreting footprints in the sand or the tracks of wildlife in the forests, with the aim to hunt it down and slay it. The point being that the philosophical basis of the forensic process has a deep-rooted connection to semiotics and other sciences informed by what may be termed the “semiotic paradigm” – which we shall get back to shortly. Firstly, let us briefly return to etymology as a starting point for the philosophical basis of the forensic process stemming from the history of science. The root of the word “science” is the Latin scire, to know, and hence scientia, or knowledge. Before the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, the word denoted any kind of knowledge, undiscriminating between different forms or types of knowledge. However, with the Enlightenment and the introduction of scientific method plus the resurgence of learning based on classical theory during the Renaissance, the word scientia came to mean knowledge of the natural world and became increasingly associated with natural science. The Italian historian Carlo Ginzburg traces the trajectory of what he terms the “conjectural or evidential paradigm” throughout European history, attempting to excavate the historical lineage of “disciplines based on reading the evidence” (Ginzburg 1980, p. 14). Since this history is rarely researched, the exposition of this part of the philosophical history of the forensic process is resumed from his seminal piece: Morelli, Freud and Sherlock Holmes: Clues and Scientific Method (1980). The roots of this paradigm, Ginzburg argues, can be found well beyond the civilizations of Ancient Greece with the earliest hunters and the skills they developed for reading signs in nature to track down the game and in the Mesopotamian cultures different forms of divination. These skills he argues, played a significant role in the invention of writing and the capacity for abstract thinking, which is based on the use of P P 3504 purposefully crafted signs to represent inherent meanings. The common characteristics of these roots of skills leading onward to modern science, are that, both traditions, hunting and divination, “require minute examination of the real, however trivial, to uncover the traces of events which the observer cannot directly experience” (Ginzburg 1980, p. 13). The way hunters used their senses – sniffing, listening, and observing – to give meaning and context to the slightest trace, “in the shadowy and treacherous clearing,” Ginzburg argues, endowed them with the ability to make complex calculations in an instant. Hunters inferred from part to whole, effect to cause. The Mesopotamian model of divination gradually intensified this tendency to generalize from basic facts, thus strengthening this mode of inferring cause from effect. The model for explanation and divination decipherable in Mesopotamian texts is one which could be oriented toward past, present, or future, depending on which form of knowledge was called upon. Seeking signs to form knowledge oriented toward the future, was divination proper. Orientation toward the past was related to jurisprudence or the body of legal knowledge. Divination oriented towards the past, present, and future in concert was that of medical knowledge of symptoms. The latter contained all of the orientations by way of its double character of diagnosis, explaining past and present, and prognosis, suggesting the likely future following from the illness running its course. The conjectural paradigm lies at the root of modern science in general. It is, however, the development into scientific disciplines of these original practical arts (hunting, divination, medicine, and law) of deciphering various signs and symptoms as well as individual cases to infer generalized meanings, which serves to characterize the philosophical basis of the forensic process in the Modern Age. It is however not well researched nor generally acknowledged how these artistic aspects of producing knowledge inform the growth of science and ultimately forensic science. Retracing this history is however the goal in the following. Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Ancient Greek Philosophy: The Cradle of Modern Science What characterized the Greek culture and the city-states, of which Modern European legal culture and science are heirs, was the emergence of a group of disciplines which all “depended on the deciphering of various kinds of signs, from symptoms to writing” (Ginzburg 1980, p. 14). Passing on to the civilizations of ancient Greece, these disciplines changed considerably, giving rise to new lines of study such as history and philology while acquiring also independence from older disciplines, such as medicine. In and through these disciplines, one finds the seeds of the development of a general scientific stance or method. Through these disciplines the “body” (e.g., medicine), “speech” (e.g., rhetoric, philology), and “history” were all for the first time subjected to dispassionate investigation, excluding the possibility of divine intervention. An important part of this change can, according to Ginzburg, be ascribed to a model of knowledge acquisition based on symptoms and signs – the evidential or “conjectural model” of knowledge. This development is most evident in the case of Hippocratic medicine. Hippocrates’ model of medicine based its central methods on the concept of “the symptom”, in Greek semeion (hence semiotics). The central tenet in the Hippocratic model was the idea that by carefully observing and registering every symptom, it was possible to establish precise histories of each disease, despite the fact that the disease as an entity would remain intangible. The insistence on the evidential nature of medicine, prevalent with the Hippocratic model, probably stemmed from a distinction between the certainty of divine knowledge and the provisional, conjectural nature of human knowledge, expounded by the Pythagorean doctor, Alcmaeon of Croton in his work Peri Physeos (or On nature). This was the first scientific treatise devoted to the art of medicine. The work itself has not been preserved, but its contents and chief findings have been passed on by commentators and collectors of ancient knowledge such as Aristotle, Theophrastus, and Aetius. From these it is known that Alcmaeon held that if reality was not Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process necessarily clear – then by implication – it was right to proceed by building up knowledge of the whole from the parts, using conjecture. Proceeding by using conjecture was in fact the most common approach in a number of spheres of activity in Ancient Greece, where physicians, historians, politicians, potters, joiners, mariners, hunters, fishermen, and women in general were held to be adept in the vast areas of conjectural knowledge. This conjectural or semiotic paradigm, continued however to be merely implicit up through the ages, since it was completely overshadowed by Plato’s theory of knowledge, holding sway in more influential circles, hence shrouded in more prestige. Plato’s theory of knowledge emphasized the existence of an ideal (i.e., ideational) world of universal untainted truth existing independently of the human species and lost to the human subject. To Plato, knowledge could only be regained or recollected (anamnesis) through inspired contemplation and philosophy. The Science of the Universal and the Problem of the Individual While Ancient Greece and the developments of disciplines of dispassionate investigation of various subjects and forms, may be the cradle of modern science, the genesis of scientific method is generally acknowledged to be the Middle Ages. The emergence of a truly scientific paradigm is commonly associated with Galileo (1564–1642). The scientific paradigm based on, but outliving, Galileo, provided significant changes in the concepts of “rigor” and “science.” The model of Galilean science was fundamentally different from any of the disciplines using conjecture to form knowledge of their subject. None of these would meet the criteria of scientific inference set out by the Galilean approach. The ancient disciplines were concerned with the qualitative, the individual and the case particular, i.e., the individual body, document or situation itself. Galilean physics were altogether different. It used mathematics and experimental method to gain knowledge of the universal order of nature. This was in stark contrast to the conjectural 3505 P model of the Ancient disciplines in the results of which there was always an element of chance (Ginzburg 1980, p. 15). In the science that grew from the Galilean model, chance was sought tamed by a dependence on measurement and repetition of results. Creating knowledge by induction from experimental design and observation of results, science increasingly became associated with the need to measure and repeat phenomena in order to draw rigorous conclusions about the phenomenal world. Paradigms following the Galilean tradition were concerned alone with knowledge of the universal and generalizable, while being unable to say anything about the individual and particular. The rise of the scientific paradigm resulted in a division of fields of knowledge which would meet the criteria of scientific inference set by and essential to the Galilean approach, and those who could not. A host of the classical disciplines could not meet or make do with the criteria set for science by the new scientific paradigm. However, one discipline in particular diverged from the rest, proclaiming its scientific status while drawing on a model of inquiry stemming from the conjectural or semiotic model – medicine. The philosophical history of forensic science leads in many ways directly to an origin in medicine. This is generally acknowledged not least in the fact that subjects of medicine such as the autopsy and toxicology are some of the first forms of knowledge enrolled in the service of law to decide on the issues of identifying and discriminating between a criminal act and a legitimate or natural one. However, there are more subtle philosophical roots to be discerned from the relation between medicine and the forensic process as a process of inquiry and theory of knowledge. The Rise of the Semiotic Model The trajectories of thought and ideas informing the move from hunter to the scientific detective are manifold and diverse. It is therefore not possible to delineate them in detail here. However, their different results may be indicated by zooming in more directly on the common P P 3506 denominator through which they all at some point pass – medical science and the paradigms informing it. The roots of this paradigm may, following Ginzburg, be traced to the contemporaries of Galileo and described through a historical event in which the medical expertise was enrolled to decide on the nature of a new phenomenon: a two-headed calf born outside of Rome in April 1625. The event became object for discussion among a group of naturalists in the Vatican Belvedere Garden, which was documented in detail by Giovanni Faber (a friend of Galileo and secretary of the Lincei Academy, a center of a thriving intellectual group founded in 1603 by Frederico Cesi). The discussion was attended besides Faber, by another friend of Galileo, a Cardinal, Pope Urbano VIII, and the pope’s chief medical man, a physician from Siena, Giulio Mancini (Ginzburg 1980, p. 20). Mancini was besides being a brilliant diagnostician renowned for his ability to divine the seat of disease by a rapid look at the patient, also a keen intellectual and the author of a book about art recognition titled: Considerazioni sulla pittura (or Some considerations concerning painting as an amusement for a noble gentleman and introducing what needs to be said) (Mancini ed. Marucchi 1956–1957 ref. in Ginzburg 1980). Part of this book was devoted to the recognition of paintings, and set out a method for telling originals from copies, by recognizing the particular strokes of the hand of the master in areas of the painting that were swiftly executed. The underlying assumption of Mancini’s views, were never stated, but were nevertheless important to the later development of connoisseurship in the century to follow and its role in transmitting the semiotic model to other areas of European cultural life and knowledge, Ginzburg argues. The core assumption of deep relevance to the rise of the conjectural paradigm was that there are ineradicable differences between a canvas painted by the hand of Rafael, for example, and any copy of it (Ginzburg 1980, p. 20). The discussion between the parties participating in the event represents a historical example of differing perspectives of different disciplines on Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process the individual case and its relation to the general, as well as a moment in the history of a converging of differing paradigms, embodied in the practitioner of medicine and art connoisseur Giulio Mancini. The first question addressed by the group was whether the animal should count as one animal or two. For the physicians the feature distinguishing the individual was the brain, whereas for followers of Aristotle it was the heart. To some extent, Mancini in the discussion of the two-headed calf represents a point of contact between the divinatory approach of the conjectural paradigm (as a diagnostician and a connoisseur) and the generalizing model of the Galilean approach to physics (as anatomist and naturalist). He represents the emergence of a generalizing paradigm within medicine while at the same time being the skilled artistically inclined diagnostician, reading the signs of the disease in the bodies of the patient or identifying the hand of the master versus that of the copyist in a piece of art. By adopting the role of the physician, Mancini was ascertaining the character of the individual as a “type” (i.e., within a scheme of classification) rather than of the character of the individual calf itself. The physician, in other words, participated with a view to arrive at a more accurate definition of what was normal – and therefore repeatable for the individual of the species, i.e., establishing the “common character” of it rather than the one peculiar to it (Ginzburg 1980). The medical paradigm that developed through the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries thus consisted of two paradigmatic models – the anatomical model and the semiotic model (Foucault and Sheridan 1973). The first aspired for a system of knowledge which could be generalized and ascertained through empirical observation and classification (continuing the natural history starting with Aristotle) and making use of the organ associated with the sciences of the time, which could not be reduced to numbers and mathematical calculation: sight. Vision and observations became synonymous with “objectivity” – the defining character of empirical science (Daston and Galison 2007). Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process The second model of medicine aspired for an effective diagnostics which were able to identify and treat illnesses in individual cases (Foucault and Sheridan 1973) and thus keep the subject alive, healthy, and maintain a productive population to the benefit of the state (Foucault and Sheridan 1979). The conjectural or semiotic model of medicine was, however, intimately connected with knowledge of the general, in the form evoked by the anatomical model. The latter was based on the dissection of corpses and the description of the anatomy of the human body. This practice was used to create knowledge of the general character of the human body, which in turn could be used as a general norm against which pathology could measure the particular body’s deviance or abnormalities to achieve new knowledge of pathologies and their effects and signs in the human body. The anatomical model, and its knowledge of the general achieved from observations and generalizations of many individual bodies was promoted and spread through the medical atlases, which became a significant artifact through which medical science flourished (Daston and Galison 1992). It did so in coexistence and mutual development with a semiotic model of medicine, based in the clinic, and the experience and knowledge of the emergence, courses, symptoms, and effects of different illnesses, which arose from the diagnostician’s effort to device the proper treatment in each individual case (Foucault and Sheridan 1973). In a similar way, the discussions and the tiny incisions made in the animal to reveal the internal organs representing the roots of the modern scientific autopsy, which developed during the Renaissance, represents the meetings of divination and science in the anatomical model of medicine. In a review article of the history of the autopsy, King and Meehan (1973) find its roots in former practices of divination using animal organs, the so-called haruspicy. Autopsy, which literally means “seeing for oneself,” reflects the central role of sight referred to above, as the key component of the scientific method of “observation” and scientific objectivity. “Seeing,” however, here has roots of a different kind, namely, that of ancient diviners 3507 P looking for signs to foretell the future by the reading of organs and tissues of dead animals. The medical atlases of the nineteenth century thus also had a predecessor in Babylonian models of livers with diagrammatic markings used for the instruction of diviners. The predicament of medical science, that is, its apparent lack of absolute scientific rigor and certainty while aspiring to be a science proper, can be said to have two basic reasons. On the one hand, there is a discrepancy between theory and practice. Theoretically adequate descriptions of particular diseases are not necessarily so in practice, where diseases can present itself in different ways in different bodies. On the other hand, knowledge of disease in the living body remains indirect and conjectural, since it is per definition out of reach (Ginzburg 1980, p. 21). Medicine and the Birth of the Detective It was however from the diagnostic branch of medicine that the ideas giving birth to both detective fiction and forensic science originated. In the late nineteenth century, there was a general upsurge in the semiotic paradigm, giving birth to the practice of art connoisseurship, the theories of psychotherapy, and the detective novel. There are actual biographical and inspirational links between the key figures representing each of the three, in the form of Giovanni Morelli, Sigmund Freud, and Arthur Conan Doyle. The connecting factor between them is medicine. Freud was a doctor, Morelli had a degree in medicine, and it is generally acknowledged that the inspiration for Sherlock Holmes was Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s esteemed professor in medical school (he was a doctor before he started writing) Professor Joseph Bell. Bell was renowned for his diagnostic abilities, and there are key passages in the stories of Sherlock Holmes, for example. The Cardboard Box (1892), where Holmes uses the actual methods of Morelli. Furthermore the peculiar similarity of the activities of Holmes and Freud have been discussed in literature (e.g., Marcus 1976). At the same time however, they represent a point in history where the semiotic model (or the conjectural paradigm) resulted in different P P 3508 ideational developments, all however sharing a common feature, namely, that they were based on an interpretive method where one takes the evidence at hand as “signs” which stands for something else otherwise inaccessible for observation. In psychotherapy, art connoisseurship, and detective fiction, methods were devised which made tiny details the key to a deeper reality or knowledge hereof that are inaccessible by other methods. These details may be symptoms for Freud, clues for Holmes, or features of paintings for Morelli, but in all three cases they are seen as evidence to inferences about the nature and characteristics of something hidden to the inquirer: the psyche, the identity of the criminal and the structure of the criminal event, or the identity of the painter and the characteristics of his paintings, behind a given piece of art. Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s character Sherlock Holmes has been deemed inspirational for one or more of the pioneers in forensic science in the area of criminalistics, such as Bertillon and Locard. Whether or not this is a historical fact, we encounter also in the foundation of the field of forensics the medical common factor, as Locard’s teacher and mentor was Alexandre Lacassagne, a physician and chair of Me´decine Le´gale de la Faculte´ de Lyon, and, Bertillon the son of a medical professor. However, developments within the natural and social sciences occurring at the same time were also influenced by the conjectural paradigm and the problem of the individual. Thus the semiotic or conjectural paradigm generated forensic science from several trajectories of thought, which in concert gave rise to the idea of the scientific detective and the forensic process. The Social Sciences and the Rise of Technologies of Government The problem of the individual in the generalizing Galilean model of science was encountered from another field of knowledge, namely, that of the emerging social sciences. During the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, a tendency evolved for the state to impose a close-meshed net of control on society: one based on knowing its individual members and submitting them to forms of Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process surveillance that became increasingly more subtle and that was based on knowledge of its population, statistical as well as biographical (Foucault 1970; Foucault and Gordon 1980; Foucault et al. 2007, 2008; Foucault and Sheridan 1979). With the emergence of a capitalist economy based on production in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century, new concepts of property and the introduction of a still greater number of punishable offenses and punishments of more severity were introduced. Thus, prison systems were built up to contain the resultant growing population of criminals. With the rise in the number and types of crimes came the problem of identifying repeat offenders. This problem became a specific subset of the more general one of keeping a complete and general track on the whole of society, that is, keeping order through knowledge. It also represents the point where the models derived from Galilean physics start to impinge on and interact with the semiotic model of medicine, in the development of new forms of control and methods for identification, devised in the same period of the 1800s as the detective novel, psychoanalysis, and connoisseurship evolved. This was evident in two competing systems for identification initiated or developed by Francis Galton (1822–1911) and Alphonse Bertillon (1853–1914), respectively. In both cases, however, science meets conjecture to give rise to the methods of scientific investigation based on classifications of the individual and interpretations of effects of specific causes in particular cases. In the first case, the system of Bertillionage, a classification scheme for identifying repeat offenders through anthropometric measures plus the description and classification of physical characteristics, was based on the idea of probability statistics used within astronomy and physics to get a measure of errors, introduced to the study of society and crime by Adolphe Quetelet (1796–1874) in his conceptualisation of a “social physics”. Quetelet’s work provided a major inspiration to Bertillon and the anthropometric method, by Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process suggesting that while single measures might be just probative, the higher number of specific measures made per individual the higher the probability of identification. In the second case, the system of fingerprint identification introduced by Francis Galton, yet not originally discovered by him (for a history of fingerprint identification, see Cole 2001; Sengoopta 2004), was based on the idea that the individual has an identity that may be recognized in his every characteristic, even the most imperceptible and the slightest, and that there will be an internal norm or “typus,” which maintains the variety of each species within its limits. The philosophical input, as well as the study of fingerprints as the empirical example of the rule, was made by a physiologist founding the subject of study of organ tissues: Purkyne´ in a work in 1923. Bertillon, being the son of a medically educated statistician and inspired by an influential figure in the emerging science of society especially criminology developed by Adolphe Quetelet, represents the meeting point of the conjectural model derived from medical semiotics and that of divining probability through the science developed to this end: statistics. Galton’s discoveries of the individuality of the fingerprint and its possible practical implications, on the other hand represent the point of contact between old divinatory traditions; the problem of identification of the complex society and the risks posed by the transgressor of laws and regulations, and the anatomical model of medicine and its attempt at understanding the relation between individual and general type, in order to diagnose individual symptoms and secure the proper treatment in each individual case. Forensic science arose from the interconnections of these ideas and trajectories of thought spanning detective fiction, graphology, art connoisseurship, statistics, sociology, criminology, administrative practices, psychology, linguistics, history, etc., as they were developed and promoted in the works of Hans Gross, Alexandre Lacassagne, Edmond Locard, Alphonse Bertillon, Francis Galton, and many more in a range of subdisciplines to emerge within the field. 3509 P New Philosophies of Science: Conjecture and “The Scientific Man” In the late nineteenth century and early twentieth century, the philosophy of science saw new developments which were influenced by processes rooted in the conjectural or semiotic paradigm. One of the ways in which semiotics was developed into scientific theories and new approaches to knowledge were through the ideas of American Pragmatism. In addition to being an exemplification of the broader upsurge and explication of semiotics as a theoretical discipline, (which itself developed into a range of different philosophical theories, for example, critical theory, post-structuralism, hermeneutics, reflexivity, etc.) this particular theoretical paradigm has overt links to the developments of forensic science. The credited founder of Pragmatism Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) was deeply inspired by the detective figure in his exposition of his thoughts on reasoning and the “scientific man”, which again was part of a more general theory of signs and sign processes as a distinct theory of knowledge (Eco and Sebeok 1983). Besides, Peirce was and is generally acknowledged as a natural scientist, above being a philosopher, although his philosophy of science is seminal. Based among other on the figure of the scientifically reasoning detective fashioned by Conan Doyle, Peirce developed a new concept of inference – abduction – which served to integrate the approach to science initiated with Galileo and the necessity of using incomplete knowledge and conjecture – not least in face of lack of enough data – to form hypotheses and predictive conditionals to be tested as a means of approaching what could qualify as secure beliefs. Abduction is Peirce’s designation of an inference which is made from an observation to its possible explanation; that is, from evidence to a hypothesis or conclusion – where the phenomenon to be explained, through the evidence of it observed, itself constitutes a significant part of the reason to presume that the explanation is correct (Lipton 2000). Peirce held that all inquiry, including science, is to be described as a struggle to move from P P 3510 irritating, inhibitory doubt born of surprise, disagreement, and the like, toward the reach of a secure belief. Belief being defined as that on which one is prepared to act, rather than as the pursuit of truth per se. Scientific inquiry, to Peirce, was thus just one part of a broader spectrum and spurred, like inquiry generally, by genuine doubt, rather than by mere verbal or hyperbolic doubt, which he held to be fruitless. Having grouped all forms of inquiry under the same pursuit, he also devised a theory of inquiry and logic, which introduced a new logic of inference to the description of science. Peirce held that abduction, induction, and deduction made a complementary whole which together constitute scientific method. None of the modes of inference could be dispensed with – since abduction to Peirce is the only way new knowledge can arise. Logic was based on all the modes of inference, including abduction, which he perceived as a precondition for the development of science. Peirce also replaced the conception of science as a collection of certified truths or systematized knowledge with a definition of science as an inquisitorial attitude, the defining characteristics of science to be found in the approach to inquiry and the controls put on it rather than in the contents of its canons. Being deeply inspired by Aristotle, whose concept of apagoge seems to entail all the things that Peirce describes as retroduction or abduction and who may be the original inspiration for his thinking (Aliseda 2006), he picks up on the same theme that Vico (as mentioned earlier) raised during the Renaissance: that all actions, whether practical decisions, medical diagnosis or scientific inquiry make use of the principle of the topics (i.e., those culturally formed beliefs, habits of experience and expectations to the order and workings of the empirical world) to form judgments and beliefs on which to act whether practically or theoretically (Miner 1998). One can legitimately speak of pragmatism as a reinterpretation of Greek philosophy about knowledge and thus a rekindling with the roots of the development of the sciences and their conjectural roots. While Peirce is not a prominent figure in the canons of forensic science – if at all present, the Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process practices, which inspire his philosophical positions, are indeed those of the forensic practitioner. It therefore seems in keeping with the micro-history of science and the conjectural paradigm delineated by Ginzburg, to point to the pragmatist philosophy as an example of trends in the philosophy of science, which are informed by the conjectural and semiotic paradigm running from Ancient Greek philosophy to some of the developments in thinking about science making way from the nineteenth century and onward, and which are in keeping – however subtle and mutely – with the philosophical basis of the forensic process. Conclusion and Further Perspectives The Forensic Process: Conjecture and Science or Conjectural Science? The philosophical basis of the forensic process is not to be discerned as a linear development of thought but rather as a meshwork of ideas. However, the influence of the ideas delineated is clear considering the principles brought to bear on the forensic process by the founding fathers and key figures in forensic science, for example: (a) the principle of transfer: that two physical objects coming into contact with each other will result in minute traces, imprints or effects of this contact (also known as the principle of exchange) commonly attributed to Edmond Locard (1928, 1930), but by him attributed to the inspiration from Alexandre Lacassagne; (b) the goal of individualization based on the identification and/or classification of the physical or chemical nature of the evidence (Saferstein 1998); (c) the idea of classification/individualization and the attempt to determine the source of evidence (Kirk 1963); (d) the idea of association linking person to crime scene and leading to inferences of source and target (Osterburg 1968), and (e) the purpose of reconstruction of past events (DeForest et al. 1983) (for an overview description, see Inman and Rudin 2001). All the central ideas of forensic analysis are based on a combination of topical inspiration (i.e., attempts at answering the 6W’s essential to legal deliberation) and the Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process foundational concepts of the semiotic paradigm that infers causes from effects and which on the basis of classifications of the nature of the physical world discerns individual characteristics of the particular situation, object, or document. Characteristics which in turn serves to discern the history, meaning, and causes of the phenomenon under scrutiny, (i.e., of the physical evidence left over from an event (possibly criminal) passed). In much the same way as the clinician of early modern medicine, the forensic practitioner may be said to embody a point of contact between two differing yet cognate paradigms – that of semiotics and that of Galilean natural science. Each has differing goals and criteria for valuing truth claims: one related to abstract disinterested truth and one related to practical effects and rationality. Like the physicians of the late nineteenth century, the forensic practitioner is a “diagnostician” and “expert connoisseur” with respect to assisting the investigative inquiry and translating the topics and questions of law into scientific questions. He is also a “naturalist” and “empiricist scientist” with respect to analyzing artifacts believed to adhere to an incident under legal scrutiny and providing conclusions regarding their identity based exclusively on knowledge obtained through observable and verifiable data. The first form of knowledge tends to be unspoken and does not easily lend itself to formalization, since nobody learns how to be a connoisseur or diagnostician simply by applying the rules. The allusion to one of the key works in Modern scientific philosophy by Karl R. Popper: Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge (1963) in the heading above is intended as a pun on words which may serve as the key points of further perspectives, since the question is not whether conjecture is part of what informed the growth of forensics but rather: How much conjecture is allowed and under what circumstances for forensic science to qualify as science? The key concern of the forensic sciences and thus the key philosophical problem with which it grapples is that of individualization (Kirk and Thornton 1974). Forensic science – arising out of the conjectural paradigm and the 3511 P semiotic model of medicine – is in many ways the science of the individual par excellence. Seeking from beginning to end of the forensic process and through the fields of knowledge informing the practical process of forensic inquiry (i.e., the forensic process) answers, which may provide individuation of both people and cases – of “who” and “what” of the Ciceroean topics. In this way, the forensic process is heir not only of the key topics identified by Cicero for the presentation of a legal case but also of the quest of the sciences build on the Galilean model and the problems facing these in their attempt to explain and describe the particular and the characteristics of the individual, and the ways that phenomena known through theoretical classifications may play out in particular situations, hereby ascertaining the span of characteristics to be associated with the phenomena in a given situation and thus ascribed to it. This problem is becoming increasingly acute to the forensic sciences, due to emergence of debates in scientific circles of is scientific status. Yet in the philosophical history of the forensic process of inquiry, can also be identified ideas and principles stemming from a semiotic paradigm, which has grown large in the human and social sciences, and which holds promise of a new formulation of a model of science, which may provide an alternative route to the problems faced, by introducing a concept of scientific rigor which is more “elastic.” Forensic sciences is finding itself in a position where new developments are imminent, if not already in process. Developments which may prove decisive for the future role and status of forensic evidence, and which springs exactly from the problem having faced sciences developed in the image of Galilean physics, since the beginning of the Modern Era. This dilemma is coined by Ginzburg (1980) as that of choosing between: (a) achieving significant results from a scientifically weak position, or (b) to establish a strong scientific position, but get meager results. Rethinking and revisiting the philosophical basis of the forensic process, and turning to key thinkers within this paradigm for new approaches to the dilemma may provide an alternative route P P 3512 bypassing the deadlock of the debates. The theories, models, and scientific content of the conjectural model that might inspire new ways of theorizing and conceptualizing the foundational and defining principles of the forensic process are still however largely unexcavated, even though it provides the philosophical basis and seed of development for a broad range of contemporary disciplines in all areas of science. Related Entries ▶ Forensic Science and Criminal Inquiry ▶ Forensic Science Culture ▶ Forensic Science Effectiveness ▶ Forensic Science in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries ▶ History of Criminal Investigation ▶ History of Forensic Science in Policing ▶ Philosophy of Forensic Identification ▶ Prosecutorial Discretion ▶ Scientific Basis of the Forensic Process ▶ Scientific Evidence in Criminal Prosecutions Recommended Reading and References Aliseda A (2006) Abductive reasoning: logical investigations into discovery and explanation. Springer, Dordrecht Aristotle, Lawson-Tancred H (1991) The art of rhetoric. Penguin Books, London Aristotle (384–322 BC) Topics: (trans: Gaza T, CR Editors) Balkin JM (1996) A night in the topics: the reason of legal rhetoric and the rhetoric of legal reason. In: Brooks P, Gewirtz P (eds) Law, stories: narrative and rhetoric in the law. Yale University Press, New Haven Cole SA (2001) Suspect identities: a history of fingerprinting and criminal identification. Harvard University Press, Cambridge/London Daston L, Galison P (1992) The image of objectivity. Representations, No. 40, Special issue: seeing science. pp 81–128 Daston L, Galison P (2007) Objectivity. Zone Books, New York/Cambridge DeForest P, Lee H, Gaensslen R (1983) Forensic science: an introduction to criminalistics. McGraw Hill, New York Eco U, Sebeok TA (1983) The sign of three: Dupin, Holmes, Peirce. Indiana University Press, Bloomington Philosophical Basis of the Forensic Process Foucault M (1970) The order of things: an archaeology of the human sciences. Tavistock, London Foucault M, Gordon C (1980) Power-knowledge: selected interviews and other writings, 1972–1977. Harvester Press, Brighton Foucault M, Sheridan A (1973) The birth of the clinic: an archaeology of medical perception. Tavistock Publications, London Foucault M, Sheridan A (1979) Discipline and punish: the birth of the prison. Penguin, Harmondsworth Foucault M, Senellart M, Davidson AI (2007) Security, territory, population lectures at the Colle`ge de France, 1977–78. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke/ New York Foucault M, Senellart M, Ewald F, Fontana A, Burchell G, Colle`ge de France (2008) The birth of biopolitics: lectures at the Colle`ge de France, 1978–79. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke/New York Giambattista V (transl. Marsh D 1999) 1744 New Science. Penguin Books, London/New York/Victoria/Ontario Ginzburg C (1980) Morelli, Freud and Sherlock Holmes: clues and scientific method. Hist Workshop J 9(1):5–36 Hookway C (1985) Peirce. Arguments of the Philosophers series. Routledge, London/New York Inman K, Rudin N (2001) Principle and practice of criminalistics: the profession of forensic science, Protocols in forensic science. CRC Press/Taylor & Francis Group, Boca Raton/London/New York King LS, Meehan MC (1973) A history of the autopsy: a review. Am J Pathol 73(2):514–544 Kirk PL (1963) The ontogeny of criminalistics. J Crim Law Criminol Police Sci 54:235–238 Kirk PL, Thornton JI (1974) In: Thornton JI (ed) Crime investigation, 2nd edn. Wiley, New York/London Leff MC (1983) The topics of argumentative invetion in Latin rhetorical theory from Cicero to Boethius. Rhetorica J Hist Rhetoric 1(1):23–44 Lipton P (1991) Inference to best explanation. Routledge, London/New York Locard E (1928) Dust and its analysis. Police J 1:177 Locard E (1930) The analysis of dust traces Am J Police Sci 1: pp. 276–298, 401–418, 496–514 Markus S (1976) Introduction to A. Conan Doyle. In: Conan Doyle A (ed) The adventures of Sherlock Holmes: a facsimile of the stories as they were first published in the Strand magazine. Schocken Books, New York, pp x–xi Miner RC (1998) “Verum-factum” and practical wisdom in the early writings of Giambattista Vico. J Hist Ideas 59(1):53–73 Mnookin JL et al (2011) The need for a research culture in the forensic sciences. UCLA Law Rev 58:725–779 National Academy of Sciences (2009) Strengthening forensic science in the United States: a path forward. National Academies Press, Washington, DC Osterburg JW (1968) The crime laboratory: case studies of scientific criminal investigation. Indianna University Press, Bloomington Philosophy of Forensic Identification Popper KR (1963) Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge, London Robertson DW (1946) A note on the classical origins of “Circumstances” in the medieval confessional. Stud Philol 43(1):6–14 Saferstein R (1998) Criminalistics: an introduction to forensic science, 6th edn. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs/New York Schoeck RJ (1983) Lawyers and rhetoric in sixteenthcentury England. In: Murphy J (ed) Renaissance eloquence: studies in the theory and practice of renaissance rhetoric. University of California Press, Berkeley Sengoopta C (2004) Imprint of the Raj: how fingerprinting was born in colonal India. Pan Books, Basingstoke/ Oxford Tilstone W, Hastrup M, Hald C (eds) (2012) Fisher’s techniques of crime scene investigation. First international edition. CRC Press/Taylor & Francis Group, Boca Raton Toulmin SE (1958) The uses of argument. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Victorinus M (1863) Explanationum in rhetoricam M. Tullii Ciceronis libri duo. In: Halm C (ed) Rhetores Latini minores. Teubner, Leipzig Philosophy of Forensic Identification Ton Broeders Faculty of Law, Institute for Criminal Law and Criminology, Leiden University, Leiden, The Netherlands Maastricht University, Maastricht, The Netherlands Overview In most if not all criminal investigations, the collection, examination, and interpretation of physical evidence plays a major role. Material traces, whether they are of a physical, chemical, biological, or digital nature, may serve to suggest or support plausible scenarios of what might have happened at a possible scene of crime. Ultimately, they may be instrumental in distinguishing between the rival scenarios that the judge or jury will have to consider in arriving at the final verdict: Was the crime committed by the suspect in the way described by the prosecution, was it someone else who did it, or was no crime committed in the first place? 3513 P Individualization of physical traces, like DNA, handwriting, or fingerprints, logically amounts to a process of inference of identity of source between a crime scene trace and some reference material whose origin is known. While its aim is to uniquely identify the source of the trace and many criminalists, most notably the dactyloscopists, have long proceeded as though individualization of traces is a routine affair, there is no scientific basis for this claim or for the methods by which individualization or source attribution is supposedly achieved. It is largely as a result of the advent of forensic DNA analysis and the conceptual framework associated with the interpretation of DNA evidence that the forensic community has come to appreciate the “individualization fallacy” (Saks and Koehler 2008) and the consequent need to adopt what has come to be known as a logical or Bayesian approach to the interpretation of technical and scientific evidence. A comprehensive model for the assessment and interpretation of forensic evidence along Bayesian lines was developed in Britain by Ian Evett and colleagues at the Forensic Science Service (Cook et al. 1998a, b; AoFSP 2009; Evett 2011). It defines a hierarchy of propositions to be addressed in casework which is composed of three levels and extends over two domains. The first domain, that of the forensic expert, involves propositions at the level of source and at the level of activity. Propositions at the level of source address the question of the origin of the trace, while propositions at the activity level relate to the question how and when the trace arose. Propositions formulated at the third level, termed the level of offense, belong exclusively to the domain of the trier of fact and relate to the ultimate, legal issue whether an offense was committed and if so, whether it was committed by the defendant. While the Bayesian approach provides an excellent framework for the evaluation and interpretation of expert evidence in that it helps define the relevant questions and draws a sharp line between the domain of the expert and that of the trier of fact, it is not an intuitively easy approach. A clear and transparent exposition of the method used by the expert to determine the weight of the P P 3514 scientific evidence is therefore of the essence. Recent research as well as court decisions suggest that if this information is lacking judges and juries will be hard put to assess the evidence at its true value. Criminalistic Processes: Individualization Versus Identification In order for material traces like DNA to be able to contribute to criminal investigations in the form of technical or scientific expert evidence, there are various questions that need to be addressed. One question seeks to determine the nature or substance of the trace material. Are we dealing with blood, gunshot residue, MDMA, or hair? The process by which this type of question is answered is called identification. A second process, classification, takes the first process one step further. It is undertaken to determine whether the crime scene trace can be assigned to a particular group or class of similar objects or substances. Examples of classification processes in the forensic sciences are: the classification of blood into human versus animal blood; of hair into animal versus human hair and, beyond that, the (sub)classification into body, head, and pubic hair; the classification of fibers into man-made versus natural fibers; the classification of firearms and cartridges in terms of their make and caliber, or that of shoes according to size, make, model, sole pattern, etc. A third process seeks to identify the origin or source of the trace material. Is it possible to relate the trace or the carrier of the trace to a particular person or object? This process, the determination of the unique source of a trace, is technically called individualization and is often seen as the process that lies at the heart of the criminalistic effort. Although, in common parlance, the term “identification” may also be used for the process of source determination, as in a phrase like fingerprint identification or indeed in the title of this entry, the proper technical term for this process is individualization. A fourth question concerns the relation of the trace material with the crime by trying to Philosophy of Forensic Identification establish how and when the trace was generated. This process, which focuses on the nature of the activity by which the trace material arose, is often referred to as association. All four processes, identification, classification, individualization, and association, are essential elements of the larger process of reconstruction (Inman and Rudin 2000): the attempt to create coherent scenarios of the chain of events that constitutes the incident under examination on the basis of the available evidence. Particularly in the context of DNA evidence, both “source level” questions of the type “Whose DNA is it?” and “activity level” questions of the type “How and when did the cell material get there?” are of paramount importance, as it is only on the strength of the combined answers to these questions that a link can be established between a particular person or object and a possible crime. Conclusions in Individualization Criminalistics is the science of individualization (Kirk 1963, p. 235) Individualization may be defined as the process undertaken to establish the unique source or origin of a particular material trace. Put simply, it tries to answer questions like “Whose DNA/handwriting/ fingerprint, etc. is this?” According to Paul Kirk (1902–1970), one of the founding fathers of criminalistics, it is individualization that marks off criminalistics as a science from other sciences. While the goal of criminalistics is always the same, there are considerable differences in the methodology used and the conclusions formulated by the practitioners of the various forensic disciplines to achieve this aim. By and large, three groups may be distinguished in terms of the way in which the conclusions of a comparative trace examination are expressed. First, the conclusions may directly address the probability of the source hypothesis given the evidence. This tends to be the case in dactyloscopy and typically also still holds for most other types of source level trace examinations. An important exception is DNA, where the conclusions expressed relate to the probability of the evidence under a particular hypothesis rather Philosophy of Forensic Identification 3515 than to the probability of the hypothesis given the evidence. Second, unlike dactyloscopists, who will generally express their conclusions in categorical terms, forensic experts in most other fields of trace examination will tend to express their conclusions in probabilistic terms, in either a verbal format or in a quantitative format, as in DNA typing. Schematically, where C stands for categorical, P for probabilistic, E for statement of the probability of the evidence, and H for statement of the probability of the hypothesis, the following distinctions may be noted: Dactyloscopy (fingerprints) Other physical traces (e.g., handwriting, fibers, shoe prints, tool marks) DNA (biological traces) C H P (and verbal) H P (and quantitative) E For example, the dactyloscopist will conclude that a finger mark does or does not originate from a particular (person’s) finger, thereby making a categorical statement of the probability of H, the source attribution hypothesis. But the handwriting expert will – traditionally anyway – typically conclude that the questioned writing probably/very probably/with a probability bordering on certainty does – or does not, as the case may be – originate from the writer of the reference material, thereby making a (verbal) probabilistic rather than a categorical statement of H, the source hypothesis. By contrast, the DNA expert will first determine whether the source material could originate from the person whose reference profile is being compared with that of the crime scene sample. If the profiles of the crime scene material and the person under investigation match, the expert will state that the crime scene material may originate from this person. To indicate the significance of this finding, the expert will add how likely the evidence, i.e., a matching profile, is if the crime scene material originates from the “matching” person under investigation as opposed to a random member of the population. Alternatively, the expert may report the estimated frequency of the profile in the relevant population. A third way to report the weight of the evidence is in terms of the so-called random match probability of P the profile: The probability that a randomly chosen member of the population who is not related to the donor of the cell material or the matching suspect will match the crime scene profile. It appears therefore that while the experts in the diverse fields are answering the same question, that of the origin of the trace, they will tend to use different conclusion formats to express their findings. The notions underlying these differences are explored below. The Classical Approach to Individualization: The Underlying Principles The traditional forensic approach to trace individualization is based on four – partly implicit – principles: 1. The principle of transfer of evidence 2. The principle of the divisibility of matter 3. The uniqueness assumption 4. The individualization principle The Transfer Principle: “Every Contact Leaves a Trace” The first of these, the transfer principle, is captured in the phrase “Every contact leaves a trace.” It expresses the notion that in the commission of criminal acts, invariably some traces will be left on the scene. It provides a theoretical basis for the generation of traces and a principled argument for the examination of the crime scene for traces. This insight was formulated most clearly by the Frenchman Edmond Locard (1877–1966), who was the first director of the Laboratoire de Police Scientifique in Lyon, France, in 1912 and is universally acclaimed as one of the fathers of criminalistics. While Locard was primarily thinking of the transfer of microscopic traces like dust, dirt, nail debris, or fibers, as left in the commission of the more violent type of crime, Locard’s exchange principle, as the principle is also commonly referred to, is also applicable to traces that arise in the context of less violent crimes as well as to latent (hidden), patent (visible to the naked eye), or plastic impression evidence, such as finger marks, tool marks, footwear marks, or striation marks on bullets and cartridge cases. In the latter case, it is not so much the physical matter that is deposited at or taken away from P P 3516 the crime scene that is of interest but the patterns or shapes that are transferred from donor (object) to recipient (object). In addition, the principle increasingly applies to so-called contact traces, as in DNA evidence. Here, terms like “trace DNA” or “touch DNA” are used to refer to cell material and debris transferred through skin contact, which may arise as a result of regular use, as on a watch, from a single, firm contact, as on a tie wrap or strangulation cord, or from a single touch, as on a glass surface (Raymond et al. 2004). As Locard observed at the time, transfer may go either way. Traces like glass fragments, blood stains, hairs, or fibers are left at the crime scene by a donor and may be picked up from there by a receptor. If (part of) the material collected is subsequently left by the receptor and picked up by a second receptor, we speak of secondary transfer. For example, fibers or DNA material picked up by A from B’s clothing may be transferred from B’s clothing to chair C, and eventually end up on the clothing of D. In principle, forms of tertiary and quarternary transfer might also occur. The Divisibility of Matter: “Matter Divides Under Pressure” The second underlying principle of criminalistics, that of the divisibility of matter, was explicitly defined only relatively recently by the American DNA experts Keith Inman and Norah Rudin (2000). It explains why transfer can play such an important role in the generation of traces. Although the principle as such is fairly obvious, it is of considerable importance for a proper understanding of the relation between the way traces arise and their interpretation. In an article entitled “The origin of evidence,” Inman and Rudin (2002: p. 12) describe the process of the division of matter and its results as follows: Matter divides into smaller component parts when sufficient force is applied. The component parts will acquire characteristics created by the process of division itself and retain physico-chemical properties of the larger piece Philosophy of Forensic Identification This mechanism has important implications for the relation between traces and their sources. They are: Corollary 1 Some characteristics retained by the smaller pieces are unique to the original item or to the division process. These traits are useful for individualizing all pieces to the original item. Corollary 2 Some characteristics retained by the smaller pieces are common to the original as well as to other items of similar manufacture. We rely on these traits to classify them. Corollary 3 Some characteristics from the original item will be lost or changed during or after the moment of division and subsequent dispersal; this confounds the attempt to infer a common source. (Inman and Rudin 2002, p. 12) While the two principles discussed so far relate to the creation or generation of traces, the following two principles are central to the interpretation of traces, as viewed in the traditional approach to trace individualization. The Uniqueness Assumption: “Nature Never Repeats Itself” The first of these is the uniqueness assumption. It is nicely captured in the phrase “Nature never repeats itself” and essentially simply states that no two objects are identical. Or, as Kirk and Grunbaum (1968, p. 289) put it: Now most students believe that all items of the universe are in some respect different from other similar items, so that ultimately it may be possible to individualize not only a person but any object of interest. This effort is the heart of criminalistics. The uniqueness assumption was probably most vigorously championed by the fingerprint fraternity. However, before the fingerprint was discovered as a means to verify a person’s identity and subsequently came to be used for forensic purposes, the same principle provided a basis for forensic anthropometry, which was developed by the Frenchman Alphonse Bertillon (1853–1914). Anthropometry. Anthropometry was developed by Bertillon primarily to identify repeated offenders. The method is based on an assumption derived from the Belgian astronomer and statistician Adolphe Quetelet (1796–1874) that no two Philosophy of Forensic Identification human bodies are equal. A founder of modern quantitative sociology, Quetelet is not only believed to be the inspiration for the frequently cited phrase that nature does not repeat itself but must also be credited with the definition of the Quetelet index, which, since 1972, has come to be more widely known as the BMI or Body Mass Index. The anthropometric method consisted in recording the dimensions of an arrestee’s body in terms of seven and later 12 measurements of a fixed set of parts of the body, including total physical height, the length and width of the head, the right ear, and the left foot, which were believed to be constant for adult members of the human race. In 1883, Bertillon succeeded in identifying a repeated offender by comparing his measurements with anthropometric data recorded earlier. Later in his life, Bertillon was the first to make a fingerprint identification in a murder case on the European Continent (Thorwald 1965, p. 83). The assumption of uniqueness, together with the temporal stability of fingerprints, or friction ridge patterns as they are more technically called, is often adduced as a theoretical ground for the justification of the use of categorical conclusions of origin, as has typically been common if not universal practice in dactyloscopy. However, as Saks and Koehler (2005, p. 892) put it, in formulating these categorical conclusions, dactyloscopists in fact rely on a flawed notion of “discernible uniqueness.” The real issue in source attribution is not whether all possible sources can be distinguished from each other in principle, which is what the uniqueness assumption – presumably correctly – implies. The crucial question is whether a trace, which, due to the factors described under the divisibility principle, will inevitably differ to some extent from its particular source, can be attributed – with certainty, or, failing that, with any reliable degree of probability – to that source. The Individualization Principle: “That Can’t Be a Coincidence” The fourth principle in the traditional approach to trace individualization states that a conclusion of 3517 P (probable) common origin of a trace and reference material – as in a comparative examination of a questioned handwriting sample and a reference sample from a known person – may be arrived at if there are so many similarities of such significance that their occurring together by chance may be practically excluded. As the American handwriting expert R.A. Huber (1959–1960, p. 289) put it in his definition of what he called “the principle of identification”: When any two items have characteristics in common of such number and significance as to preclude their simultaneous occurrence by chance, and there are no inexplicable differences, then it may be concluded that they are the same, or from the same source. The suggestion here is that a criterion, i.e., “of such number and significance,” may be defined which will provide a principled and objective way to determine that the possibility (or probability) that two objects meet this criterion by chance can be excluded. Such a criterion is not only not feasible in practice, as it begs the question what number and what degree of significance is required, but it also lacks a theoretical basis in that it ignores the essentially inductive nature of the individualization process. The reason why individualization is problematic from a theoretical point of view is that any attempt to identify the unique source of physical, biological, or pattern evidence like finger marks, footwear marks, DNA, or handwriting is typically frustrated by the induction problem. We cannot, solely on the strength of even an extreme degree of similarity between trace and reference material, conclude that a particular trace must have originated from some specific reference material to the exclusion of all other possible sources, unless we have been able to examine all these alternative sources and eliminate them categorically. To begin with, the population from which a finger mark or a questioned handwritten text actually originates is typically indefinite in size and frequently largely unavailable for examination. But even if it were possible to examine a large number of potential writers or fingers, P P 3518 we could not exclude finding one or more whose reference handwriting or fingerprint would show a similar or even greater degree of similarity with the questioned handwriting or finger mark than did the reference sample of the suspect. Since this possibility cannot be excluded, the individualization problem tends to be impossible to solve and in that sense is strongly reminiscent of that of Popper’s white swans: We cannot conclude that all swans are white unless we have been able to examine all swans (Popper 1959). Nor for that matter can we conclude that the trace probably originates from the reference material with which it shares many features. Indeed, although the observed degree of similarity between trace and possible source will tend to make the hypothesis of identity of source more probable in relative terms than it was before the comparative examination was carried out, similarity is neither a sufficient nor even a necessary condition for identity of source in absolute terms. It is interesting that the individualization criterion as captured in the phrase “That cannot be a coincidence” is essentially similar to that used in traditional, standard textbook statistical significance testing. In this approach, the result of a hypothesis test is termed significant if it is unlikely to have occurred by chance. More specifically, the so-called null hypothesis that the result is due to chance may be rejected if the obtained result is less likely to occur under this hypothesis than a predetermined threshold probability of – frequently – 1 or 5 %. Like the traditional identification paradigm, this approach is also coming in for more and more criticism, partly because it also fails to take account of the probability of the result under the alternative hypothesis. Class Characteristics Versus Individual Characteristics In an attempt to overcome the induction problem traditional forensic identification, experts frequently rely on the distinction between class characteristics and individual characteristics. For example, all firearms of a particular make and caliber may leave the same markers on a cartridge or bullet, thereby making it possible to identify the type of weapon on the basis of the Philosophy of Forensic Identification class or system characteristics that the particular type of firearm is known to leave. However, a certain configuration of striation marks left on a bullet may be distinctive for a particular weapon. As Thornton and Peterson (2002) put it: Class characteristics are general characteristics that separate a group of objects from a universe of diverse objects. In a comparison process, class characteristics serve the very useful purpose of screening a large number of items by eliminating from consideration those items that do not share the characteristics common to all the members of that group. Class characteristics do not, and cannot establish uniqueness. Individual characteristics, on the other hand, are those exceptional characteristics that may establish the uniqueness of an object. It should be recognized that an individual characteristic, taken in isolation, might not in itself be unique. The uniqueness of an object may be established by an ensemble of individual characteristics. A scratch on the surface of a bullet, for example, is not a unique event; it is the arrangement of the scratches on the bullet that mark it as unique. Unfortunately, the definition of individual characteristics is circular. They are defined as characteristics that are – collectively – capable of establishing uniqueness. But whether an ensemble of individual characteristics is unique is itself an inductive question: We can never be sure that a feature or combination of features is unique, until we have observed all relevant objects, which is impossible. What practitioners of traditional forensic identification sciences really do is perhaps best described by Stoney (1991), who used the image of the “leap of faith” as the mechanism whereby the forensic scientist actually establishes individualization, as in dactyloscopy: When more and more corresponding features are found between the two patterns scientist and lay person alike become subjectively certain that the patterns could not possibly be duplicated by chance. What has happened here is somewhat analogous to a leap of faith. It is a jump, an extrapolation, based on the observation of highly variable traits among a few characteristics, and then considering the case of many characteristics. [] In fingerprint work, we become subjectively convinced of identity; we do not prove it. Ultimately then, in traditional identification disciplines, in reaching a conclusion about the Philosophy of Forensic Identification probable or categorical origin of the trace material, the expert delivers an essentially subjective opinion. When informed by adequate levels of training, experience, and expertise, this conclusion will frequently be correct, but it must be clear that the expert becomes convinced of the (probable) origin of the trace. He does not “prove” it: There is no logical basis for the conclusion. The Logical Approach to Individualization: The Concept of the Likelihood Ratio By contrast, in the logical approach, the expert does not primarily seek to determine the probability of the source or activity hypothesis. Instead, the purpose of the comparative examination is to determine the likelihood of the evidence under two mutually exclusive propositions or hypotheses. Suppose we find a size 14 shoeprint at a crime scene and a suspect emerges who takes size 14. It will be clear that the shoe size information by itself gives us insufficient basis to say that it was the suspect who left the print rather than one of the other shoe size 14 wearers in the area (or beyond). The mere fact that the suspect wears size 14 shoes does not make him more suspect than anybody else with this size shoes. At the same time, it is clear that the finding looks incriminating. Or is it a mere coincidence? The likelihood ratio (LR) provides a principled way to address this question. To calculate it, we need to determine the ratio of the likelihood of a size 14 turning up at the crime scene under two rival hypotheses: (1) The shoe mark was left by the suspect versus (2) the mark was left by a random member of the relevant potential donor population. We know that the likelihood of finding a size 14 mark if the suspect left it (and assuming he does not occasionally or otherwise wear a different size shoe) is 1, or 100 %. To assess the likelihood of finding a size 14 shoe mark under the alternative hypothesis that a random member of the relevant population left the print, we need to know what percentage of that population takes a size 14 3519 P shoe. Suppose we know this figure to be 4 %. We can now calculate the likelihood ratio of the evidence under these two competing hypotheses, which in this case would amount to 100/4 ¼ 25. We can paraphrase this result by saying that the footwear evidence is 25 times more likely if the suspect left the mark than if a random member of the population left it. We can also say that the evidence makes it (25 times) more likely that the suspect left the mark than we believed was the case before we obtained the evidence. But we cannot on the basis of the shoe mark evidence alone pronounce upon the probability of the hypothesis that the suspect left the mark in absolute terms. Alternatively, what we can say in a case like this is that an LR of 25 reduces the group of potential suspects by a factor 25, leaving just one potential suspect on average for every 25 potential suspects considered before the shoe print evidence became available. Similarly, when applied to DNA evidence, the likelihood ratio is a measure of the weight of the evidence and may be seen as an indication of the extent to which the uncertainty about the source hypothesis is reduced by the evidence. If, for example, the matching profile is known to have a frequency of 1 in a million in the relevant population, the LR of the matching DNA evidence may be reported as one million: It is the ratio of the likelihood of the evidence under the hypothesis that the person under investigation is the donor of the DNA material, i.e., 1 (or 100 %) divided by the likelihood of the evidence under the alternative hypothesis that the DNA originates from a random member of the population, i.e., 1/1,000,000. The conclusion implies that the evidence is a million times more likely if the crime scene sample originates from the donor of the reference material than if a random member of the population were the donor of the crime scene sample. It is only if there is no match that the DNA expert may make a – negative – categorical statement of the probability of the hypothesis. Discrete Versus Continuous Variables In the examples involving DNA and shoe sizes discussed above, the variables of interest are P P 3520 discrete or categorical in nature and the similarity between trace and reference material could be said to be either complete or to be entirely absent: The DNA profiles and the shoe sizes are the same or they are different. If they are different, the suspect’s shoe or body can be eliminated as the source of the trace. However, in many cases, the correspondence between trace and source will not be perfect. Many variables are not discrete (like DNA markers or shoe size) but continuous. Examples are quantitative variables such as length, weight, or shape. For these variables, there will always be a difference between trace and reference materials because in both cases, we are dealing with samples that will at best only approximate the “true,” i.e., average, population value for the feature of interest. Again, handwriting analysis may serve as a case in point, but the same holds for any other type of trace with continuous properties like tool marks, fibers, speech, glass, or paint. Both the questioned writing and the reference writing must be seen as samples taken from the indefinitely large population of handwriting productions that the writers of these samples are capable of producing. This means that any marker that is examined, like the shape and execution of the letter t or the figure 8, will exhibit a certain degree of variability even within samples originating from the same source. However, traces originating from a single source will typically show a relatively small degree of within-source variation, while samples of material originating from different sources will typically show a relatively larger degree of between-source variation. As a result, in these cases, the numerator of the likelihood ratio will not be 100 % or 1, but say 80: A degree of similarity as great as that found between trace material and reference material will then be found in 80 % of cases if both originate from the same source and in say only 10 % of cases if trace material and reference material originate from different sources. The likelihood ratio would then be 80/10 ¼ 8. If, however, the degree of similarity found would be expected in only 20 % of cases under the hypothesis of common origin and in 40 % of Philosophy of Forensic Identification cases under the hypothesis of different origin, the likelihood ratio would be 20/40 ¼ ½, and the evidence would actually weaken the common source hypothesis rather than strengthen it. In the first instance, the likelihood ratio would exceed 1 and the evidence would (weakly) support the hypothesis of common origin; in the second instance, the likelihood ratio would be less than 1 and the evidence would – again weakly – support the alternative hypothesis, that the trace did not originate from the same source as the reference material. The Likelihood Ratio and the Diagnostic Value The concept of the likelihood ratio is similar to that of the diagnostic value, a measure which has found wide acceptance in fields like medicine and psychology as a way to express the value of a diagnostic test result. It is arrived at by dividing the relative number of correct (positive or negative) results of the test in question by the relative number of false (positive or negative) results of the test. In more technical language, by dividing the sensitivity of the test by (1 – the specificity). The sensitivity of the test is the percentage of correct positives it produces, the specificity the percentage of correct negatives. Applied to an HIV test, if the sensitivity of the test is 98 % and the specificity is 93 %, this would mean that 98 % of those infected would (correctly) test positive and 7 % of those not-infected would (incorrectly) also test positive. The diagnostic value of a positive result for the test would then be 98/(100 93) ¼ 14 and the probability of the patient being infected would be 14 times greater now that the test result is known than whatever it was estimated to be before the test result was known. The diagnostic value of a negative test result would in this case be 93 (the relative number of correct negatives) divided by (100 98) ¼ 2, the relative number of false negatives, i.e., 93 divided by 2 or 46.5. Scientific evidence may be said to have diagnostic value in much the same way as a medical test such as an HIV test, which will not provide absolute proof of infection or otherwise but, depending on the result and its diagnostic value, Philosophy of Forensic Identification will make infection more or less probable. Similarly, evidence may be more or less likely under one of two rival hypotheses. To the extent that the evidence favors, or better fits one hypothesis rather than another, it may be said to lend more support to that hypothesis. Bayes and the Prior Probability The likelihood ratio may be seen as a measure of the extent to which the hypothesis of interest is more probable or less probable after the scientific evidence is known than it was before the evidence was known. Another way of putting it is to say that we can update what we saw as the prior probability of the hypothesis with the evidence that has become available to arrive at the posterior probability of the hypothesis, in which the weight of the new evidence has been taken into account. By means of the Bayes’ Rule, the odds form of Bayes’ theorem, so called after the Rev. Thomas Bayes (1702–1761), we can calculate the posterior probability of a hypothesis by multiplying its prior probability with the likelihood ratio: Prior probability Likelihood ratio ¼ Posterior probability A simple example may illustrate the application of the rule. Suppose a prisoner is found dead and we may safely assume that one of the 99 remaining fellow prisoners in the ward is the perpetrator. As it happens, one of these 99 prisoners, S, admits to being the killer. His DNA profile is obtained and found to match with a partial profile obtained from the nail debris secured from the victim. The estimated frequency of the partial profile in the relevant population is 1 in 1,000. If the cell material in the nail debris originates from S, the likelihood of the evidence, i.e., the matching profile, would be 1, or 100 %. If, on the other hand, the cell material belonged to a random member of the population, the likelihood of a match would be 1 in 1,000 or 0.001. The likelihood ratio of the DNA evidence would therefore be 1 divided by 0.001 ¼ 1,000. 3521 P To determine the prior probability, we assume that all 99 remaining prisoners are equally likely to be the perpetrator. In that case, the prior probability of any one of them being the donor is 1/99, or, expressed in odds, 1 to 98. We can now calculate the prior probability of S being the donor of the cell material in the nail debris by applying Bayes’ rule: Prior probability LR ¼ Posterior probability ð1 to 98Þ 1; 000 ¼ 1; 000 to 98: The odds form of the posterior probability may be converted to a fraction, i.e., 1,000/1,098, and from that into a percentage, i.e., 91.1 %. This means that on the basis of the DNA evidence alone, the probability of the suspect being the donor of the cell material is 91.1 %, assuming that the donor is one of the remaining 99 prisoners. Of course, apart from the DNA evidence, the fact that S admitted to killing his fellow inmate is also relevant to the determination of the ultimate issue whether S is the perpetrator. However, this type of evidence as well as possible eyewitness accounts from fellow prisoners or prison staff, and any other non-DNA evidence, clearly extends beyond the domain of the DNA expert. Other experts might be able to assign a particular weight to a spontaneous confession or an eyewitness identification, in the form of a likelihood ratio. For example, empirical research may be available on which an estimate may be based of the diagnostic value (¼ likelihood ratio) of a confession. This could take the form of a statement that a confession is on average seven times more likely if the suspect is the perpetrator than if he is not. This evidence in turn could then be used to further update the hypothesis of guilt. When Numbers Are Lacking It is worth noting that the concept of the likelihood ratio may also be applied to evidence types where the frequency of relevant markers cannot be estimated in numerical terms, for example, because there are no suitable reference databases. P P 3522 This would in fact hold for many types of trace evidence, including handwriting, glass, paint, fibers, toolmarks, and firearms. The logical framework may then be applied to the verbal statements that are used in these fields. In response to the logical objections raised to the use of traditional probability scales in forensic identification, various proposals have been made in recent years for the introduction of logically correct verbal probability scales. One such format, developed at the Netherlands Forensic Institute (NFI) and used primarily in the various forensic identification disciplines, looks as follows: The findings of the comparative examination are equally likely/ more likely/ much more likely/ very much more likely under the prosecution hypothesis that the suspect is the source of trace material as/than under the defence hypothesis that a random member of the population is the source of the trace material Note that, true to the logical format, it is the likelihood of the evidence that is addressed. While the verbal phrases used clearly have a probabilistic basis, the probabilities are not based on quantitative empirical data but informed by the analyst’s experience and may be seen as internalized frequency estimates. In those exceptional cases where the forensic scientist arrives at a subjective conviction that the trace material originates from a particular source (as in physical fits of torn paper, or qualitatively superior shoe prints or tool marks), he or she might express his or her subjective conviction, emphasizing that this is precisely that – a subjective conviction, not a scientific fact. Words Versus Numbers In the United Kingdom as well as in some Continental European countries, conclusions in forensic identification are increasingly expressed in a slightly different logical format. According to the “standards for the formulation of evaluative forensic science expert opinion,” compiled by the Association of Forensic Science Providers (AoFSP 2009), “the evidential weight (. . .) is the Philosophy of Forensic Identification expression of the extent to which the observations support one of the two competing propositions. The extent of the support is expressed to the client in terms of a numerical value of the likelihood ratio (where sufficiently robust data is available) or a verbal scale related to the magnitude of the likelihood ratio when it is not.” (AoFSP 2009: p. 63) For this purpose, the following scale is used: Value of likelihood ratio >110 10100 1001,000 100010,000 10,0001,000,000 >1,000,000 Verbal equivalent Weak support for proposition Moderate support Moderately strong support Strong support Very strong Extremely strong In the case of the DNA evidence with a likelihood ratio of 1,000, the expert would either report the numerical value of the likelihood ratio as such or would report that the DNA evidence provides “moderately strong” to “strong” support to hypothesis 1 (the suspect is the donor). The decision to use the numerical or the verbal form would depend on the extent to which the expert considers the data underlying the calculation of the likelihood ratio to be robust. This sounds like a sensible criterion. However, there are those who advocate the blanket use of verbal terms, i.e., even if perfectly valid qualitative empirical data are available, arguing that the use of a uniform reporting format is vastly preferable and adding that quantitative data are generally too complex for nonscientists to grasp. The Prosecutor’s Fallacy Regardless of the use of words or numbers, statements of the probability of the evidence under a particular hypothesis, as made in the Bayesian approach, are often prone to misunderstanding and may strike the recipient as counterintuitive. The finding that the similarities observed between the handwriting of the writer of an anonymous letter and the reference material produced by the suspect are much more likely if the suspect wrote the questioned sample than if it was written by a random member of the population is often taken to mean the converse: that it is much more Philosophy of Forensic Identification likely that the suspect wrote the questioned handwriting sample than that it was written by a random member of the population. However, if we do this, we are guilty of making a fundamental logical error which, in the judicial context, has come to be referred to as the prosecutor’s fallacy (Thompson and Schumann 1987). Although the term would seem to suggest that prosecutors are particularly prone to this fallacy, it is in fact an example of a more general type of error that is often made in the context of probability statements or inverse reasoning, where it is known as the “fallacy of the transposed conditional.” In its simplest form, it is easily spotted: if an animal is a cow, it is very likely to have four legs. However, the converse clearly does not hold: if an animal has four legs, it is not very likely to be a cow. Transposed conditionals or prosecutor’s fallacies are very frequently encountered in the context of DNA evidence. Suppose a partial profile is obtained from a crime scene sample whose frequency in the relevant population is estimated to be smaller than 1 in 100,000. If the expert subsequently reports the probability that a random member of the population has the same profile as the crime scene sample as being smaller than, say, 1 in a 100,000, this statement is frequently understood to mean that the probability that the DNA does not originate from the suspect is smaller than 1 in a 100,000. However, the former is clearly a statement of the probability of the evidence (i.e., a match with the partial profile), while the latter is a statement of the posterior probability of the source hypothesis. Mathematically, the latter statement would be correct in a situation where the prior probability was set at 50 %, or 1 to 1. This would be the case if, in addition to the matching suspect, only one person would equally qualify as a possible donor, which will not frequently be a reasonable assumption to make. If, for the sake of the argument, the prior probability were set at 200,000 (e.g., the size of the adult male population of a large town), application of the odds form of the Bayes’ rule would yield a posterior probability of 33.3 %: (1 to 200,000) 100,000 ¼ 1 to 2, or 33.3 %. 3523 P Transposed conditionals may also occur in the context of cause and effect arguments. While it is correct to say that the street will be wet if it has been raining, the converse is clearly not necessarily true. The single observation that the street is wet does not allow us to infer that it must have been raining, or even that it has probably been raining. Alternative explanations are possible: The street may have got wet when the police used water cannon to break up a demonstration, or it is wet because somebody has just been washing his car. So we can make a statement about the likelihood of a particular finding (e.g., a wet street) under a particular hypothesis (“it has been raining”) but not about the probability of this same hypothesis merely on the basis of the finding that the street is wet. To determine the posterior probability that it has been raining, we need to combine the evidence of the wet street with the prior probability of rain. In England, the prior would be high, but in a country like Dubai, it would presumably be very low. The same evidence combined with vastly different priors may lead to very different posterior probabilities. Controversy The Bayesian approach is not uncontroversial. Its opponents frequently view its advocates as “believers” (Risinger 2012). More specifically, critics of the Bayesian approach object to the subjective nature of the prior probability, as well as to the use of likelihood ratios which lack an empirical basis. While the former criticism is clearly valid, it might be argued that the explicit consideration of the prior probability and the formulation of alternative hypotheses is a virtue in that it helps identify the relevant questions and prevents tunnel vision. The conclusion format propagated by the predominantly British Association of Forensic Science Providers is not unproblematic either, in that a phrase, like “the examination provides strong support for the proposition that X originates from Y,” will almost invariably be interpreted to mean that it is very likely that X originates from Y. Without due warning, logically correct conclusions of this type will P P 3524 almost inevitably tend to be mistaken for the logically flawed ones they are meant to replace. A further problem is highlighted by a decision of the English Court of Appeal in R v T (2010). In it, the judges express sharp criticism of the report of a footwear expert, who, quite in line with the policy of the (now defunct) UK Forensic Science Service, had phrased his conclusion in verbal terms without making it clear to the judge or the jury that the verbal conclusion was based on a quantitative estimate of the frequency of the characteristics size, pattern, and wear as exhibited by the shoe mark found at the crime scene. The expert’s conclusion was formulated as: “(. . .) there is at this stage a moderate degree of scientific evidence to support the view that [the Nike trainers recovered from the appellant] had made the footwear marks.” However, as later appeared from case notes that were not added to the original report, the expert had calculated a likelihood ratio of 100, which number he had subsequently converted into the verbal phrase “moderate support,” in accordance with the scale presented above. In addition, counsel for the appellant pointed out to the Court of Appeal that in his testimony in court in response to questions by the defense, the expert had mentioned estimates of the relevant characteristics of the shoe mark which, when combined, would lead to a likelihood ratio of no less than 26,400, in which case the footwear evidence would have been much more incriminating (in verbal terms expressed as “very strong support”). The Court of Appeal’s judgment is perfectly clear: The process by which the evidence was adduced lacked transparency. (. . .) it is simply wrong in principle for an expert to fail to set out the way in which he has reached his conclusion in his report. The Court of Appeal continues: (. . .) the practice of using a Bayesian approach and likelihood ratios to formulate opinions placed before a jury without that process being disclosed and debated in court is contrary to principles of open justice. The ruling in R v T has led to various reactions, many (Berger et al. 2011; Evett 2011; Redmayne et al. 2011) but not all (Risinger 2012) in defense Philosophy of Forensic Identification of the Bayesian approach. While one may disagree with some of the views expressed in the Court of Appeal judgment, recent research conducted in the Netherlands suggests that there is at least one other problem with the use of these “logically correct” conclusion formats. It appears that evaluative opinions expressed in the Bayesian format are likely to be misunderstood not only by defense lawyers and judges but also by forensic experts themselves. Participants in the study were asked to indicate for a variety of statements whether they were correct paraphrases of the Bayesian style conclusions that were used in a fictitious report. The study shows that a proper understanding of statements involving likelihood ratios by jurists is alarmingly poor. In order to be able to compare actual versus supposed understanding, participants were also asked to indicate how well they understood the Bayesian style conclusions of the reports on a scale from 1 (“I do not understand it at all.”) to 7 (“I understand it perfectly.”). The most worrying finding to emerge from the study is no doubt that not only did judges, defense lawyers, and forensic experts alike tend to interpret the conclusions of the submitted reports incorrectly but they combined their lack of understanding with a high degree of overestimation: They believed they understood the conclusions much better than in fact they did. This suggests that the continued use of Bayesian style conclusion formats or likelihood ratios requires a major educational effort if structural miscommunication between experts and triers of fact is to be avoided. Aitken et al. (2010) and Puch-Solis (2012) may be seen as attempts to meet this demand. Conclusion The findings of a comparative examination undertaken with a view to establishing the source of a particular trace or set of traces do not strictly allow the type of probabilistic source attributions, be they of a quantitative or verbal nature, that until recently were used by the vast majority of forensic practitioners. With the advent of forensic DNA analysis over the last decades and the widespread use of the conceptual framework Philosophy of Forensic Identification associated with the interpretation of DNA evidence, awareness among forensic practitioners of other identification disciplines of the inadequacies of the traditional evidence evaluation paradigm has grown rapidly. Increasingly, this is leading to attempts to apply a logically correct way to express the value of the findings of a source attribution examination of trace material other than DNA by expressing the weight of the trace evidence in a way similar to that used in forensic DNA analysis. This takes the form of a so-called likelihood ratio. The concept is similar to that of the diagnostic value, a measure which has found wide acceptance in fields like medicine and psychology as a way to express the value of any diagnostic test result. The concept of the likelihood ratio requires the consideration of the probability of the evidence under two competing hypotheses, one based on a proposition formulated by the police or the prosecution, the other based on an alternative proposition which may be based on a scenario put forward by the defense. As such, the Bayesian approach may be seen as a remedy against suspect-driven investigations, in which the police tend to focus on collecting evidence that will confirm the suspect’s involvement in the crime and ignores alternative explanations. By contrast, in a crime-driven investigation, the investigators base the direction of the investigation on the clues provided by the crime rather than by the person of the suspect and develop one or more scenarios based on the evidence rather than make the evidence fit a particular scenario. Technical or scientific evidence derived from material traces such as DNA, finger marks, handwriting, fibers, footwear marks, or digital data derived from a harddisk or a mobile telephone may be incompatible with a particular hypothesis that is central to a larger scenario and then effectively eliminate that scenario. More frequently, scientific evidence may be more or less likely to be found in one scenario than another and in this way may help discriminate between various scenarios. It is the consideration of the totality of evidence, both direct, witness and scientific evidence if available, which forms the basis for the ultimate decision made by the trier of fact. 3525 P Related Entries ▶ Automated and Manual Forensic Examinations ▶ Bayesian Updating and Crime ▶ Cognitive Forensics: Human Cognition, Contextual Information, and Bias ▶ Crime Science ▶ Criminal Investigative Analysis ▶ DNA Profiling ▶ DNA Technology and Police Investigations ▶ Fingerprint Identification ▶ Forensic Science in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries ▶ Identification and the Development of Forensic Science ▶ Identification Technologies in Policing and Proof ▶ Scientific Basis of the Forensic Process ▶ Scientific Evidence in Criminal Prosecutions Recommended Reading and References Aitken C, Roberts P, Jackson G (2010) Communicating and interpreting statistical evidence in the administration of criminal justice: fundamentals of probability and statistical evidence. In criminal proceedings – Guidance for judges, lawyers, forensic scientists and expert witnesses, Royal Statistical Society, London Association of Forensic Science Providers (2009) Standards for the formulation of evaluative forensic science expert opinion. Sci Justice 49:161–164 Berger CEH, Buckleton J, Champod C, Evett IW, Jackson G (2011) Evidence evaluation: a response to the court of appeal judgment in R v T. Sci Justice 51:43–49 Broeders APA (2006) Of earprints, fingerprints, scent dogs, cot deaths and cognitive contamination: a brief look at the present state of play in the forensic arena. Forensic Sci Int 159(2–3):148–157 Cook R, Evett IW, Jackson G, Jones PJ, Lambert JA (1998a) A model of case assessment and interpretation. Sci Justice 38(3):151–156 Cook R, Evett IW, Jackson G, Jones PJ, Lambert JA (1998b) A hierarchy of propositions: deciding which level to address in casework. Sci Justice 38(4):231–239 de Keijser J, Elffers H (2010) Understanding of forensic expert reports by judges, defense lawyers and forensic professionals. Psychol Crime Law 18(2):191–207 Evett IW (2011) Expressing evaluative opinions: a position statement. Sci Justice 51:1–2 Inman K, Rudin R (2000) Principles and practice of criminalistics: the profession of forensic science. CRC, Boca Raton P P 3526 Inman K, Rudin R (2002) The origin of evidence. Forensic Sci Int 126:11–16 Kirk PL (1963) The ontogeny of criminalistics. J Crim Law Criminol Police Sci 54:235–238 Kirk PL, Grunbaum BW (1968) Individuality of blood and its forensic significance. Leg Med Annu 289–325 Popper KR (1959) The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchinson, London Puch-Solis R, Roberts P, Pope S, Aitken C (2012) Communicating and interpreting statistical evidence in the administration of criminal justice: 2. Assessing the probative value of DNA evidence. Royal Statistical Society, London Quetelet A (1870) Anthropome´trie ou Mesure des Diffe´rentes Faculte´s de l’Homme. Muquardt, Bruxelles R v T (2010) EWCA Crim 2439 Raymond JJ, Walsh SJ, Van Oorschot RA, Roux C (2004) Trace DNA: an under-utilized resource or Pandora’s box? – A review of the use of trace DNA analysis in the investigation of volume crime. J Forensic Identif 54(6):668–686 Redmayne M, Roberts P, Aitken CGG, Jackson G (2011) Forensic science evidence in question. Crim Law Rev 5:347–356 Risinger DM (2012) Reservations about likelihood ratios (and some other aspects of forensic ‘Bayesianism’). Law Probab Risk 0:1–11 Saks MJ, Koehler JJ (2005) The coming paradigm shift in forensic identification science. Science 309:892–895 Saks MJ, Koehler JJ (2008) The individualization fallacy in forensic science evidence. Vanderbilt Law Rev 61:199–219 Stoney DA (1991) What made us ever think we could individualize using statistics? J Forensic Sci Soc 31(2):197–199 Thompson WC, Schumann EL (1987) Interpretation of statistical evidence in criminal trials: the prosecutor’s fallacy and the defence attorney’s fallacy. Law Hum Behav 11:167–187 Thornton JI, Peterson JL (2002) ‘The general assumptions and rationale of forensic identification’ } 24–2.0–2.1. In: Faigman DL, Kaye DH, Saks MJ, Sanders J (eds) Modern scientific evidence: the law and science of expert testimony. West Publishing Co, St. Paul Thorwald JT (1965) The century of the detective. Harcourt, Brace & World, New York, first published in German as Das Jahrhundert der Detektive, Droemersche Verlagsanstalt: Z€ urich 1964 Physical Punishment Place-Based Randomized Trials Robert Boruch1, David Weisburd2,3, Richard A. Berk4 and Breanne Cave5 1 Graduate School of Education, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA, USA 2 Department of Criminology, Law and Society, George Mason University, Fairfax, VA, USA 3 Faculty of Law, The Hebrew University, Mt. Scopus, Jerusalem, Israel 4 Department of Criminology, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA, USA 5 George Mason University, Fairfax, VA, USA Overview Place-randomized trials are an important vehicle for generating evidence about “what works” in criminology. Place-based randomized trials are a form of cluster randomization that involves identifying a sample of places (for instance, crime hot spots) and randomly allocating these locations to different police or community interventions. Random allocation assures a fair comparison among the interventions, and when the analysis is correct, a legitimate statistical statement of confidence in the resulting estimates of their effectiveness can be made. This entry provides basic definitions and practical counsel about the use of such trials in generating evidence in crime prevention. It also identifies issues, ideas, and challenges that might be addressed by future research. Finally, it discusses the special analytic difficulties that may occur in the development of place-randomized trials as opposed to more traditional trials where individuals are the units of allocation and analysis. Places that Are Randomized: Theory and Units of Randomization Physical Punishment ▶ History of Corporal Punishment Place-randomized trials depend on a clear understanding of the role of place. A place can be an entity in itself; for instance, a business establishment that has a legal status separates from that of Place-Based Randomized Trials owners or employees. Or a place can be an organizational convenience for smaller units within it. One may, for instance, become interested in the effect of neighborhood context on the likelihood of individual victimization. Inasmuch as individual habits can also contribute to risk of victimization, attention may also be directed toward both the attributes of neighborhoods as well as to the individuals who live within the neighborhood. Whether the place is an entity per se or a receptacle for lower-level observational units can dramatically affect how the randomized trial is designed and analyzed. The key definitional point in a “place-randomized trial,” however, is that the random assignment occurs at the place level. The implication is that the methodological benefits of random assignment are realized across places, not the units within them. Statistical analysis at the place level therefore conforms to well-understood and accepted statistical practices. Analysis attempted at the level of the nonrandomized units which are nested within places can be complex and controversial. The “units of randomization” in a placerandomized trial may vary considerably. Weisburd and Green’s (1995) study, for instance, operationalized “drug hot spots” as street segments rather than institutions such as housing developments, schools, or business units. The broad theory underlying the trial posited that focusing police and other resources on these hot spots would reduce crime, rather than leading to no effect or a migration of criminal activity into other areas. An earlier crime hot spot trial by Sherman and Weisburd (1995) in Minneapolis similarly defined the unit of analysis as a single street segment from intersection to intersection. Other places have been targeted for different types of interventions, such as saloons in the context of preventing violence and glasswarerelated injuries (Warburton and Sheppard 2000). Private properties, including apartment houses and businesses, have been targeted in a study of the effects of civil remedies and drug control (Mazerolle et al. 2000). Convenience stores, crack houses, and other entities have also been randomly allocated to different interventions. 3527 P These examples invite a number of basic questions. How can such trials be deployed well? Can better theory be developed about what should happen as a consequence of an intervention at high levels of units: province or county, city or village, institution or housing development, or crime hot spot? Can theories be developed to guide thinking about change or rate of change at the primary aggregate level – the places – and below it? What new statistical problems emerge from randomization of places? These examples also invite questions about how to learn about other trials of this sort, involving yet other units of allocation and analysis. Relationships and Agreements People get place-randomized trials off the ground through agreements between the trialist’s team and prospective partners in the place-based trial. Here, “partners” mean individuals or groups whose cooperation and experience are essential in deploying both the intervention and the trial. Weisburd (2005) emphasizes the need to develop personal relationships that lead to trust and willingness to experiment on innovations that might work better than conventional practice. In his Jersey City experiment, for instance, the strong involvement of the senior police commander as principal investigator in the study played a critical role in preventing a breakdown of the experiment after 9 months. In Jersey City, the Deputy Chief who administered the interventions was strongly convinced of the failures of traditional approaches and the need to test new ones. The commander took personal authority over the narcotic unit and used his command powers to carefully monitor the daily activities of detectives in the trial. This style of work suggests the importance of integrating “clinical” and research work in criminal justice, much as they are integrated in medical experiments. It also reinforces the importance of practitioner “belief” in the necessity of implementing a randomized study. The Kingswood experiment described by Clarke and Cornish (1972) illustrates how doubts regarding the application P P 3528 of experimental treatment led practitioners to undermine the implementation of the study. Place-randomized trials do not only involve the practitioners and researchers who are directly involved with implementation and analysis. For instance, in policing, federal funding agencies, such as the National Institute of Justice and the Bureau of Justice Assistance; accreditation agencies; and professional organizations such as the International Association of Chiefs of Police, the Police Executive Research Forum, or the Major Cities Chiefs Police Association can all influence the willingness of individual police departments to adopt place-based practices and implement place-based trials. The capacity of researchers and practitioners to carry out place-randomized trials is therefore often influenced by the preferences and priorities of these institutional stakeholders. Developing relationships in place-randomized trials as in many other kinds of field research depends on reputation and trust, of course. The topic invites attention to questions for the future. How can better contracts and agreements in networks of organizations, public and private, ones that permit us to generate better evidence about the effects of an innovation, be developed? How can “model” contracts and memorandums of understanding be developed and made available to other trialists and their potential collaborators? Justifications for a Place-Randomized Trial For many social scientists, an important condition for mounting a randomized trial on any intervention that is purported to work is that (a) the effectiveness of a conventional practice, policy, or program is debatable and (b) the debates can be informed by better scientific evidence. In the crime sector, police of course are local theorists, and they often disagree about what could work better. Crime experts have also disagreed about what approaches might be effective in high-crime areas. More generally, of course, people disagree with one another about what might work in the Place-Based Randomized Trials policy sector, and there is, at times, some agreement that better evidence would be helpful. For instance, Weisburd (2003) points out that one of the major justifications for random trials is disagreement among experts about the effectiveness of an intervention. This is an important factor in justifying a randomized trial using individuals or places as the units of random allocation. For instance, the Cambridge-Somerville Youth Study, one of the most famous experiments in youth crime prevention, illustrated that even well-planned and implemented intervention programs may have no effect on offending behavior or even have a “backfire” effect (McCord 2003). Experimental studies of the effectiveness of random beat patrol and foot patrol likewise provided surprising results regarding the effectiveness of widely accepted standard practices in criminal justice in reducing crime (Kelling et al. 1974). In these cases, experimental research concerning the effectiveness of commonly accepted practices spurred criminologists and criminal justice agencies to revise and improve intervention strategies. The scientific justification for placerandomized trials is the assurance that if the trial is carried out properly, there are no systematic differences between groups of places randomized, which in turn carries a guarantee of statistically unbiased estimates the intervention’s effect. It also assures that chance and chance imbalances can be taken into account and that a legitimate statistical statement of one’s confidence in the results can be made. Further, Weisburd (2005) and others have pointed out that the simplicity and transparency of the idea of fair comparison through a randomized trial has a strong appeal for policy makers and practitioners who cannot understand and do not trust complex model-based analyses of data from nonrandomized studies. For the abiding statistician, the crucial aspect of simplicity is that the statistical inferences as to the effect’s size relative to chance need not depend on econometric, statistical, or mathematical models. The randomization feature permits and invites less dependence on such speculation. And modern methods permit the use of randomization tests. Place-Based Randomized Trials The empirical evidence on the vulnerability of evidence from nonrandomized trials in comparison to the evidence from randomized trials has been building since at least the late 1940s. Assuring that one does not depend on weak and easily assailable evidence when stronger evidence can be produced is an incentive at times in parts of the policy community. Assuring that one does not needlessly depend on heroic assumptions to produce good estimates of effect, assumptions often required in the nonrandomized trials, is an incentive for the scientific and statistical community. Boruch (2007) summarizes these concepts in the field of health care, employment and training, and economics. Shadish and colleagues (2008) provided a persuasive illustration that is especially compelling because comparisons between a randomized experiment and an observational study were anticipated as part of their research design and before the data were collected. Their results suggest comparability, as opposed to major differences, if the quasi-experiment is designed well in a particular domain. Theirs is an interesting and potentially important specific case. More generally, the biases in estimating an intervention’s effect based on the quasi-experiments can be very large, small, or nonexistent (Weisburd et al. 2001). The variance in estimates of effects appears to be typically larger in the quasi-experiments than in the randomized tests. So far, and with some narrow exceptions, there is no way to predict the directionality or magnitude of such biases or in the variances of the estimates of the intervention’s effect based on a nonrandomized trial. It remains to be seen whether similar methodological studies on aggregate level analyses using randomized versus nonrandomized places, clusters of individuals, or groups yield similar results, that is, uncover serious biases in estimating effects or the variance of the estimates or both. But it is reasonable to expect biases here also. Bertrand, Duflo, and Mullainathan (2002), for instance, focused on biases in estimates of the standard error of effects assuming no effect at all using conventional difference in differences methods and found type I error rates that were nine times the error rate presumed (0.05) in using 3529 P conventional statistical tests. This was partly on account of serial correlation. More methodological research, however, needs to be done on the quasi-experimental approaches to aggregate level units so as to understand when the biases in estimates of effect appear, when the biases in estimates of their standard errors appear, and how large the mean square error is, relative to place-randomized trials. It is important to identify dependable scenarios in which bias and variance of estimates generated in nonrandomized trials are tolerable. Doing so can reduce the need for randomized trials (Boruch 2007). It is also not easy, as yet, to identify particular scenarios in which bias in estimates of effect or variance will be small, as was the case in some work by Shadish et al. (2008). Berk’s (2005) more general handling of the strengths and weaknesses of randomized controlled trials at the individual level is pertinent to the analysis of data generated in place-randomized trials also. The scientific justifications that are identified here are important in the near term. In the long term, it would be good to understand what other incentives are and to make these explicit at different levels, for example, policy, institution (agencies), and individual service-provider levels. Incentives for better evidence may differ depending on whether the stakeholders are members of the police force at different levels, the mayor’s office, and the community organizations that have a voice, and so on. Many police executives, for instance, want to improve policing and produce evidence on whether things do improve and also usually want to keep their jobs. The two incentives may not always be compatible if a city council or mayoral preferences are antagonistic toward defensible evidence generated in well-run field tests. Sturdy indifference to dependable evidence of any kind is, of course, a problem in some policy sectors. Deploying the Intervention: Implementation, Dimensionalization, and Measurement Justifications and incentives are essential for assuring that places, and influential people within P P 3530 them, are willing to participate in a randomized trial. Understanding how to deploy a new program requires expertise at a ground level, as well as substantial cooperation between researchers and mid- and upper-level management. It also requires constant communication between researchers and street-level practitioners to ensure that their daily practices conform to the treatment that they intend to occur. The Drug Market Analysis Program, which fostered a series of randomized experiments on crime hot spots, suggests that “ordinary” criminal justice agencies can be brought on board to participate in experimental study if there is strong governmental encouragement and financial support that rewards participation (see Weisburd et al. 2006). A similar experience in the Spouse Assault Replication Program (SARP) reinforces these observations. Joel Garner (2002), who served as program manager for SARP, noted that he knew that the program was a success the “day that we got 17 proposals with something like 21 police agencies willing to randomly assign offenders to be arrested” (Weisburd 2005, p. 232). Day-to-day implementation of placerandomized trials also requires significant forethought on the part of both the researchers and middle managers who are involved with the experiments. For instance, during Lum and colleagues’ (2010) trial of the effectiveness of license plate recognition systems, the research team made an effort to directly involve both the officers who would be implementing the intervention and the middle managers who would be responsible for directly supervising the officers in the process of identifying hot spots, developing mechanisms for reporting officer patrol, and overseeing implementation. Given that the intervention involved the participation of two separate police departments, it was also important to understand and account for different practices in supervising officers, in the responsibilities of officers to continue to respond to calls for service, and other functions. Gaining an understanding of the experience and obligations of these practitioners allowed the researchers to revise plans for patrol deployment Place-Based Randomized Trials and ensure that the experiment could realistically be implemented given the normal practices of the two police departments. The reports on deploying programs and the randomized trials that are published in peerreviewed journals can be excellent, but they are typically brief. The brevity invites broad questions about how the authors’ experience in detail can be shared with others, that is, through web-based journals, reports without page limits, workshops, and so on. It invites more scientific attention to the question of how one can dimensionalize implementation and the engineering questions of how to measure or observe implementation level inexpensively and how to establish a high threshold condition for implementation. Resources for the Trial’s Design, Statistical Problems, and Solutions Some of the important technical references for trial design and model-based data analysis include Hayes and Moulton (2009) on clusterrandomized trials in different countries, mainly in the health arena. Murray’s (1998) book on group-randomized trials focuses more on individuals within groups and considers diverse applications in the USA. Bryk and Raudenbush’s (2002) text considers in detail model-based statistical analyses of multilevel data that may or may not have been generated in randomized trials. The models are complex and entail assumptions that the analyst may not find acceptable. In the context of place-randomized, clusterrandomized, or group-randomized trials, there are few publications covering the simplest and least model-dependent approaches to analyzing data from such a trial. Such approaches fall under the rubric of randomization tests or permutation tests. A simple randomization test, for instance, involves computing all possible outcomes of the trial, ignoring the actual allocation to intervention or control conditions, and then making a probabilistic judgment about the dependability of the effect detected based on the distribution of possible outcomes so generated. There is no dependence on linear or other parametric models. Place-Based Randomized Trials Given the relatively small sample sizes involved in place-randomized trials (typically less than 200 are allocated to one or another intervention) and given contemporary computing capacity, generating the distribution of possible outcomes in these approaches is relatively straightforward. The basic concepts were described by Sir Ronald Fisher in the 1950s for trials in which individuals or plants were the independent units of random allocation and analysis. The idea is directly relevant to trials in which places are randomly allocated and inferences are made about the effects of intervention in places. The Campbell Collaboration organized conferences on place-randomized trials in 2001 and 2002 to update researchers on the design and conduct of place-randomized trials. A special issue of the Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Sciences (Vol. 599, 2005) resulted from these. After 2002, the William T. Grant Foundation funded workshops and software development to enhance the technical capacity of researchers to design such trials and analyze results. At the time of this writing, there was no information on more specialized efforts sponsored by the National Institute of Justice or private foundations in criminology. One of the major scientific challenges in designing a place-randomized trial is assuring that the size of the sample of places is large enough to detect the relative effects of interventions. A statistical power analysis is essential to this planning process and allows the researcher to determine the number of places that are needed given assumptions about the expected effect size, randomization levels, and specific statistical tests of hypotheses and related procedures. Userfriendly software for estimating the modelbased statistical power of a trial under various assumptions about sample size and other factors is available on the William T. Grant Foundation’s website (http://www.wtgrantfdn.org). There are a number of common mistakes made during analysis of place-randomized trials. First, researchers have often wrongly employed the number of people in places for hypothesis testing and power analysis rather than employing the 3531 P number of places randomly allocated (see, e.g., Kelling et al. 1974). Second, simple linear regression models are often used to analyze data even though many of the modeling assumptions are not necessarily true, as the “uncertainty” in randomized trials stems from the assignment process, rather than unobservable disturbances that are assumed to be the source of variation in regression models (see Freedman 2008). It is very difficult to determine how misleading the results of such regression analyses are likely to be in multilevel contexts. Analyses based on regression models with categorical, count, or time-tofailure outcomes create additional problems (Freedman 2008). Place-based trials often involve the study of people within places, and thus, a very small number of independent units (places) may be present at the randomized level and a large number of related units (people) may be nested within each place. A key issue in this scenario is that individuals or other units within a place were not randomly assigned to the intervention or control conditions. Randomization at the place level ensures that preexisting differences between treatment and control groups in the study are not systematic; this is due to the matching and subsequent randomization process. However, since all individuals within each place are automatically assigned the same condition, intervention, or control, the analysis is riskier to carry out at the individual level (Raudenbush and Bryk 2002; Spybrook et al. 2006). Prior techniques for clustered data involved either aggregating all information to the group level as in a randomization test or a “t-test” of mean differences between place level outcomes or have involved disaggregating all group-level traits and confining attention to all the individuals within the intervention and control conditions. For Raudenbush and Bryk (2002), the problem with the first method is that all within group information is wasted; it is omitted from the analysis. The problem with the second method is that the observations are no longer independent, as all individuals within a certain intervention or control condition will have the same value on a certain variable and will not be independent P P 3532 from one another on account of the intra-class correlation among people within place. To account for the dependence that arises when using samples of individuals nested within places, researchers can use several statistical methods to correct for clustering, such as hierarchical linear modeling techniques (i.e., HLM) and generalized least squares estimation techniques with robust standard errors. There are several options for analyzing the results of place-based randomized experiments in a largely model-free manner. Small and colleagues (2008), for instance, emphasize randomization/permutation tests with different kinds of adjustments for covariates, not relying on any form of HLM. Imai, Kind, and Nall (2009) advanced the state of the art by showing how matched pair designs in place-randomized trials can often enhance precision in estimates of the effects of interventions, increase statistical power of analysis in detecting effects, and better assure unbiased estimates of variability of the effect with a small number of places. Matched pair designs can also be used in this context, but the concern is that matching may unnecessarily reduce degrees of freedom and statistical power of the studies. As a practical matter, the work by Imai and his colleagues (2009) shows that the number of units within a place are an important matching variable that can reduce costs and increase statistical power in a trial. Bloom and Riccio (2005) advance the state of the art in another important respect by coupling conventional comparison of randomized places in a time series analysis of data from places. While the coupling of randomized and nonrandomized approaches to estimating effects of interventions is not a new concept (see, e.g., Boruch 1985), incorporating these ideas thoroughly into design and analysis is unusual. Another novel contribution relating to designing place-randomized trials lays in the idea of “step wedge” and “dynamic wait list” designs. The wait list design assigns a random half sample of eligible places to the intervention for some period of time. The remaining half sample receives the intervention after this period has Place-Based Randomized Trials ended, under the assumption that all units will eventually receive the intervention. While this approach satisfies ethical concerns that may arise if a beneficial treatment is not administered to certain places, it may be problematic if there are treatment consequences for a delay in treatment. To address such concerns about the sequence of treatment, places may also be divided into subsets which are periodically given treatments of a given intensity at a given time period. In a related area of work, Hussey and Hughes (2006) develop the idea of step wedged designs, with the “steps” being a point at which a subset of places is randomly assigned a treatment. The step wedge and dynamic wait list designs are innovative and have attractive features. However, the power and design analysis of these approaches have relied on hierarchical linear models with unusual and sometimes untestable assumptions. There may be alternatives that are less model dependent. Registers of Place-Randomized Trials Learning about place-randomized trials can be difficult. Reports may be published in a variety of scientific journals and may appear in unpublished (gray) literature. Relying on webbased searches may not be as effective as hand searches in terms of locating randomized trials in social sciences. Taljaard et al. (2009), for instance, found that fewer than 50 % of published place-randomized trials in health are appropriately classified in titles and abstracts. There are a number of data sources concerning randomized trials that can help to reduce these difficulties. For instance, the Cochrane and Campbell Collaborations, which are concerned with the fields of health care and social sciences, respectively (including psychology, education, criminal justice, and sociology), publish reviews of results of randomized trials in which references to original sources can be accessed through their websites. In the United States, one can learn about trials in the health sector, including placerandomized trials, at http://www.clinicaltrials. gov. Often the interventions tested or the Place-Based Randomized Trials outcome variables examined in these trials are pertinent to criminologists as well as health-care researchers and practitioners. Finally, in 2007 David Greenberg and Mark Schroder developed a new register of randomized trials oriented toward tests of economic interventions under the auspices of the Social Sciences Research Network (SSRN). Standards for reporting randomized trials where individuals are the unit of allocation were the product of the late 1990s. The Consolidated Standards of Reporting Trials (CONSORT) statement, which provided guidance on the composition of a report on randomized trial in health care, has been modified to provide guidance on reporting place-randomized trials. For instance, studies should provide information on the rationale for a randomized design and measure outcomes on all levels of sampling and statistical inference. As of this writing, there are no uniform standards for reporting randomized trials in criminal justice. These problems have been raised by scholars of criminology who have emphasized that “reporting validity” is critical for the development of experimental science in criminology (Perry et al. 2009; Gill 2009; Farrington 2003). A lack of clear and uniform standards in this area of research means that reanalysis of experimental studies is difficult and often impossible. While some funding agencies have tried to make policy to assure that independent analysts have access to record data in research that they sponsor, clear criteria such as that included in the CONSORT statement are critical for advancing experimental criminology. Ethics and the Law As of this writing, no professional society or government agency has promulgated explicit statements about the ethical propriety of placerandomized trials. Applying contemporary standards to place-randomized trials can be awkward and imperfect (see, e.g., Boruch 2007), and at times, standards of ethics and government regulations are not clearly relevant to placerandomized trials (see, e.g., Taljaard et al. 2009, 3533 P for a discussion of these issues in health care). For instance, ethical standards established for the treatment of human subjects are arguably inappropriate for randomly allocated treatment in a city’s crime hot spots. The ethical issues surrounding place-based trials in criminology are complex. For instance, researchers may confront concerns about equality of treatment, as in research surrounding hot spot policing, wherein residents were concerned that concentrated patrol in one area would result in reduced services in other locations (see Weisburd 2005). Or officers could feel that sitting for extended periods of time reduces their capacity to protect the public (Weisburd et al. 2006). Finally, residents of areas that are designated as crime hot spots may feel as if they are being unfairly targeted by the police. In these cases, the implementation of a place-randomized trial can undermine the relationship between the practitioners involved in the trial and the clients whom they serve (see also Clarke and Cornish 1972). Regardless of the ethical dilemmas engendered by place-based trials over the last decade, there appear to have been no serious challenges in the US courts to the conduct of place-randomized trials. For instance, the former director of the Institute for Education Sciences (IES), Russ Whitehurst, reported in a personal communication (2008) that he had encountered no court challenges as a consequence of the IES’s sponsoring many such trials in education during 2002–2008. Similarly, we are aware of no judicial challenges in the context of placerandomized trials in the crime sector, such as the trials on crime hot spots, bar room violence, convenience store vulnerability to holdups, and so on. Conclusions and Implications for the Future Place-randomized trials have become important not only in criminology but also in a broad range of other disciplines because they employ substantive theory about the effects of intervention at the place level. The experience of people who have P P 3534 been involved in the design, execution, and analysis of place-randomized trials is an important source of intellectual and social capital. This experience must be exploited by future researchers and incorporated into graduate and postgraduate education, as should the knowledge of researchers in disciplines such as medicine and education who have substantially advanced the state of knowledge about more generally clusterrandomized trials. The statistical armamentarium for design and analysis of place-randomized trials is fundamental and lies on the simple idea of randomization rather than complex statistical models. Future development of placerandomized trials should better explore the implications of randomization of different interventions when the expected effects of the interventions are in “equipoise” and advance investigations into the ethics of this type of research. Further, standardized reporting of design, execution, and analysis of placerandomized trials should be advanced in criminology to allow for reanalysis and secondary analysis, particularly of controversial studies. Walter Lippmann, an able social scientist and newspaper writer, had a strong interest in cops and crimes by adults and adolescents and was familiar with political ambivalence about or opposition to sound evidence. He was a streetlevel criminologist, remarkable writer, and good thinker. In the 1940s, Lippmann said: “The problem is one for which public remedies are most likely to be found by choosing the most obvious issues and tackling them experimentally. . .the commissions of study are more likely to be productive if they can study the effects of practical experimentation.” Nowadays, trialists in criminology would have little difficulty in subscribing to Lippmann’s counsel. Related Entries ▶ Cambridge-Somerville Youth Experiment ▶ Criminology of Place ▶ History of Geographic Criminology Part I: Nineteenth Century Place-Based Randomized Trials ▶ History of the Statistics of Crime and Criminal Justice ▶ Hot Spots and Place-Based Policing ▶ Randomized Block Designs ▶ Randomized Experiments in Criminology and Criminal Justice Recommended Reading and References Berk R (2005) Randomized experiments as the bronze standard. J Exp Criminol 1(4):417–433 Bertrand M, Duflo E, Mullainathan S (2002) How much should we trust difference in differences estimates? Working paper 8841. National Bureau of Economic Research, Cambridge Bloom HS, Riccio JA (2005) Using place random assignment and comparative interrupted time-series analysis to evaluate the jobs-plus employment program for public housing residents. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 599:19–51 Boruch RF (2007) Encouraging the flight of error: ethical standards, evidence standards, and randomized trials. N Dir Eval 133:55–73 Boruch RF, Wothke W (1985) Seven kinds of randomization plans for designing field experiments. N Dir Prog Eval 28:95–113 Bryk AS, Raudenbush SW (2002) Hierarchical linear models. Sage, Thousand Oaks Clarke RVG, Cornish DB (1972) Controlled trial in institutional research – paradigm or pitfall for penal evaluators. The Home Office, London Farrington DP (2003) Methodological standards for evaluation research. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 587(1):49–68 Freedman DA (2008) Randomization does not justify logistic regression. Stat Sci 23:237–249 Gill C (2009) Reporting in criminological journals. Report for seminar on advanced topics in experimental design. Graduate School of Education and Criminology Department, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia Hussey MA, Hughes JP (2006) Design and analysis of stepped wedge cluster randomized trials. Contemp Clin Trials 28(2):182–191 Imai K, King G, Nall C (2009) The essential role of pair matching in cluster randomized experiments, with application to the Mexican universal health insurance evaluation. Stat Sci 24:29 Kelling GL, Pate T, Dieckman D, Brown CE (1974) Kansas City preventative patrol experiment: a technical report. Police Foundation, Washington, DC Lippmann W (1963) The young criminals. In: Rossiter C, Lare J (eds) The essential Lippmann. Random House, New York, Originally published 1933 Plea Bargaining Lum C, Merola L, Willis J, Cave B (2010) License plate recognition technology (LPR): impact evaluation and community assessment. Accessed from http://gemini. gmu.edu/cebcp/lpr_final.pdf Mazerolle L, Price J, Roehl J (2000) Civil remedies and drug control: a randomized trial in Oakland, California. Eval Rev 24(2):212–241 McCord J (2003) Cures that harm: unanticipated outcomes of crime prevention programs. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 587(1):16–30 Murray D (1998) Design and analysis of group randomized trials. Oxford University Press, New York Perry AE, Weisburd D, Hewitt C (2009) Are criminologists reporting experiments in ways that allow us to access them? Unpublished manuscript/report Raudenbush SW, Bryk AS (2002) Hierarchical linear models: applications and data analysis methods. Sage, Thousand Oaks Shadish WR, Clark MH, Steiner PM (2008) Can nonrandomized experiments yield accurate answers? A randomized experiment comparing random and nonrandom assignments. J Am Stat Assoc 103(484):1334–1356 Sherman LW, Weisburd DL (1995) General deterrent effects of police patrol in crime “hot spots”: a randomized, controlled trial. Justice Q 12(4): 625–648 Spybrook J, Raudenbush SW, Liu X, Congdon R (2006) Optimal design for longitudinal and multilevel research: documentation for the “Optimal Design” software. Accessed from http://rmcs.buu.ac.th/ statcenter/HLM.pdf Taljaard M, Weijer C, Grimshaw J, Bell Brown J, Binik A, Boruch R, Brejhaut J, Chaudry S, Eccles M, McRae A, Saginur R, Zwarenstein M, Donner A (2009) Cluster randomized trials: rational design of a mixed methods research study Warburton AL, Sheppard JP (2000) Effectiveness of toughened glass in terms of reducing injury in bars: a randomized controlled trial. Injury Prev 6:36–40 Weisburd D (2003) Ethical practice and evaluation of interventions in crime and justice: the moral imperative for randomized trials. Eval Rev 27(3): 336–354 Weisburd D (2005) Hot spots policing experiments and lessons from the field. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 599:220–245 Weisburd DL, Green L (1995) Policing drug hot spots: the Jersey City drug market analysis experiment. Justice Q 12(4):711–735 Weisburd D, Lum C, Petrosino A (2001) Does research design affect study outcomes? Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 578:50–70 Weisburd D, Wycoff L, Ready J, Eck JE, Hinkle JC, Gajewski F (2006) Does crime move around the corner? A controlled study of spatial displacement and diffusion of crime control benefits. Criminology 44(3):549–591 3535 P Plea Bargaining Ronald F. Wright Wake Forest University, Winston-Salem, NC, USA Synonyms Negotiated guilty pleas Overview As criminal justice systems increase in volume, they turn to negotiated guilty pleas as a primary method to dispose of cases. The prosecution offers reduced sentencing risk to defendants in exchange for more certain and inexpensive convictions. Although such negotiated outcomes are unpopular with the general public, the full-time practitioners who operate the system think of plea bargains as a necessary practice in busy courts. Negotiated guilty pleas have become by far the most common disposition of criminal charges in the United States, and similar practices are becoming more prevalent in other countries. Plea bargains create some uncertainty about the accuracy of convictions in the system and alter the balance of power among criminal justice actors by making judges and juries less influential by comparison to prosecutors. While external legal limits on plea bargains have mostly proven ineffectual, prosecutor offices routinely place internal administrative limits on the use of plea bargains. Introduction Criminal defendants in the United States usually decide to plead guilty. Very often, defendants negotiate with the prosecution to receive particular benefits as a precondition to entering a guilty plea – so often, in fact, that these so-called plea bargains have become more P P 3536 common and more important than criminal trials. In the United States, more than 9 out of every 10 felony convictions (and more than 99 out of every 100 misdemeanor convictions) derive from guilty pleas, and the overwhelming majority of guilty pleas occur after the parties negotiate the terms of that plea. Plea negotiations have been slower to arrive in other countries, but criminal court systems around the world often deal with increased volume by allowing some form of discounted sentence in return for a negotiated settlement. Plea bargains, in some form or another, are critical to the operation of high-volume criminal justice systems around the world today. The dominance of plea bargaining has predictable effects on the institutions of criminal justice in the United States. Most immediately, it makes criminal juries less influential. Negotiated pleas also shift power away from the trial judge toward the parties; they particularly strengthen the hand of the prosecutor. The prosecutor does not merely present legal and factual arguments to the judge on an equal footing with the defense attorney. Instead, the prosecutor hears arguments from the defense and then selects from the available charges and evidence thus substantially impacting the ultimate sentence. The judge, in effect, reviews these prosecutor decisions for possible error in exceptional cases. This shift of power in favor of prosecutors is more pronounced in “guideline sentencing” states that link the sentence more closely to the charge of conviction and to particular factual findings about the crime. Plea bargaining also affects outcomes in the criminal courts. For one thing, system volume goes up. A system that relies heavily on negotiated pleas can process more cases than a jurisdiction that resolves more of its cases through trials. Negotiated plea bargains also probably trade the quality of convictions for a higher quantity of cases. As systems get busier, the risk of erroneous convictions increases. External limits on the terms of negotiation between prosecution and defense are available in some systems but are still unusual and have shown only limited practical effects. Internal limits on bargaining practices imposed within Plea Bargaining the bureaucratic hierarchy of the prosecutor’s office are still the most common limits on individual sentencing discretion of a prosecuting attorney. This entry begins with a review of the most common topics for bargaining between the defense attorney and the prosecutor in criminal cases. It then discusses the prevalence and systemic effects of those party negotiations, both domestically and internationally. The entry closes with a review of the external and internal controls that legal systems use to structure prosecutorial discretion. Topics for Plea Negotiations During plea negotiations, the prosecution can offer the defendant two categories of benefits in exchange for a plea of guilty. First, under a “sentence bargain,” the prosecutor agrees to recommend to the judge a sentence below the maximum available, without amending the charges. A variation on this type of agreement involves a “fact bargain.” In this situation, the prosecution and defense agree to represent to the court that certain facts were either present or absent in a case. Under the sentencing rules of some jurisdictions, these facts trigger specific sentencing consequences. The second major category of negotiated plea aims for a “charge bargain.” In this situation, the prosecutor agrees to reduce the most serious charge to some lesser offense or to reduce the total number of counts in the indictment or information. The effect of amending the charges is to reduce the defendant’s potential exposure to more severe sentence outcomes. Sentence Bargains The parties develop detailed knowledge about the strength of the evidence, the expectations of the victims, the most likely outcomes of any legal issues presented, and the normal sentences imposed in similar cases. The judge, meanwhile, does not get involved in the details of the case as early as the parties and never becomes as familiar as the parties with the specifics of the crime and the offender’s background. When the court faces a crowded docket and the parties Plea Bargaining assure the judge that a given sentence is appropriate – particularly if that recommendation falls roughly into a normal range of sentences for this crime – the judge usually accepts the recommendation (Scott and Stuntz 1992). Sometimes the parties want a level of certainty about the sentencing outcome that is not possible based on sentencing recommendations alone. The criminal procedure rules in some jurisdictions allow the defendant to enter a plea of guilty conditioned on the judge’s acceptance of the agreed-upon sentence. In other words, the defendant may withdraw the plea of guilty if the court later rejects the specified sentence. Some scholars favor sentence bargains that give the judge something more than a “take it or leave it” option; more substantial input for the judge in the selection of the sentence leads, according to this view, to a more balanced sentencing system (Alschuler 1976; Wright and Miller 2002). Before accepting a plea of guilty, the trial court judge must be convinced that the defendant’s plea is “knowing and voluntary” and that the prosecution holds a sufficient “factual basis” to prove each element of the crime beyond a reasonable doubt. Other facts may be relevant to the sentence, as well, even if they are not elements of the offense. For instance, in the federal system, a defendant who plays a “minimal role” or “minor role” in a group offense receives a lower sentence. Given this opportunity to control the available sentence through the facts they plan to present, the parties naturally turn to negotiations about the proof of these non-element facts; they agree in some cases to tell the judge that the fact is present or absent from the case. The parties cannot lie to the judge and cannot compel the judge to make the factual finding that forms the basis for their agreement. But the prosecutor and defense attorney do exercise serious practical influence when they present a united front to the judge. This subtype of sentence bargaining is sometimes known as “fact bargaining.” It is especially pertinent in jurisdictions with sentencing guidelines or other statutes that attach specific sentencing consequences to particular facts. 3537 P For instance, some state codes authorize a 5-year increase in a sentence based on the use of a weapon during commission of the crime. The prosecution and defense might negotiate an agreement to stipulate to the judge that no weapon was used during the crime. The prosecutor sometimes goes beyond the role of advocate and plays a strong gatekeeper role for some non-element facts. In these special situations, the prosecutor does not merely request a factual finding from the judge; instead, the prosecutor herself exercises the power to increase or decrease a sentence automatically. For example, in the federal system (and in some states), the offender is eligible for a sentence discount after cooperating in the government’s investigation of further crimes only if the government certifies that the defendant provided “substantial assistance.” The government’s willingness to file such a motion is one of the important bargaining chips available to the prosecutor. Some states give the prosecutor a similar gatekeeper function over certain sentencing enhancement facts, such as the proximity of a narcotics sale to school grounds or the fact that a defendant’s prior record makes him or her a “habitual felon.” The defense attorney and prosecutor routinely bargain to determine whether the prosecutor will file the allegations that trigger such a sentencing enhancement. P Charge Bargains Criminal codes in both the federal and state systems give prosecutors a generous menu of options in the selection of charges. Many common fact scenarios could support criminal charges under multiple sections of the criminal code, each leading to different potential sentencing outcomes. After the initial filing of charges and the assignment of defense counsel to a case, the parties often negotiate over possible amendments to those charges. The defense attorney might request a dismissal of the most serious charge to be replaced by a less serious charge (a “vertical” charge bargain). Alternatively, the defense lawyer might ask for a dismissal of some charges in a multi-count indictment (a “horizontal” charge bargain). Both types of amendments reduce the P 3538 maximum sentence that a judge could legally impose on the defendant. Negotiations between the parties about revised charges take on even greater importance in the context of more highly structured sentencing systems. Sentencing laws that structure or reduce judicial discretion, including “mandatory minimum sentences” and “presumptive sentencing guidelines,” make the charge of conviction a more important predictor of the sentence. Once the defendant is found guilty of a particular crime, these highly structured sentencing laws give judges relatively few options for how to sentence the defendant (and perhaps no options at all). Because a structured sentencing environment makes visible the sentencing consequences of charging decisions, the parties can isolate the impact of a charge reduction and negotiate based on a more certain prediction of the outcome. Mandatory minimum sentencing laws offer a clear-cut example of the impact of charge bargains on sentencing outcomes. These laws create “cliff effects” that dramatically affect the potential sentence, depending on whether the parties agree to the mandatory sentence versus a similar crime with no mandatory penalty attached. Mandatory penalties could lead to wholesale increases in sentence severity in a jurisdiction. Empirical studies confirm, however, that prosecutors selectively mitigate the impact of specific mandatory sentencing laws by dismissing or reducing charges in some cases (Bjerk 2005). Presumptive sentencing guidelines tie sentencing options to the charge of conviction, much like mandatory minimum sentencing laws do. Systems that link the charge of conviction to a narrow range of sentence outcomes limit the options for the sentencing judge and empower the prosecutor, who controls both the filing of charges and the proof of the defendant’s conduct. Empirical studies have examined what prosecutors in guideline jurisdictions actually do about charge reductions. For the least serious cases, studies found only small shifts from sentence bargains to charge bargains. Apparently, busy prosecutors in high-volume systems do not change their customary negotiation practices across the board. Plea Bargaining Charge bargains increased more markedly, however, in more serious cases. In cases where conviction on the original charge would result in a presumed prison sentence and conviction on a lesser charge would allow probation or a shorter jail sentence, charge bargains happened more often after the arrival of sentencing guidelines in a jurisdiction. The amended rules gave the parties greater control over the sentencing outcomes in those cases, and they took advantage of that new power (Miethe 1987; Frase 2005). Research on the charging and plea bargaining practices of federal prosecutors under the federal sentencing guidelines also suggests that prosecutors frequently exercise their charge bargaining discretion to reduce sentences, particularly in drug and weapon possession cases (Bowman and Heise 2001). On the whole, the empirical evidence suggests that sentencing guideline systems make charge bargains somewhat more attractive than they are in discretionary sentencing regimes. There are also questions about the equal distribution of charge bargain benefits. The presence of legally relevant facts is the most important determinant of the charge of conviction (i.e., the charge that ultimately forms the basis for the conviction). Some nonlegal factors, however, also have some effect on the charge of conviction. Factors such as the race of the defendant appear to have a relatively small but persistent impact on the outcomes (Steffensmeier et al. 1998). Defense Concessions While the prosecutor can offer reduced sentences to the defendant, the defense attorney also holds certain bargaining chips during plea negotiations. Each of the defendant’s concessions involves the removal of procedural hurdles from the prosecutor’s path. The defendant’s power to make the government’s work easier begins with the investigation. If the defendant cooperates in an ongoing investigation, the government might be able to convict additional defendants. This form of assistance is especially important in the federal Plea Bargaining Plea Bargaining, Fig. 1 Percent of convictions obtained by guilty plea in federal court, 1950–2010 P 3539 Percent of Convictions Obtained by Guilty Plea in Federal Court, 1950-2010 100% 98% 96% 94% 92% 90% 88% 86% 84% 82% 80% 2010 2005 2000 1995 1990 1985 1980 1975 1970 1965 1960 1955 1950 system. The discounts available for “substantial assistance” lead to some difficult anomalies in the sentences among defendants who commit their crimes as part of a group, with the largest discounts awarded to the most blameworthy (and knowledgeable) organizers of the criminal enterprise (Maxfield and Kramer 1998). Another procedural hurdle that the defendant can remove for the prosecution is discovery and disclosure. The prosecution has a constitutional duty to disclose all material exculpatory information in its possession and a duty under state statutes or procedural rules to respond to any discovery requests for certain types of inculpatory evidence. The defendant, however, can remove most of those obligations from the prosecution by pleading guilty. The most valuable concessions that defendants make in plea negotiations are waivers of pretrial hearings and the trial itself. These waivers might extend to all the procedural rights at trial, including the right to a jury, confrontation of adverse witnesses, counsel, and so forth. In some jurisdictions, defendants can obtain some benefits by offering to waive the jury trial in favor of a bench trial (Schulhofer 1984). The defendant can also offer the government certainty and finality of outcomes by waiving the right to appeal or to file post-conviction collateral attacks on the conviction. Most state and federal courts have concluded that a defendant may explicitly waive the right to appeal a conviction as part of a plea agreement. One empirical study of federal cases found that nearly two-thirds of the cases settled by plea agreement included a waiver of appeal rights and three-quarters of the defendants who waived appeal also waived collateral review (King and O’Neill 2005). Prevalence of Plea Negotiations The concessions that the prosecutor and the defense attorney offer each other during plea negotiations have become the norm in criminal justice: plea agreements account for the great majority of convictions in every jurisdiction in the USA. The proportion of negotiated pleas changes over time and across different systems. Negotiated outcomes were not at all common in the mid-nineteenth century in state systems (Fisher 2003). In the federal system, less than 8 % of convictions were obtained through guilty pleas in the early 1970s; that number rose inexorably through the decades to reach the current level, above 97 % (Wright 2005). See Fig. 1. A high volume of cases within a court system – both the civil and criminal dockets – creates the conditions for plea bargaining to thrive (Bibas 2012). Courts that resort to plea bargaining, in turn, increase their caseloads even further. Routine practices and expectations also play a role in sustaining the institution of plea bargaining: some courts with relatively uncrowded dockets still depend almost entirely on negotiated pleas. The United States is unusual in an international context in its heavy reliance on P P 3540 party negotiations to resolve criminal proceedings and the tight connection it promotes between plea negotiations and sentencing outcomes. For example, only a generation ago, Germany was known as the “land without plea bargaining” (Langbein 1979). Over time, however, many European nations have faced a higher volume of criminal cases; crowded court dockets have led to various innovations that allow the prosecutor to designate some cases for summary treatment. In some countries, party negotiations to achieve these more streamlined criminal adjudications have become more common. Parties not only negotiate guilty pleas but also dismissals and diversion into alternative punishment or restitution programs (Jehle and Wade 2006; Luna and Wade 2010). In the past, these negotiated summary dispositions were restricted to less serious cases, but that limitation is disappearing over time (Langer 2004). Plea bargaining is somewhat more prevalent in Israel, Canada, Australia, England, and Wales than in European Continental countries. Negotiation Effects It is difficult to say whether plea bargains reduce the typical sentence imposed on a defendant over the long run. On the one hand, defendants who plead guilty to a crime receive a definite “discount” for waiving trial rights, when compared to defendants facing the same charges during the same time period. On the other hand, as the courts rely more heavily on plea bargains and prosecutors file more charges, the legislature tends to pass new criminal laws that increase the risk for defendants who refuse to plead guilty. That is, the new laws authorize higher sentences that defendants potentially face if they insist on a trial and lose. Over the long run, reliance on plea bargains does not correlate with reduced sentences (Pfaff 2011). Other potential effects of plea bargains go beyond the sentences imposed, raising issues about the accuracy of system outcomes and the influence of different system actors. Plea Bargaining Questions About Accuracy Established constitutional doctrine declares that the courts may not punish a criminal defendant simply for exercising the constitutional right to a trial. Daily practice in every American criminal court, however, contradicts this doctrine. It is clear that defendants routinely receive more severe sentences after trial than they would receive if they were to plead guilty (Brereton and Casper 1981). Judges resolve this apparent conflict between constitutional doctrine and daily reality by declaring that they reduce sentences in guilty plea cases based on the defendant’s cooperative attitude and prospects for rehabilitation, and not based simply on the fact that the defendant waived trial rights. The exact size of the “trial penalty” – or to put it more politely, the “guilty plea discount” – is difficult to measure. Studies of the trial penalty that attempt to control for the seriousness of the offense and other variables find a substantial gap between posttrial sentences and post-plea sentences. One study found a wide range of differences – between 13 % and 461 % – depending on the crime and the jurisdiction involved (King et al. 2005). When defendants face such a large trial penalty, concerns start to mount that some defendants with valid defenses nevertheless plead guilty. Although there is a reasonable prospect that such defendants would be acquitted at trial, they dare not risk the large increase in the sentence that happens after a conviction at trial (Wright 2005). Behavioral economics offers some reasons to believe that defendants will undervalue the long-term impact of a felony conviction, leading defendants to accept a guilty plea too easily (Bibas 2004). On the other hand, there is evidence that some innocent defendants resist highly attractive plea offers, even when it might be rational to accept the offer in light of the risk of a wrongful conviction (Gazal-Ayal and Tor 2012). The risk of coercing innocent defendants into pleading guilty is built into some basic structural features of American criminal justice. Criminal codes that offer more bargaining options to the Plea Bargaining prosecutor make it possible to increase the trial penalty and to pressure some defendants into waiving potentially effective defenses. The same holds true for increased sentence severity. When the law authorizes higher maximum sentences for a wide range of offenses and retains low potential sentences for lesser-included offenses, defendants face an enormous range of risk. Particularly in those states with sentencing guidelines or other limits on judicial sentencing discretion, the defendant can control some of that risk through a charge bargain. It would be an overstatement to claim that sentencing guidelines lead directly to more inaccurate convictions. They can, however, contribute to a coercive environment for defendants. Finally, the structure of criminal justice institutions increases the risk of coercive and inaccurate guilty pleas. The public does not invest in enough judges, courtrooms, prosecutors, and public defenders to try a substantial proportion of the cases filed each year. The “working group” dynamic that develops in most courtrooms places the highest value on agreements that will move cases more quickly through the system (Nardulli et al. 1985). 3541 P from judges to prosecutors since judges might find other methods to influence sentences (Engen 2008). At the very least, fears that prosecutors would entirely usurp the judge’s sentencing authority in presumptive guideline jurisdictions appear to have been overstated. For one thing, judges in an indeterminate sentencing system do not, in reality, control the sentence that an offender actually serves. The judge announces one sentence, but parole authorities could later reduce that sentence. Since the judge in an indeterminate system never held actual power over the sentence to be served, guidelines do not take that power away from the judge. It is also true that presumptive sentencing guidelines leave important zones of discretion available to judges in the selection of sentences. Limits on Prosecutorial Discretion Legal institutions place some controls on the negotiation of guilty pleas. Those constraints originate both from outside the office of the prosecutor and from the internal workings of a local prosecutor’s office. External Constraints Balance of Power Among Sentencing Actors Sentencing guidelines and other structured sentencing laws that began to proliferate in the 1970s were designed to regulate judicial discretion in sentencing. As a result, some critics of these laws expressed concern that the reforms would transfer power from judges to prosecutors. Compared to traditional indeterminate sentencing schemes, the more structured systems would concentrate sentence authority in one branch rather than allowing one institution to check and balance the other (Alschuler 1991). The transfer of power hypothesis finds some tentative empirical support. For instance, studies of guideline systems confirm that charge bargains become more common for at least some crimes, and charge reductions determine an important component of the sentence actually served (Frase 2005). But this shift in charging practices may not result in a provable transfer of authority If the legislature defines crimes narrowly and sets penalties at modest levels, it reduces the risks of inaccurate convictions and increases the power of different sentencing actors to check each another. This approach to crime legislation, however, does not thrive in the American political climate. Voters expect prosecutors to take the lead in addressing crime, and they expect legislators to give them the legal tools to do the job. Legislators respond with broadly worded criminal laws and multiple statutes (each with a different corresponding punishment) that could apply to a single common factual scenario. Although legislators do not seriously constrain prosecutors through the terms of the substantive criminal law, statutes in a few jurisdictions do limit the timing of plea negotiations or limit the size of the charge reduction that a prosecutor can offer to dispose of a case (at least for some high priority categories of crime). While these P P 3542 legislative directives can be meaningful, their current impact is small. Statutory limits on the timing of negotiations simply push plea bargains into earlier phases of the proceedings. Judges also refuse, for the most part, to monitor and control the negotiation of guilty pleas. Granted, judges hold the power to accept or reject guilty pleas, along with the plea agreements that the parties present to them. These judicial powers, however, operate within a system of mass justice. The caseload would become overwhelming if judges balked regularly at proposals to remove a case from the trial docket, or even took the time regularly to investigate this possibility. The law in some jurisdictions also limits the role of the judge during plea negotiations. Statutes, rules of criminal procedure, rules of judicial ethics, and judicial opinions in more than half of the states instruct the judge not to “participate” at all in the plea discussions. The judge’s only role is to evaluate the legitimacy of the guilty plea after the parties finalize their agreement. A smaller number of states discourage judges from participating in plea negotiations, but they do not ban the practice outright. The laws in these states allow the judge to comment on the acceptability of charges and sentences that the parties themselves propose or to participate in the negotiations only upon the invitation of both parties. The rules of professional responsibility as enforced by state licensing authorities are also a potential source of limits on the plea bargaining behavior of prosecutors. For instance, a prosecutor who withholds discoverable information from the defense during plea negotiations might violate the specialized ethical obligations of prosecuting attorneys. Again, however, we get limited accountability from these regulators. State bar authorities rarely discipline prosecutors, and the penalties are usually not severe (Zacharias 2001). Although institutions external to the prosecutor’s office do not exert much power over the discretion of line prosecutors, the chief prosecutor is directly accountable to the voters. Prosecutors in the United States are normally Plea Bargaining elected. Given the distaste among voters for the practice of plea bargaining, elections in theory should limit the prosecutor’s ability to reduce charges or to recommend lower sentences as part of a plea negotiation. In practice, however, the influence of voters over the plea bargaining policies of the prosecutor’s office is limited. The heavy advantage of incumbents in prosecutorial elections makes this a weak accountability mechanism (Wright 2009). Internal Constraints While legal institutions outside the prosecutor’s office do not fully meet the need for checks and balances, internal regulation has a substantial constraining effect. Forces within the prosecutor’s office can produce plea policies that remain true to declared sources of law, in keeping with current public priorities in the enforcement of that law, applied with reasonable consistency across cases (Bibas 2012; Miller and Wright 2008). These internal regulations take several forms. First, the managers in a prosecutor’s office sometimes arrange the flow of cases to encourage line attorneys to interact dispose of cases through plea negotiations. This might involve the use of “horizontal” prosecution for some crimes, with different attorneys or units in the office making decisions as a file moves up through the system. It is also common, particularly in larger offices, to require supervisor approval for any plea agreement that dismisses a charge in priority cases, such as homicide and domestic violence. Second, chief prosecutors can promote consistency and fidelity to public values among their line attorneys by creating written guidelines for the disposition of cases (Podgor 2012). The United States Attorney’s Manual is one such resource. The guidelines typically declare that they do not carry the force of law and are not enforceable in judicial proceedings, but they nevertheless exert some control over the behavior of prosecutors (Abrams 1971). Through the use of such guidelines, prosecutors have from time to time banned the use of plea bargains for certain classes of Plea Bargaining cases, although such guidelines require serious monitoring and enforcement to remain effective. While there is much promise in the power of chief prosecutors to hold their line prosecutors accountable, the system also depends on professional tradition, informal office culture, peer pressure, and individual conscience to achieve just results. At the end of the day, each prosecutor must remain individually committed to the ideal of responsible prosecution. Policy Challenges The most significant checks on the use of plea bargains come from inside prosecutors’ offices. Prosecutors in the United States are profoundly decentralized: the state courts operate over 2000 separate prosecutors’ offices, with no effective hierarchical control over the local offices in most states. As a result, the internal controls on plea bargains are often nontransparent and inconsistent from place to place. Policy makers who hope to promote enforcement of the criminal law that is consistent with legal values and with current popular priorities must find ways to make these local internal policies and practices more visible and subject to evaluation by the public and by other legal actors. A balance of power, in a transparent environment, would lead to the most responsible use of negotiated guilty pleas. Related Entries ▶ Prosecution and Wrongful Convictions ▶ Prosecutorial Discretion Recommended Reading and References Abrams N (1971) Internal policy: guiding the exercise of prosecutorial discretion. UCLA Law Rev 19:1–58 Alschuler AW (1976) The trial judge’s role in plea bargaining (pt. 1). Columbia Law Rev 76:1059–1154 Alschuler AW (1991) The failure of sentencing guidelines: a plea for less aggregation. Univ Chic Law Rev 58:901–951 Bibas S (2004) Plea bargaining outside the shadow of trial. Harv Law Rev 117:2463–2547 3543 P Bibas S (2012) The machinery of criminal justice. Oxford University Press, New York Bjerk D (2005) Making the crime fit the penalty: the role of prosecutorial discretion under mandatory minimum sentencing. J Law Econ 48:591–625 Bowman FO, Heise M (2001) Quiet rebellion? Explaining nearly a decade of declining federal drug sentences. Iowa Law Rev 86:1043 Brereton D, Casper J (1981) Does it pay to plead guilty? Differential sentencing and the functioning of criminal courts. Law Soc Rev 16:45–70 Engen RL (2008) Have sentencing reforms displaced discretion over sentencing from judges to prosecutors? In: Worral JL, Nugent-Borakove ME (eds) The changing role of the American prosecutor. State University of New York Press, Albany Fisher G (2003) Plea bargaining’s triumph: a history of plea bargaining in America. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto Frase RS (2005) Sentencing guidelines in Minnesota, 1978–2003. Crime Justice: A Rev Res 32:131–219 Gazal-Ayal O, Tor A (2012) The innocence effect. Duke Law J 62:339–401 Jehle JM, Wade M (2006) Coping with overloaded criminal justice systems: the rise of prosecutorial power across Europe. Springer, Berlin King NJ, O’Neill M (2005) Appeal waivers and the future of sentencing policy. Duke Law J 55:209–261 King NJ, Soule DA, Steen S, Weidner RR (2005) When process affects punishment: differences in sentences after guilty plea, bench trial, and jury trial in five guidelines states. Columbia Law Rev 105:959–1009 Langbein JH (1979) Land without plea bargaining: how the Germans do it. Mich Law Rev 78:204–225 Langer M (2004) From legal transplants to legal translations: the globalization of plea bargaining and the Americanization thesis in criminal procedure. Harvard Int Law J 45:1–64 Luna E, Wade M (2010) Prosecutors as judges. Washington Lee Law Rev 67:1413–1532 Maxfield LD, Kramer JH (1998) Substantial assistance: an empirical yardstick gauging equity in current federal policy and practice. United States Sentencing Commission, Washington, DC Miethe TD (1987) Charging and plea bargaining practices under determinate sentencing: an investigation of the hydraulic displacement of discretion. J Crim Law Criminol 78:155–176 Miller ML, Wright RF (2008) The black box. Iowa Law Rev 94:125–196 Nardulli PF, Flemming RB, Eisenstein J (1985) Criminal courts and bureaucratic justice: concessions and consensus in the guilty plea process. J Crim Law Criminol 76:1103–1131 Pfaff JF (2011) The myths and realities of correctional severity: evidence from the National Corrections Reporting Program. Am Law Econ Rev 13:491–531 P P 3544 Podgor ES (2012) Prosecution guidelines in the United States. In: Luna E, Wade M (eds) The prosecutor in transnational perspective. Oxford University Press, New York Schulhofer SJ (1984) Is plea bargaining inevitable? Harv Law Rev 97:1037–1107 Scott RE, Stuntz WJ (1992) Plea bargaining as contract. Yale Law J 101:1909–1968 Steffensmeier D, Ulmer JT, Kramer JH (1998) The interaction of race, gender, and age in criminal sentencing: the punishment cost of being young, black and male. Criminology 36:763–798 Wright RF (2005) Trial distortion and the end of innocence in federal criminal justice. Univ PA Law Rev 154:79–156 Wright RF (2009) How prosecutor elections fail us. Ohio State J Crim Law 6:581–610 Wright RF, Miller ML (2002) The screening/bargaining tradeoff. Stanford Law Rev 55:29–118 Zacharias FC (2001) The professional discipline of prosecutors. North Carol Law Rev 79:725–743 Plural Policing ▶ Family Engagement Strategies to Reduce Crime ▶ Legal Frameworks for Third-Party Policing Poaching ▶ Crimes Against Animal Life Police ▶ Privatization of Policing in an International Context ▶ Police and the Excessive Use of Force Police Accountability ▶ Control of Police Misconduct Plural Policing Police and the Excessive Use of Force Robert J. Kane Program in Criminal Justice, Drexel University, Philadelphia, PA, USA Synonyms Brutality; Coercion; Force; Police Overview The excessive use of force by police is often a difficult phenomenon to identify, as well as a difficult concept to define. Unlike corruption that is motivated by profit – which is generally impermissible by its very nature – excessive use of force often resides at the marginal end of the acceptable use of force continuum. That is, because society authorizes the police to use physical coercion to carry out their mandate, it is often unclear when, along the use of force continuum, the acceptable use of force becomes excessive. Perhaps this is why excessive force, or brutality, often seems to occur unchecked in communities that are unable to advocate for themselves, making it difficult to hold police officers accountable for the use of unauthorized violence. Several classic police scholars have developed occupational templates to help describe the circumstances under which some police officers engage in brutality. These perspectives try to account for police-suspect interactions, the police working environment, and dangers therein; while others locate the causes in the personalities of the officers, or the agencies in which they work. By understanding some of the causes of police brutality, society and policy-makers have a better chance of developing prevention strategies that can minimize the use of excessive force, particularly in the most vulnerable communities. Currently, these prevention strategies are rooted in the areas of recruitment and training, as well as the proper supervision of officers in the field. Police and the Excessive Use of Force Introduction When two officers of the Los Angeles Police Department were shown on tape beating the motorist Rodney King with batons – after their field supervisor had already exposed King, with little effect, to the Taser, a conductive energy device designed to “stun” suspects into submission – even while he was rolling on the ground and seemingly defenseless – few observers were left with any doubt that they had just witnessed an example of police brutality. Some experts (e.g., Skolnick and Fyfe 1993; Toch 1996), however, who viewed the entire tape – as opposed to simply its last 7 s – saw a more nuanced escalation of force that ultimately became excessive. Rodney King had broken a primary subcultural rule in policing: When initially contacted by the team of California Highway Patrol officers who attempted to stop his vehicle for speeding on Interstate 210 in the San Fernando Valley area of Los Angeles, he failed to pull over for them. Indeed, King would later report that he fled from the CHP cruiser because he was driving while intoxicated and feared that an arrest would violate the provisions of his parole (the result of an earlier robbery conviction) (Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). For his failure to submit to police authority in ways that satisfied the five LAPD officers at the scene, King was “Tazed” once, struck with police batons 56 times (several of which were blows to the head), and kicked six times by officers (Independent Commission 1991). To date, the beating of Rodney King represents the archetype of police brutality, and it encapsulates multiple conceptual perspectives – from the levels of the social interactionist, workgroup, and cultural – aimed at explaining why some police officers resort to excessive force during their encounters with members of the public. Excessive use of force by police is a tricky phenomenon to identify and explain. Even in the most “obvious” and infamous examples of police brutality, it is frequently the case that at some point during the violent encounter, some force on the part of police was justified – perhaps even necessary – to preserve officer and/or public 3545 P safety. As such, excessive force by police is substantively distinct from other forms of misconduct, such as profit-motivated corruption because, while the later is usually wrong on its very face (e.g., police officers are not permitted to extort money from drug dealers or motorists; and they are not permitted to steal jewelry off corpses they encounter during health-and-welfare checks), they are allowed, and in many cases even expected, to use coercive force as part of their role in society. In fact, it as a virtual axiom in policing that the use of force is a “tool,” whose use should be regulated but not taken away. Several leading scholars have developed frameworks to explain why the excessive use of force occurs and how it may foster in some police departments. Van Maanen (1978) identifies the “asshole” as one lens through which to view the use of force encounter. He argues that when a suspect commits an “affront” to a police officer’s authority, the officer – under certain circumstances – may respond with violence as a way of (re)establishing control over the police-suspect event. Muir (1977) takes a more individualistic approach, observing that some police officers have an “enforcer”-type personality borne out of their inabilities to (1) empathize with people whom they contact under the worst of circumstances, and (2) communicate in ways that may de-escalate potentially violent encounters. Skolnick and Fyfe (1993) view the excessive use of force from an organizational-level, noting that certain police departments develop and foster a so-called “siege mentality” in which officers are made to feel outnumbered, outgunned, and unwelcome in the communities they serve. Indeed, the siege mentality – which stems from the top levels of police department administration – views officers as a collective occupying force deployed in dangerous communities inhabited by dangerous people. As a result, officers in such locations are often made to believe that the only way for them to maintain order is through the use of highly aggressive enforcement strategies that may translate into excessive force. This entry examines the use of excessive force by police through the perspectives offered above P P 3546 while also noting the difficulty and complexities involved in defining police brutality. As alluded to above, identifying excessive force is made allthe-more difficult by virtue of the use of physical coercion that is a large part of how the police fulfill their mandate in society. In addition to discussing these conceptual issues, the entry also describes how legal mechanisms, such as judicial review and the US Code, have made the excessive use of force difficult to prove at an acceptable legal standard, which may inadvertently stifle efforts to redress abusive police practices and reform police departments in need of reforming. The entry closes with a discussion of how to prevent and control the excessive use of force. The Excessive Use of Force Prism Before trying to define the excessive use of force by police, the reader might first start with a more fundamental question: Why do we have the police in our society? It is common knowledge that at times, some police officers use more force than is necessary on suspects they encounter; some engage in profit-motivated misconduct and then lie on the witness stand to protect their corrupt enterprises; and these practices often take place in the most socially and economically vulnerable communities (Kane 2002). So, again, while most people understand that some police officers, as well as some departments, have the propensity to engage in brutality, the question is again begged: Why have the police in the first place? American citizens enjoy – perhaps more than those of other developed nations – almost unfettered access to their court system. They have the ability to report crimes directly to their local District Attorney’s Offices, and they have the right to request protective orders and other forms of injunctive relief directly from magistrates in open court. In short, American citizens under the best of circumstances have the ability to mobilize government on their behalf in ways that could theoretically bypass the police entirely, and yet, most Americans – even those who have had bad experiences with them – would scarcely Police and the Excessive Use of Force advocate dissolving the police as a public institution. Why? As cited by Klockars (1985), we maintain a collective police force because of what Egon Bittner wrote in 1970: “something-ought-not-to-be-happening-aboutwhich-something-ought-to-be-done. . .NOW!!” That is, although it is possible to mobilize the government without using the police, it is often not feasible to do so. In highlighting this reality, Klockars (1985) notes that if a crazy resident goes into the yard of his neighbor to chop down a prized apple tree with an axe, seeking an injunction against such an intrusion likely will not prevent the destruction of the apple tree. In such events, therefore, the point of the police is to stop – or at the very least – freeze a moment in time in order for the courts to gain the opportunity to properly adjudicate the case. The police accomplish this mandate by exercising their “general right to use coercive force” (Klockars 1985) – a right bestowed upon them by the American public through the Executive Branch of government. And it is this general right to use coercive force that makes possible both the best and worst practices of policing. At their best, the police use their coercive authority to improve the life chances of people they contact – often under the most abject social and economic conditions imaginable. At their worst, police use their coercive authority in ways that abuse, denigrate, and otherwise “tread on the human dignity” (Carter 1985, p. 322) of people they encounter. Although the American public grants police the general right to employ coercive force, it does so with few guidelines as to the boundaries of its proper use, making it difficult for evaluators of police behaviors to determine – for example – when appropriate force may have become excessive, or when excessive force was used when no force was necessary. The following serve as instructive examples: • Incident 1: Two police officers on foot see a man on a public sidewalk who matches the description of a robbery suspect. They attempt to contact the man, but as they summon him their way, the man turns and runs. Both officers engage the suspect in chase. The man Police and the Excessive Use of Force leads them on a 5-min foot pursuit through alleys, over fences, and across a vacant lot until they finally catch him in an open field. At the point of contact, the man physically resists the officers’ efforts to subdue and handcuff him. He swings and kicks at them, making glancing contact, until one of the officers makes two baton strikes to the man’s body, sending the suspect hard to the ground. One of the officers is bleeding slightly from a scratch on his face, the other suffered a hyperextended knee. As the suspect writhes on the ground from the pain of the baton strikes, one of the officers kneels to handcuff him, while the other officer kicks the man twice in the ribs. Even after the suspect is securely cuffed and clearly incapacitated, the other officer punches him with a closed fist in the kidney two times just after the other officer pulled him from the ground. • Incident 2: A police officer working traffic duty sits in his marked cruiser at mid-day. The car is parked in a somewhat concealed position relative to the corner of an intersection governed by a four-way stop. When he observes a pickup truck roll confidently through the intersection without stopping, the officer ignites his engine, activates the light bar, and pulls quickly away from the curb to initiate a vehicle stop on the truck. After a few hundred yards, and two siren “chirps,” the driver of the pickup truck finally pulls to the curb. The officer exits his vehicle, walks to the truck, and instructs the driver to put down his window. The officer observes that the driver and his one passenger are teenage boys, most likely between the ages of 16 and 18 years. The officer waits with expectancy while the driver – who is wearing a smirk on his face – finally begins to slowly roll down his window. The officer, losing patience, asks for the driver’s operating license. After a pause, the driver says, “Why do you need that? I am just taking my buddy home.” The officer again requests the young man’s license, and although the driver complies, he does so slowly. Suddenly, the officer reaches in through the window, grabs the young man by 3547 P the hair, and swiftly pulls him through the window and out onto the street. The officer then drags the young man – still by the hair – around the front of the truck to the sidewalk, where he slams the young man’s head against the hood of the truck. The young man screams in surprise and pain, while the officer repeats the motion of bashing his head against the hood. The officer then drags the young man back around the front of the truck, opens the driver’s side door, and roughly deposits the young man back into the truck, slamming the door closed. The officer then advises, “The next time a police officer asks for your driver’s license, I suggest you give it to him the first time.” Then officer then turns, walks back to his patrol car, enters, and drives away. The above scenarios indicate two types of situations during which excessive force may be used by police, and both have their own definitional difficulties associated with them. In the case of incident #1, it is clear that the two officers involved in the foot chase were justified – even compelled – to use force in the apprehension and control of the suspect. The suspect, in fact, used physical force to prevent his apprehension, swinging, kicking, and striking the officers as they attempted to subdue him. The officers were probably justified in the use of their batons while the suspect was fighting them, but what about the subsequent kicks and blows once the suspect was handcuffed and effectively restrained? At what point did the appropriate use of force by the police become excessive? Different people – e.g., police officers, police administrators, community residents, and promoters of law and order – may have different answers to this question. For some, the baton strikes may have been regarded as excessive, considering there were two officers and the suspect was not at all armed with a weapon. To others, the kicks and punches delivered by officers at the conclusion of the encounter were not excessive, but rather “just desserts” visited upon a “victim” who should have cooperated with the police in the first place. The events described in incident #2 suggest perhaps a less ambiguous evaluation of the use of excessive force. Although the driver of the P P 3548 pickup truck was not physically combative with the officer who stopped him, he was defiant, and he failed to comply with the lawful order of police officer, namely, to produce his operator’s license. In doing so, the driver of the pickup truck left the officer with two categories of choice: (1) make a tactical retreat, perhaps to his vehicle where he could have radioed for a supervisor to join him at the scene in an effort to avoid the use of force; and (2) increase the dosage of coercion in order to secure the driver’s compliance. From the description of events in incident #2, the officer clearly chose the latter by using physical coercion to neutralize the young man’s defiance. And again, commentators of police behaviors may disagree as to the appropriateness of the officer’s actions. Some would conclude that the force used by the officer was unnecessary, excessive, and perhaps even illegal; others may conclude that the officer rightly punished a smart-aleck kid who needed to be taught to respect authority. Despite potential differences in assessments of the excessive use of force across incidents 1 and 2, the hypothetical events share a common link: From the perspective of responding officers, both victims may have “deserved” it. That is, in both cases described above, an argument can be made that both suspects-turned-victim forced a confrontation with the police, which led to the excessive force. This is another feature of many use of force incidents that makes identifying brutality or excessive use of force difficult. As Walker (2010) has argued in his criticism of drug-war policing, when police officers use excessive force during their encounters with the public, they usually do so on socially marginalized and/or otherwise “undesirable” suspects, often rendering it unlikely that the victim of brutality can successfully hold officers accountable for their actions. Thus, despite the procedural and legal constraints (discussed in the following section) placed on officers’ authority on the use of physical coercion, the sociology of use of force encounters often challenges society’s definition of the excessive use of force, particularly when the force may have been used on someone who at least initially defied the police. Police and the Excessive Use of Force The following section discusses several of the legal issues associated with defining the excessive use of force, which adds further difficulty of successfully defining excessive force and brutality. Excessive Force Through Legal and Social Lenses Moving more thoroughly into an evaluation of the excessive use of force by police requires some definitional clarity. In general, police use of force can be categorized into four types: (1) appropriate, (2) deadly, (3) excessive, and (4) unnecessary. Once these types of force are defined, the entry focuses on excessive force, also commonly referred to as police brutality (e.g., Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). The appropriate use of force occurs when police officers use physical coercion that is proportional to a suspect’s resistance to gain compliance and/or diffuse a violent or potentially violent encounter. Though perhaps commonly believed, police officers are not required to match a suspect’s resistance incrementally with force that follows a use of force continuum (Graham v. Connor 1989). Rather, police officers are legally (and usually administratively) permitted to “skip” steps on the use of force continuum in order to overwhelm a suspect – within reason – to achieve custody. Society and the courts do not require police officers to engage in fist fights with suspects in order to gain compliance. Indeed, most police officers are trained to control many suspects – whether armed or not – from a safe distance, often via the threat or use of chemical spray, a conductive energy device (e.g., Taser), or a firearm. To provide a framework for assessing the appropriateness of the use of force, the Supreme Court applied an “objective reasonableness” standard (via the Search and Seizure Clause of the Fourth Amendment) in the case Graham v. Connor (1989), holding that the legality of the use of force must be evaluated based on the judgment of a “reasonable” officer at the scene of the event rather than through a “retrospective” lens. The Court reasoned that when police Police and the Excessive Use of Force officers become involved in violent or potentially violent encounters, they frequently have just seconds to decide how to apply coercion, often in self-defense and/or in the defense of others. As such, the fairest assessment of the legality (and administrative permissibility) of the application of force must be made from the perspective of someone at the incident who would have had to make a force decision in the heat of the moment – just as the actual officer did. Deadly force – i.e., “force that kills or is likely to kill” (Fyfe 1979) – and which is usually, but not always, the result of a firearm discharge – is governed largely by the same objective reasonableness standard as nonlethal force (the standard appears to change to a test of “deliberate indifference,” as governed largely by the Eighth Amendment, if deadly force is used on a suspect while in a custody facility), though with an extra restriction. In the case Tennessee v. Garner (1985), the Supreme Court abolished the common law custom that had historically allowed police officers to use deadly force against fleeing suspects who posed no threat to life. In abolishing this practice – which was known as the “fleeing felon rule” – the Court reasoned that using deadly force to apprehend a person suspected of having committed a felony, but who seemed to pose no imminent threat to life – constituted an unreasonable seizure of the person under the Fourth Amendment. Despite this landmark decision that made the “defense of life” standard the law of the land, the Court in Garner failed to outline circumstances under which deadly force was permissible. Thus, Garner allows officers to determine the meaning of “life” threatening: The risk to life need not be real at the time of the incident; it must be apparent. Among all the dimensions of the use of force construct, “unnecessary” force is perhaps the most difficult to assess and the most controversial to condemn. Unnecessary force usually represents the proper use of force at the immediate moment of application, but which could have been avoided had officers not allowed, or caused, the incident to escalate (Fyfe 1986). Thus, rather than representing the product of malice or the inclination to “punish,” unnecessary force 3549 P generally results from police officer’s professional incompetence. A typical example of this occurs when police respond to a man with a gun call. They might arrive on the scene to find an agitated man pacing in his front yard with a pistol in hand. Because officers neglected to find cover and concealment (i.e., failing to position themselves behind parked cars or out of direct line of fire), they shoot the man when he makes a furtive movement. When focusing on the last point in the encounter – i.e., the instance immediately preceding the shooting – the force used may be justifiable since the police were compelled to protect their lives and perhaps the lives of bystanders. When considering, however, the events that led to the shooting, professional incompetence left the officers at risk of being shot in the first place. Had they found proper cover, they might have been able to wait and persuade the man to drop the gun, which would have averted the use of violence. Although the examination of unnecessary force is largely beyond the scope of this entry, it is important to at least identify because (1) it represents a component of the overall use of force construct, and (2) likely happens more frequently than does excessive force, often without the subsequent application of accountability remedies (Fyfe 1986). As the above discussion should suggest, police brutality is physical force that breaches the confines of legally permissible physical coercion. Because police brutality is often committed out of malice, disrespect, and/or officers’ desires to reassert their authority over a suspect (e.g., Skolnick and Fyfe 1993), several academic researchers often regard excessive force as an example of police abuse of authority (e.g., Carter 1985) rather than a mere “excess” of force. This is because police brutality often stems from the same theoretical processes that lead to verbal chastising and psychological abuse during police interrogations (e.g., Carter 1985) – both of which are abusive but not physical. Although most state criminal codes in the United States include statutes that specifically make police brutality under “color” of state authority illegal, the most common legal remedy for parties attempting to redress the alleged P P 3550 excessive use of force by police is Title 42, Section 1983 of the US Code. This is the Federal civil rights statute that allows persons alleging harm by police (and any representative of the State who may have acted under color of authority) to seek damages from both the individual officer(s) and the government agency that employed them. The reason why Section 1983 is likely the most common legal mechanism invoked in excessive use of force claims is because the statute relaxes the usual requirement placed on plaintiffs that they exhaust all lower administrative and legal outlets before filing a claim in Federal court. Although the statute does not require proof that a police officer intended to harm the victim (that is, the plaintiff need not prove an officer’s psychological state of mind), it does require the plaintiff to successfully demonstrate that the government entity (e.g., municipal police department) that employed the officer maintained official policies and directives that directly resulted in the harm caused, or that the entity had established informal customs and practices that led to the harm. For this reason, Section 1983 lawsuits are often colloquially referred to as “patterns and practices” suits and generally allege that the brutality (or other problematic behaviors) occurred because the police agency failed to train and/or supervise the officers properly and/or negligently retained the officers as employees. Thus, integrating the Section 1983 statute with Supreme Court decisions results in plaintiffs gaining ready access to Federal court for the purposes of attempting to hold police officers and the agencies/governments that employed them accountable for brutality, though trial courts must adhere to Graham’s “objective reasonableness” requirement of evaluating the use of force from the standpoint of a reasonable officer at the scene. The net effect has been that, while it is relatively easy to sue police officers and police departments, it is highly difficult to win such cases due to the “reasonable officer at the scene” requirement (Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). Moreover, as research has shown, even when plaintiffs are generally successful in proving police brutality at an acceptable legal threshold, Police and the Excessive Use of Force juries historically have been reluctant to decide against police officers due to generalized public support for the police, and the fact than many plaintiffs who allege brutality occupy dubious social positions relative to the officers they are accusing. Perhaps the best example in modern history was the Rodney King case in which all officers accused of brutality were found not guilty in the first trial. Classic Templates to Explain Excessive Use of Force As noted in the opening pages of this entry, police brutality – or excessive use of force – occurs for myriad reasons across multiple levels of analysis: the psychological, sociological, social contextual, and organizational. Since William Westley (1970) published his classic ethnography of police in Indiana (which was actually published 20 years after his dissertation work that produced the findings) in which he described for the first time the importance officers and police organizations placed on making felony arrests, several researchers have replicated Westley’s methodology in an effort to highlight several aspects of the police occupation that previously had been generally unknown. The result was the publication of classic statements on police coercion that described the processes by which police officers may commit, and why police departments sometimes attempt to hide, police brutality. This entry considers these perspectives as occupational templates and describes the most important of these below. Starting at the individual-level, in his largely ethnographic study of the police in “Laconia” (a pseudonym), Muir (1977) interviewed and then observed a group of police officers in an effort to understand how they responded to “critical” incidents in their work settings. It is now commonly known that “Laconia” was Oakland, CA, a large city that employed 800 police officers at the time of Muir’s research, and which was characterized by high levels of racially concentrated economic resource deprivation and crime. During his research, Muir observed four police officer Police and the Excessive Use of Force personality “types” that were differentiated by two elements: the abilities to (1) empathize with those whom they encountered on the street, and (2) morally reconcile need to use force in certain circumstances. For example, the archetypal officer in Muir’s typology was the “professional” – i.e., a collective group of officers who could place themselves psychologically in the life circumstances of the suspects they encountered, and although professionals did not care to use force to resolve most conflicts during their engagements with members of the public, they used force when necessary to stop conflict, protect lives, and restore order. Once the situational exigencies were neutralized, professionals ceased their use of physical force. A key attribute of professionals was their ability to communicate effectively with suspects in ways that often minimized, de-escalated, or even eliminated the need to use force during many incidents. In contrast to the professionals were the “enforcers:” Officers who had the highest propensity to use excessive force against suspects because they (1) generally lacked the capacity to fathom the often “tragic” conditions that characterized the lives of many people they encountered, and (2) were quick to resort to violence when they perceived minimal threats to their safety or when they felt compelled to assert police authority. Muir (1977) noted that, unlike the professionals, enforcers usually lacked the communication skills necessary to de-escalate and/or otherwise avoid the need to use force in certain circumstances. As a result, enforcers often created situations where other officers near them were forced to use violence against suspects because of the degree to which enforcers provoked violence during their contacts with the public. Thus, and as Muir notes, enforcers were problematic to police workgroups partly because they frequently engaged in excessive force, and partly because they often caused potentially violent encounters to escalate into actual violent encounters. Perhaps the most interesting and important element of Muir’s (1977) typology was the recognition that officers might slide between one personality type and another based on cues in 3551 P the social environment. For example, officers regarded as professionals – and who usually conducted themselves appropriately during most police-citizen encounters – sometimes became enforcers during certain incidents. Muir, for example, identified one “professional” officer among those he studied who was highly communicative and restrained in virtually all street encounters except when he responded to sexual or domestic assaults against female victims. These events tended to trigger an uncharacteristic response in the officer – perhaps due to family history or other personal experience – leading him to take on the attributes of the enforcer: He was quick to use violence as an initial response when contacting an alleged domestic or sexual assault offender. Thus, although Muir’s typology was largely psychological, it recognized the importance of social context when analyzing street-level behavior of officers. Although no identified studies have found reliable empirical support for Muir’s typology (see, for example, Hochstedler (1981)), none has tested the typology in a setting that replicates that in which Muir conducted his research. It may be that Muir’s findings hold primarily for postindustrial port cities with large urban African-American populations that live predominantly in poverty conditions, socially isolated from the larger urban matrix. Such are the conditions that most often allow officers to engage in abuse of authority – including excessive force – with little fear of recourse (e.g., Kane 2002; Kubrin and Weitzer 2003). Moreover, despite scant support for the typology itself, at least one study has found that – like Muir’s findings – officers who exhibit certain personality characteristics (diffuse though they may be) often “slide” between profiles as the social contexts in which they work vary (Hochstedler 1981). This finding supports Muir’s observation that even socalled professional police officers may become “enforcers” under the circumstances that elicit particularly strong responses, and perhaps where local social constraints are wanting. Such findings demonstrate the importance of the social ecological contexts in which officers work as determinants of their behaviors. At the very P P 3552 least, Muir’s typology provides a useful taxonomy for efficiently describing certain officer characteristics that are easily recognized – i.e., enforcer. Residing one level up from Muir (1977) on the social ecological progression is Van Maanen’s (1978) “asshole” perspective. This framework is so-named for the colloquial usage of the term by police officers as a shorthand for suspects who – through speech or gesture – “deny” a police officer’s “definition” of the power structure that characterizes their interactions with the public – namely, that officers are in charge. Van Maanen argued that the line officers he studied tended to classify members of the public into three groups: “suspicious persons” (suspected criminal offenders), “assholes” (people who challenge police authority), and “know nothings” (people who do not fit the previous two categories and who are also not police officers). Whereas police officers usually have little or no cause to use coercion against know nothings, and they generally use coercion only as necessary to control and/or gain the compliance of suspicious persons, they may use coercion – i.e., force – against those labeled assholes as a retaliatory mechanism to redress an affront to an officer’s authority (Van Maanen 1978). Van Maanen (1978) observed that a suspect’s initial response to a police officer’s inquiry determined the officer’s categorization of him (Van Maanen never clarifies as to whether the template applies to female suspects), as well as the subsequent police reaction. Suspects who appeared to reject the officer’s definition of the situation – thereby challenging the officer’s authority and legitimacy – were labeled assholes and were often subjected to a violent response as a form of punishment or reassertion of authority. From an officer workgroup standpoint, police officers who labeled a suspect an asshole were justified, and perhaps even expected, to use violence to reestablish control. Recall Incident #2 – the dramatized use of force scenario – in the “Excessive Force Through Legal and Social Lenses” section of this entry. The officer’s response to the youthful driver’s verbal resistance was a quintessential example Police and the Excessive Use of Force of how a person may become labeled an asshole under Van Maanen’s model. Importantly – and as shown in Incident #2 – when officers label a suspect an asshole, and to the extent that the officers use brutality to redress the affront, they often do so to impose police authority typically at the expense of formal sanctioning (e.g., arrest). As such, some suspects – particularly those engaged in illegal behavior when contacted by the officer – may accept the brutality in lieu of a formal sanction because if they reported the brutality, they would also have to report their activities that led to their initial contact with the police. Though it is the case that occupational templates-perspectives often fail to yield empirical support, at least one recent study has offered some empirical validation of Van Maanen’s (1978) “asshole” thesis. In a study of how the occupational goals of police may sometimes conflict with rule of law practices, Kane and Cronin (2011) examined the extent to which police officers used force in situations that may have been characterized by the “asshole” process. Through the use of discriminant function analysis, Kane and Cronin reported that during coercive exchanges with suspects (i.e., situations that ultimately ended in arrest), suspects who demonstrated “verbal antagonism” toward officers – but not physical resistance – were likely to be “punched” and “kicked” during the incident. Interestingly, when suspects demonstrated physical resistance, but not necessarily verbal antagonism, they were usually subjected to more “normal” types of force, such as chemical sprays, baton strikes, or basic joint locks (Kane and Cronin 2011). Verbal antagonism appeared to elicit “asshole” responses in the form of punches and kicks – use of force techniques that usually do not exist on a police use of force continuum. Whereas Van Maanen (1978) operationalized the “asshole” perspective as one rooted primarily in the social interactionist tradition, there is evidence that the asshole process also may be driven in part by police subcultural pressures. In his observational study of how the Los Angeles Police Department controls space within its vast jurisdictional boundaries, Herbert (1998, p. 347) Police and the Excessive Use of Force adds a conceptual dimension to Van Maanen (1978) with his identification of normative orders: a collective subcultural belief system “. . .oriented around a common value.” Herbert argues that police officers working in small groups develop informal work and productivity standards within the context of six normative orders that include law, bureaucratic control, adventure/machismo, safety, competence, and morality. Herbert (1998, p. 347) observes that officer workgroups place differential values on the normative orders in ways that “provide guidelines and justifications for” workgroup enforcement activities. For present purposes, Herbert notes that normative orders – such as law and safety or law and competence – may conflict with one another as officers use their coercive authority to satisfy one normative order (e.g., competence), perhaps at the expense of another (e.g., law or bureaucratic control). Herbert’s normative order system, which he referred to a police subculture, may be integrate with occupational templates because it explains how situational circumstances may trigger police responses designed to satisfy occupational goals. For example, officers confronted by a suspect they label as “dangerous” will likely invoke the normative order of safety to minimize the threat of violence. Similarly, officers who enter into a coercive encounter with a bellicose suspect – an “asshole” in Van Maanan’s (1978) taxonomy – may seek to demonstrate their competence to other officers in their workgroup by using excessive force or brutality, which may be regarded as situationally justified to reassert police authority over a noncompliant suspect. Again, such an application of coercion may conflict with rule of law orders, but may be regarded as occupationally necessary if officers achieve the objectives of their primary normative value. Finally, to understand how police agencies themselves may create a culture that fosters, if not encourages, the excessive use of force by their officers, it is important to consider the research on police organizations. In Los Angeles, the Christopher Commission assigned to investigate patterns of excessive violence in the LAPD in the wake of the 1991 beating of motorist 3553 P Rodney King identified a “siege mentality” that was prevalent among officers of that department (Independent Commission 1991, p. 95). This siege mentality, the Commission argued, led officers to view their relationship with the community at large as adversarial (the “us vs. them” perspective) and appeared to legitimize the excessive use of force by police against suspects in an environment that all but guaranteed immunity from accountability (Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). The confidence that officers placed in their ability to freely “punish” suspects who committed affronts against police authority was perhaps best illustrated by the routine exchanges among officers via their mobile data terminals in which anecdotes describing violent activities – often in racist terminology – were openly exchanged (see: Independent Commission (1991)). Appealing to occupational templates to help explain the processes by which excessive force may be used and legitimized by police officers is instructive because they offer a social ecological context within which to interpret police brutality that is often absent from the empirical literature that examines excessive force. Templates, such as Muir’s (1977) extortionate transaction model, Van Maanen’s (1978) “asshole” perspective, Herbert’s (1997) identification of workgroup “normative orders,” and Skolnick and Fyfe’s (1993) elaboration of the “siege” mentality, show that police brutality may be influenced at every level of a police officer’s contextual occupational life. Moreover, they offer insight into how some officers who may be disinclined to use brutality on suspects may operate in layered contexts that favor, or even expect, them to use excessive against certain suspects under certain circumstances. Some Consequences of Police Brutality Perhaps the most obvious consequences of police brutality are the direct effects endured by victims. Although there are no national data on the subject, it seems clear that people who experience police brutality can suffer physical harms ranging P P 3554 from minor aches and pains to serious injury, and in some cases, death. It is also likely that people who experience physical abuse at the hands of police may suffer emotional trauma. In the United States, however, police agencies are not required to report use of force – let alone excessive force – incidents to any centralized authority, leading researchers and policy-makers to make guesses about the frequency and severity of police brutality. This problem could be ameliorated by the implementation of a national reporting system on the police use of force. In addition to the direct effects of police brutality to those who experience such abuse, there are often broader sociological consequences that may result when police engage in the excessive use of force, particularly when the force is systemic in nature and occurs in communities whose residents perceive that they have been socially and legally marginalized by their municipal governments. Among these, perhaps the gravest consequence is the loss of legitimacy police forces can experience when officers are viewed as brutal or abusive, and when community residents perceive little or no recourse to control them. Tyler (1990) has argued that societies are more likely than not to comply with the law when they believe in the morality of the law and in the legitimacy of the government making the law. For a society to accept law as moral and the government as legitimate, its members must believe in the fairness of the law-making process (Tyler 1990). This model of procedural justice generally argues that the way a state achieves and maintains legitimacy is by distributing its authority through consensus-based processes without regard for the social and economic statuses of societal subgroups. If the public becomes polarized over issues related to the distribution of legal authority, the government may lose legitimacy and find it difficult to fulfill its “regulatory role” in society (Sunshine and Tyler 2003, p. 515) without having to resort to the frequent use of physical coercion. This issue is important for municipal authorities, as some members of the public, particularly those residing in communities characterized by racial segregation and/or systemic economic resource deprivation, may Police and the Excessive Use of Force perceive inequities in the distribution of police resources in violation of procedural justice expectations (Jacob 1971). Kubrin and Weitzer (2003) were among the first researchers to find social scientific evidence supporting the above arguments. In their study of retaliatory homicide in St. Louis, Kubrin and Weitzer found that certain types of homicides predicted subsequent homicides in the form of retaliation, suggesting that, had the initial homicide been stopped, the net reduction in many cases would have been two, given that the retaliatory homicide also would have been negated. In the qualitative portion of their study, Kubrin and Weitzer found through unstructured interviews that the initial homicides were allowed to occur in large part because community residents refused to share information related to criminal activity with the police due to their distrust of law enforcement authorities. This distrust stemmed from perceived abuses – including brutality – of community residents by police over a number years. Kubrin and Weitzer’s (2003) findings were largely consistent with Anderson’s (1999) observations of the so-called Code of the Street. Anderson argued that the Code – in which respect was valued as a social good, earned and maintained by the threat and/or use of violence – prevailed in the north Philadelphia community he studied in part because the police had virtually no legitimacy due to their perceived abuses of authority. Kane (2005) made similar findings in New York City in his examination of the consequences of “over-policing” and police misconduct (including violence) on violent crime. For present purposes, Kane found that in economically stable communities, police misconduct had no effect on violent crime. In economically disadvantaged, and “extremely” economically disadvantaged, communities, police misconduct (including violence) led to subsequent increases in violent crime. Kane attributed this relationship to the same processes driving Kurbin and Weitzer’s (2003) findings: As residents of socially/economically marginalized communities perceived increases in police abuses, they likely ceased sharing crime-related intelligence with Police and the Excessive Use of Force authorities, allowing violent crimes to occur that may have been otherwise prevented. In his classic lecture, “Politics as a Vocation,” Max Weber (see: Weber et al. 2004, pp. 78–79) argued that because the State “claims the monopoly on the legitimate use of force” to enforce its laws, politicians who hope to gain the “obedience” of those whom they govern need not simply do the right thing; politicians must appear to do the right thing. Weber’s arguments are made salient by Kubrin and Weitzer (2003) and Kane (2005): Failure of the police to “govern” effectively the territories they serve may lead to noncompliance on the part of people who reside in communities characterized by the perceptions of police abuse of authority. In the “everyday” sense, citizen’s noncompliance may manifest in the form of people failing to readily yield to police authority during traffic stops and stopand-frisk events – both of which may create a context of hostility and distrust on the part of the police and members of the public. In the broader and more extreme sense, generations of police abuse, including unchecked or redressed brutality, may lead to urban violence. Indeed, two of the most destructive urban riots in American history have been attributed to long-standing patterns of police abuses, including unchecked brutality. On August 11, 1965, a white California Highway Patrol officer stopped an African-American motorist in the Watts section of Los Angeles for suspected Driving While Intoxicated. Even at that time, Watts was an area of Los Angeles, characterized by racially concentrated economic resource deprivation, which had a difficult history with the police. The motorist – Marquette Frye – resisted being taken into custody, which led to an escalating confrontation with police (Barnhill 2010). As more officers arrived on scene, the crowd of bystanders also grew until someone finally began throwing bottles and other objects at the officers, who continued their struggle to subdue Frye (Barnhill 2010). In the process of taking Frye into custody, officers also arrested his mother and brother for unlawfully interfering with the arrest, which led the crowd to switch from throwing bottles to throwing rocks and 3555 P other large items at police (Barnhill 2010). This inciting incident led to 6 days of rioting in Watts, leading to 34 deaths, 1,032 injuries, and over 3,000 arrests (Barnhill 2010). Although post-riot analyses generally concluded that poor living conditions and the social marginalization of African-Americans in Los Angles represented the root causes of the Watts riot (e.g., California Governor’s Commission on the Los Angeles Riots 1965), some researchers concluded that years of police abuse and brutality in Los Angeles – particularly during the tenure of Police Chief William H. Parker, during which the LAPD transformed into highly aggressive paramilitary police force – was largely responsible for the riot (Skolnick and Fyfe). Indeed, the McCone Commission, empanelled just a few months after the riots and charged with identifying the causes, noted from its many interviews of AfricanAmerican Watts residents: “Police brutality” has been the recurring charge. One witness after another has recounted instances in which, in their opinion, the police have used excessive force or have been disrespectful and abusive in their language or manner (Governor’s Commission 1965, p. 40) The social and economic costs of the 1965 Los Angeles riot were eclipsed only by those of the 1992 Los Angeles riot, which occurred in the immediate aftermath of two white police officers being acquitted for beating motorist Rodney King. During the 1992 riot, the LAPD and the California National Guard killed 53 people. More than 2,000 people were injured, and over 1,000 buildings were destroyed by fire (Wood 2002). The fact that both riots occurred in Los Angeles was no surprise to Jerome Skolnick and James J. Fyfe – two of the nation’s leading scholars of police authority and accountability – who argued that since William Parker was appointment police chief of Los Angeles in 1950, the LAPD became increasingly insular, aggressive, and unaccountable to the mayor and city council (Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). The unaccountability was particularly pronounced under Chief Daryl Gates, who enjoyed civil service protection and indemnity from lawsuits (Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). P P 3556 It seems clear that, while people subjected to direct forms of police brutality suffer the most immediate harm from such abuse, those residing in communities – even cities – in which the police engage in the excessive use of force with little accountability also experience the resulting harms. Violent incidents in Los Angeles (1965 and 1992), Detroit (1967), Chicago (1968), Liberty City-Miami (1980), Cincinnati (2001) – even Tulsa in 1921 – were not so much riots as they were urban rebellions. In each event, the triggering incident was related to some form of police abuse, and all post-riot analyses identified abusive police practices, largely in communities characterized by racially concentrated economic resource deprivation and social marginalization, as major causal factors (see: Independent Commission 1991; Kerner Commission 1968; Skolnick and Fyfe 1993). Preventing Excessive Use of Force As previously alluded to, people who experience police brutality or the excessive use of force have recourse through the conventional mechanisms of police accountability: the citizen complaint process, mediation, and the courts. Each of these avenues of recourse has varying chances of success, depending on the several factors related to the event, including the social desirability of the accuser, the degree to which the incident occurred in the public realm and/or in view of credible witnesses, the extent to which the accuser may have attempted to initially evade or who otherwise resisted police officers, and in many cases the quality of the accuser’s legal counsel. While individual plaintiffs may prevail in their attempts to hold police accountable for the use of excessive force, most would probably argue that best recourse would be the prevention of police brutality before it occurs. The most immediate methods by which to control and/or prevent the excessive use of force by police are probably rooted in the recruitment of police officers, training and supervision, and the establishment of organizational cultures within police Police and the Excessive Use of Force departments that value the protection of life over the enforcement of law as a primary function. The personnel processes police departments use to recruit and hire officers play a crucial role in shaping subsequent organizational behavior, but in ways that are perhaps more subtle than they are apparent. Police department hiring practices are generally designed to screen out undesirable applicants, which is substantively different from trying to screen in desirable applicants. These so-called screening-out practices are rarely evidence-based; and they are often not followed consistently over time or across police recruiters or background officers. Moreover, to the extent that the excessive use of force is a relatively rare event within police organizations, it is difficult to accurately predict who might have become “problem” officers over the course of their careers were they allowed to join the force. Although emerging evidence supports the practices of screening out applicants on the basis of employment and criminal histories to prevent general misconduct (see: Kane and White 2012), there is virtually no evidence that “violence-prone” (Toch 1996) police officers can be identified and effectively screened out through the normal recruiting process. Screening methods that favor recruits whose education, experience, cultural identities, and world views would create police department cultures not dominated by a single gender or ethnic group, and it would raise the possibility that members of all subgroups would contribute to the development of a sensitive workforce tolerant of people across race and class. Empirical findings support this claim: In their study of careerending misconduct in the New York City Police Department, Kane and White (2012) found that from 1975 to 1998, as the NYPD became increasingly racially and ethnically diverse, it also became better behaved. Rates of misconduct decreased as diversity increased, independent of external factors that often influence organizational rates of misconduct. Although the NYPD over that time period may not have systematically recruited persons with diverse characteristics or personal histories, the results of bringing diverse Police and the Excessive Use of Force pools of recruits into policing are clear: Organizational misconduct declines. In addition to recruitment, supervision of police officers is also critical in preventing excessive use of force – particularly in communities that historically have had difficult access to the conventional mechanisms of police accountability. For example, in a study of police misconduct in New York City police precincts, Kane (2002) found that the traditional antecedents of social disorganization – particularly, structural disadvantage – predicted increased rates of careerending police misconduct. Precincts characterized by the highest rates of racially concentrated structural disadvantage also had the highest rates of police misconduct. This finding led Kane (2002, p. 891) to conclude that, “The very communities likely in need of the most protection by the police. . .(are also) in need of the greatest protection from the police. . .” One way to offer that protection is through the supervision of officers. In many American police departments, the average staffing ratios call for one sergeant for every nine patrol officers (Walker and Katz 2010), and while scant research highlights what supervisors actually do, at least one study suggests that low spans-of-control (i.e., high ratio of supervisors to officers) decreased excessive force (Terrill 2001). Although modern organizational police theory generally argues that low spans-ofcontrol are inefficient to the administration of police departments (making the assumption that “flatter” organizations function more efficiently than “tall” organizations) (e.g., Walker and Katz), in communities where the risk of misconduct may be higher than average, it seems that lower spans-of-control would reduce the risk of brutality as supervisors have more contact with line officers in the field. Indeed, under such conditions, what may be sacrificed in terms of organizational efficiency may be gained in effectiveness. Finally, recruitment and supervision to limit police and the excessive use of force seem to have their highest probabilities of success if the overall police department culture supports the structural efforts in place to guard against brutality. The 3557 P tone must be set at the top through the implementation of progressive policies that strive for transparency in the disciplinary review process and promote model tactics and strategies. In addition, evidence suggests that when line officers are involved in the development of use of force policies and field tactics designed to reduce police officer violence (i.e., Fyfe 1997), then the use of force within departments tends to decrease, partly because police officers view themselves as contributors to the policy development process, rather than simply as people who need to be controlled. Once the chief administrator implements an infrastructure of progressive policy and gains the “buy-in” of line officers, the message of progressive policing must filter through all layers of the police organization. One method by which to accomplish the process of communicating the department’s value system is via the field training officers (FTOs). Toch (1996) argued that for the purposes of controlling police violence, field training officers were instrumental in bridging the gap for new officers between the messages they received in the training academy and the messages they received from their peers once on the street. Toch argued that FTOs serve a crucial organizational role because, among other functions, they help probationary police officers practice their recently acquired skills in live settings while under highly structured supervision. During this formative period in a police officer’s career, FTOs can help new officers interpret street encounters in ways that allow them to learn and practice good policing through the metaphorical lenses of a protection of life mandate. Once they complete their field training programs, police officers may continue to practice good policing and the protection of life in both patrol and specialized settings. Successfully preventing the use of excessive force by police likely requires a multilayered approach that considers the social ecology of the total police organization. While the chief administrator is an important part of the process within the organization, it must be noted that the chief also represents the will of the community. Chief administrators for police departments are P P 3558 usually chosen by the elected bodies of local governments (e.g., city councils, county boards of supervisors, etc.), often for their stated positions on certain issues, such as violent crime, fear of crime, urban disorder, etc. Excessive use of force will be minimized only if governing boards select chief administrators who are actively interested in controlling and preventing excessive use of force. Moreover, the governing boards themselves need to share the same commitment to police accountability if excessive force is to be controlled and prevented in a police organization. Conclusions Evaluating the use of excessive force by the police tends to be much more difficult than other forms of misconduct, such as profitmotivated corruption. Unlike other forms of police deviance, which tend to be wrong by their very occurrence, the roots of police brutality reside in the legitimate use of force – a tool society gives police to accomplish its mandate. Therefore, when an officer is accused of brutality, it is often difficult, if not impossible, to determine where the justified use of force may have become excessive. Even in the infamous, and unquestioningly brutal, Rodney King case, the police officers who contacted King had cause to use some physical coercion in their initial attempts to bring him into compliance. This entry identified classic occupational templates of the police use of force in an effort to identify context within which the excessive use of force may be considered. Although these templates have received little empirical validation, they are meaningful because in many cases, they offer a shorthand for describing the conditions under which police officers may resort to brutality. Although police departments can use recruitment as a tool to prevent the excessive use of force by their officers, the best prevention is likely based on a multilevel approach that involves local governing bodies selecting chief administrators with strong commitments to transparency and the virtues of “good” policing. Police and the Excessive Use of Force Related Entries ▶ Biased Policing ▶ Control of Police Misconduct ▶ Crime and the Racial Composition of Communities ▶ Democratic Policing ▶ Drug Enforcement ▶ Hot Spots and Place-Based Policing ▶ Law of Police Use of Force ▶ Minorities Within the Police Workforce ▶ Police and the Military Nexus ▶ Police Corruption ▶ Police Culture ▶ Police Discretion and Its Control ▶ Police Integrity ▶ Police Leadership Styles ▶ Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters ▶ Police Line-Level and Agency Accountability ▶ Police Selection ▶ Police Use of Firearms ▶ Risk Management in Policing ▶ Sex Offenders and Criminal Policy Recommended Reading and References Anderson E (1999) Code of the street: decency, violence, and the moral life of the inner city. New York: W.W. Norton & Company 42 U.S.C. } 1983 Barnhill JH (2010) Watts riots (1965). In: Danver SL (ed) Revolts, protests, demonstrations, and rebellions in American history, vol 3. Santa Barbara, ABC-CLIO Carter D (1985) Police brutality: a model for definition, perspective, and control. In: Neiderhoffer A, Blumberg A (eds) The ambivalent force. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York Fyfe J (1979) Administrative interventions on police shooting discretion: an empirical examination. J Crim Justice 7:309–323 Fyfe J (1986) The split-second syndrome and other determinants of police violence. In: Anne T. Campbell, John J. Gibbs (eds) Violent Transactions. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp 207–225 Fyfe J (1997) Good policing. In: Dunham R, Alpert GP (eds) Critical issues in policing: contemporary readings, 5th edn. Waveland, Prospect Heights, pp 194–213 California Governor’s Commission on the Los Angeles Riots (1965) Violence in the city: an end or a beginning? Graham v. Connor, 490 U.S. at 388 (1989) Herbert S (1997) Policing space: territoriality and the Los Angeles Police Department. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis Police and the Military Nexus Herbert S (1998) Police subculture revisited. Criminology 36:343–369 Hochstedler E (1981) Testing types: a review and test of police types. J Crim Justice 19:451–466 Independent Commission (1991) Report of the Independent Commission on the Los Angeles Police Department. The Commission, Los Angeles Jacob H (1971) Black and white perceptions of justice in the city. Law Soc Rev 6:69–89 Kane R (2002) The social ecology of police misconduct. Criminology 40:867–896 Kane R (2005) Linking compromised police legitimacy to violent crime in structurally disadvantaged communities. Criminology 43:469–498 Kane R, Cronin S (2011) Maintaining order under the rule of law: occupational templates and the police use of force. J Crime Justice 34:163–177 Kane R, White M (2012) Jammed up: bad cops, police misconduct, and the New York City Police Department. New York University Press, New York Kerner Commission (1968) Report of the National Advisory Commission on civil disorders. Bantam Books, New York Klockars C (1985) The idea of police. Sage, Beverly Hills Kubrin C, Weitzer R (2003) Retaliatory homicide: concentrated disadvantage and neighborhood culture. Soc Probl 50:157–180 Muir WK (1977) Police: streetcorner politicians. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Skolnick J, Fyfe JJ (1993) Above the law: police and the excessive use of force. Free Press, New York Sunshine J, Tyler T (2003) The role of procedural justice and legitimacy in shaping public support for policing. Law Soc Rev 37:513–547 Tennessee v. Garner, 471 U.S. 1 (1985) Terrill W (2001) Police coercion. LBF Scholarly Publishing, New York Toch H (1996) The violence-prone police officer. In: Geller W, Toch H (eds) Police violence: understanding and controlling police abuse of force. Yale University Press, New Haven, pp 94–112 Tyler T (1990) Why people obey the law. Yale University Press, New Haven Van Maanen J (1978) The asshole. In: Manning PK, Van Maanen J (eds) Policing: a view from the street. Goodyear, Santa Monica, pp 221–238 Walker S (2010) Sense and nonsense about crime, drugs, and communities, 7th edn. Wadsworth, Belmont Walker S, Katz C (2010) Police in America: an Introduction. McGraw-Hill, New York Weber M, Owen D, Strong TB (2004) The vocation lectures: “Science as a Vocation” and “Politics as a Vocation,” (trans: Livingstone R). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company Westley W (1970) Violence and the police. MIT Press, Cambridge Wood DB (2002) L.A.’s darkest days. Christian science monitor. Retrieved 2 Nov 2012 3559 P Police and the Military Nexus Otwin Marenin Department of Criminal Justice and Criminology, Washington State University, Pullman, WA, USA Synonyms Constabularization; Militarization Overview The police and military (armed forces), the two coercive agencies of the state, are restricted by law, tradition, and policy to two domains in which they exercise authority. The police protect the domestic order against risk, threats, and crimes by persuasive communications, the enforcement of laws, and, ultimately, force (or its potential use), while the military defends the nation and the state against aggression from without. These analytical and policy distinctions between two agencies (or systems of agencies) which are authorized to employ legitimate internal and external use of force to deal with threats have become blurred in practice (Easton et al. 2010). The argument and worry that the police in the USA and other democratic countries are increasingly becoming militarized, hence will loose the civil and democratic orientation to their work, the use of force, and the collections of intelligence, has been raised by a number of scholars who study the police and by the police themselves (Kraska 2001, 2007; Kraska and Kappeller 1997). Much of the concern that the blurring of distinctions between the policing and the military work will undermine civil and democratic policing rests on two limited understandings about the police, namely, that policing has never been militarized to any degree and by comparing two “ideal types” (yet legitimate conceptions) of both the police and the military rather than their historical configurations, relationships, and work. P P 3560 The blurring of policing and military work and tasks is not new; it only has increased and taken many new forms in recent times, specifically by recent domestic and international developments (transnational crime, fears of terrorism, civil violence in failed states, peacekeeping and peacebuilding interventions, the weakening of border controls, technological advances in information acquisition, processing, and distribution). The distinctions drawn between military and police forces have always been blurred in practice. Police and military have worked in the same occupational space – the protection of society against threats; they have been bestowed by their societies with the right to use force, and the core values enshrined in their occupational cultures (internal authority, discipline, closed ranks, loyalty, courage, masculinity) are similar (den Boer et al. 2010, 225–226). Ideal Typing the Police and the Military Ideal Typing Democratic, Civil Policing The classic image of the democratic police officer is the patrol officer, the constable walking the beat, known by and knowing the community and the village; approachable, protective, and friendly when encountering citizens in need; committed to service, the protection of human rights, and the rule of law; doing her/his work with integrity; and ensuring the effective protection of public order and the security of property and lives of the populace against threats and crimes. Democratic, civil police retain substantial domains of discretion in how to respond and to adjust their decisions to situational exigencies, guided by law, professional norms, public demands, and democratic political oversight (OSCE 2006). Since full service tasks are most common work done by police in democratic countries, this image is not a false one. The essence of democratic policing is captured in six aspects of their work: authority to control and suppress illegal conduct is limited by and large to the domestic arena; the composition of police personnel should approximate the distribution of salient identity groups in society; Police and the Military Nexus orientation to public service; the constrained use of force; transparency in actions; and accountability to civic society by various mechanisms. The occupational culture of democratic police officers and the organizational policies which shape their work and guide their discretion stress that policing is a service to the public and not to the state. Their use of force should be strictly limited by law, professional norms, and organizational directives and used only as a last resort when dealing with all people they encounter. The police have a responsibility to explain when asked, and the public has a right to know what the police are doing (except for legitimate secrecy in pending cases and investigative aspects of their work). The police cannot hide behind the shield of expertise and secrecy related to their general work, nor deny the media, the public, and the political leaders’ access to the information in their possession, unless legitimately protected. Lastly, if allegations of misconduct, abuse of power, or corruption are made against them, the police have an obligation to submit to external oversight, and the public has the right to require their submission to civic reviews. They do not have the exclusive authority and power to investigate allegations of misconduct in their ranks by themselves and take corrective actions. As government officials having great power over the routines of living in society, they cannot claim impunity for their conduct. Ideal Typing the Professional Soldier The military are an armed, professionally trained, and hierarchically controlled organization in which lower ranks are expected to respond quickly and without questioning to commands from the top. The military protects the nation, its people and territory, and the “national interest” by using its ability to detect and suppress external threats. It uses its capacity to exercise force to capture, disable, or kill enemies of the nation in an efficient, fast, and effective manner. The military collects information in secret via sophisticated and complex technologies and human spies and evaluates and distributes information as “intelligence” which is typically kept secret by national security justifications and Police and the Military Nexus tactical contingencies. Transparency is severely limited by the need to keep the country safe from aggression which, were the nature of the intelligence and the means by which it was collected be known, would jeopardize the ability to plan and execute the collection of information. Accountability of the military for its strategic and tactical conduct is first to itself, with civilian oversight by elected leaders the last overriding democratic option. By law and tradition, the military in democratic societies only intervene in domestic security when national and local policing systems are unable to maintain control. Distinctions In short, ideal-type descriptions of police and military emphasize fundamental distinctions between the two security agencies authorized to use force in order to protect the nation-state, its government, its economic and political ways of life, and its people and properties against domestic and external threats. Specifically, the police see the people they have to deal with primarily as customers, innocents, and suspects, while the military sees real and potential enemies. The police are committed to maintaining public order, provide services, and enforce domestic laws while the military seeks the defeat of enemies and victory. The police use force only as the last resort in encounters, while the military resorts to force immediately to disable, capture, or kill enemies. The police tend to work as individuals (or limited teams) while teamwork is essential to the military. The police at the lowest ranks of the organizational hierarchy have substantial discretion in specific actions and encounters, a discretion that is circumscribed by situational exigencies and the best judgment of the officers on what is the appropriate, effective, and balanced action in the situation they are faced with. The military limits discretion at the lowest ranks through intensive training, a commitment to authoritative interpretations of what needs to be done in a situation (“that’s an order, soldier”), and loyalty to group. The discretion of the police is influenced by personal morality and ideological beliefs, while the military seeks to socialize new recruits and experienced 3561 P soldiers to an ideology that eliminates personal views as guides to actions. The police are accountable to public oversight and the courts; the military has its own legal system, code of conduct, and “criminal justice” institutions (military police, administrative tribunals and courts, investigative units). Civilian law enters only at the appeals level, after military institutions have reached a decision on alleged criminal misconduct or violations of the code of conduct. Control over actions by a professional military in a democracy is exercised largely internally, supported by professional norms which accept that the military is ultimately subject to civilian leadership (by the “Commander in Chief,” or some such term). Unlike the police, which are always guided and judged by laws made through an open, participatory political process external to the police, the military judges itself by its own laws and rules with external domestic political oversight and international conventions on the conduct of war as the ultimate backstops. The argument predicts that the “militarization” of the culture, policies, and actions of police – that is, the adoption by civilian police forces “of militaristic practices, hardware, technology, values, language, and ideology” (Kraska 1997: 299) – will be a danger to democratic norms and professional ethics of the police. Rather than follow the rule of law, professional codes of conduct, or commitment to public service and the protection of human rights, the police will drift toward a professional ideology which stresses the need to protect national and local security against threats and risks without interference or oversight by legal institutions, political oversight, or public demands. The necessary democratic balance between the rights of people and the practical need for security will tilt strongly toward security. This argument rests on four main assertions. First, the police will alter their orientation to the use of force and the identification of categories of people against whom force can and should be used quickly and easily, justified by appeals to an “enemy” and “threat” language. Second, the police will shift from an orientation to public P P 3562 service toward a suppression of crime and disorder mentality and compliance with political definitions of threats to public order and safety. Third, the police will be drawn into the secretive collection of intelligence and categorical risk assessments which invade the privacy of people and assume threats, risks, and criminal intentions based on an individual’s membership in categories of persons (e.g., young male members of minority or ethnic groups, bikers, Roma, Muslims, travelers from certain countries) as these categories are defined by the police and intelligence agencies. Perceived threats and risks will have to be deterred and prevented by proactive police and intelligence collection policies before they can be executed. Fourth, transparency will decline. The police will become less accountable via civic oversight of their actions. There is evidence to support these arguments but less support for the conclusions that democratic policing is threatened and may be replaced by new forms of aggressive, forceful policing which undermine basic privacy rights and equal treatment of people and communities. Beyond Ideal Typing: Existing Overlaps in History and Space The reality is that the police have always done a variety of work in nondemocratic ways and that the military has always worked with the police on specific security and order maintaining tasks. In practice, historically and currently, the police and the military have exhibited overlapping characteristics and work habits. Varieties of Policing Being visible, available, and responsive to the needs of people, though crucial to any conception of democratic policing, is not the only type of work done by any police force. Tasks specified for the police have always included multiple goals and roles ranging from civil policing to state security policing (Brodeur 1983). All police forces anywhere include functional specializations which approach military-style tactics and mentalities: riot control, specialized units Police and the Military Nexus confronting dangerous situations (armed response teams, paramilitary police units), border policing, state security police protecting the political regime against threats to its rule, and the complete exception to democratic norms of colonial policing. Specialized police agencies and units tend not to share the mentalities, priorities, and practices which are claimed to be the defining traits of civil, democratic, and accountable police force. Control of riots and demonstrations is not targeted primarily against individual malfeasance but is deployed as an organized, forceful police response to public, frequently violent, disorders (Della Porta and Reiter 1998). In most countries, should the police fail to control disorders, the military (e.g., the National Guard in the USA) stands in the background ready to enter the fray and restore order. Distinct units trained in and employing military-style tactics (PPUs, Paramilitary Police Units) have infiltrated normal policing, a process which Kraska and Kappeller (1997) have argued is expanding. PPUs are expensive; not using them wastes public money; they have high status within the police profession; hence, their arms, group cohesion, and tactics are attractive to other police. Persons entering a country at recognized border crossing points, whether legally or illegally, have restricted democratic rights based on the overarching need to keep the country secure against threats and risks. Seeking to cross outside of legal control points will bring swift and forceful reactions from border guards who can be police, military, or integrated units (Andreas 2009; Caparini and Marenin 2006). At the US land borders, Marine units are deployed along the Mexico-US border, nominally for exercises but also to occupy and preempt territory through which threats and illegal migrants might enter the USA (Dunn 1996). At the Canada-US border, IBETs (Integrated Border Enforcement Teams), which include Canadian and US police, military, and intelligence agents, are a more recent development dealing with security threats (IBETs, web). Also, at that border, military drones have been called upon to assist Police and the Military Nexus local law enforcement in detecting fleeing felons and have responded successfully. The Coast Guard, an arm of the armed forces, has been responsible for the protection of sea borders. In most countries, including the European Union member states, border control is shared with police agencies or done exclusively by the military. State security police tasked with protecting the state, the ruling regime, and the powerful against challenges to their rule and status have few qualms about abiding by legal and democratic norms, nor do state security police take their orders from or are responsive to public concerns. Their job is to keep those in power safe. This is true in democratic countries and even more so in authoritarian, transitional, or military states. The prototype of state security police agencies were the KGB in the Soviet Union and other socialist and authoritarian countries, but they can also be found in democratic countries, as during the Franco dictatorship in Spain when the Guardia Civil (a constabulary force) was the tool used to terminally eliminate political and intellectual opponents of the regime, or in lesser and more benign forms, such as transnational threat assessment and anti-terrorism units in police departments or specialized security agencies, to arrest suspects before they can act (Brodeur 2000). In the history of state development (Bayley 1985; Tilly 1990) and the creation of security forces, there has always been a significant overlap between police and military work. That overlap has been strengthened in recent years by the shift in organized violence from traditional forms of aggression (requiring a military response) toward diffused, asymmetrical, nonconventional, substate forms – civil wars, guerilla insurgencies, identity group-based riots, and killings; the emergence in many parts of the world of powerful organized transnational crime groups who exert influence on states and societies by corruption, fear, and violence; and the growth in privatized policing and international policing and security providing companies. These developments have been enabled and smoothed by new technologies for sharing information and intelligence on a (almost) real-time basis. This new world (dis) 3563 P order (Kaldor 2001; Oakley et al. 1998) has led to a transformation in how all state-based, and even non-state, actors (e.g., private risk assessment and security companies) can be engaged in an integrated manner against new threat and risk dynamics. This convergence is most apparent in internationally sanctioned peacekeeping and peacebuilding operations. Police in UN and regional peacekeeping interventions, where local security forces have collapsed (e.g., Haiti, Timor Leste, Kosovo), have had to assume semi-military suppression and control functions as well as “normal” policing operations (Bayley and Perito 2010; Goldsmith and Harris 2010; Greener 2009). The biggest exception to democratic, nonmilitarized policing have been colonial policing systems. When European colonial powers developed police organizations for their colonies, they did not export policing systems deemed appropriate for their own, that is, civilized people, but constabulary forces to protect their economic, political, and “civilizing” interests in their colonies. As the majority of the world’s territories and states are former colonies, at independence they inherited nondemocratic and militarized policing systems which since have been quite resistant to changes, despite massive efforts to make them more democratic in their performance. Constabulary forces are semi-militarized police units created in different political, organizational, and cultural forms. In France, the gendarmerie developed as an occupying force in outlying areas of what is now France, in regions which opposed the imposition of central rule from Paris. In consequence, until very recently, the gendarmerie was located within the Ministry of Defense, even though it had become the police force which protected small towns and rural areas in France. British policy on policing England versus policing the colonies exemplifies the use of constabulary forces. The British practiced how to control restless populations during their centuries-long and brutal rule of the Irish. After Irish independence, policing in Northern Ireland, which remained part of the United Kingdom but was beset by ethnic, religious, and political violence P P 3564 and conflicts, continued the constabulary tradition via the Royal Ulster Constabulary, which was used to protect Irish loyalists in Northern Ireland often in cooperation with the British military. The lessons learned by the British in their colonial rule of Ireland became the model for policing their colonies (Brogden 1987). The Spanish and Portuguese colonizers exported their security systems to Latin and Central America which closely combined military and policing functions under one overarching organization. The police in most Latin American countries remained part of the military until fairly recently but still retain their titles (e.g., the Policia Militar in Brazil) and their outlook on citizens and criminals, captured nicely in the title of Husain’s (2007) study of police reform in Rio de Janeiro, “Those Who Die in War Are Not Innocent.” The USA established constabulary forces in Central America and the Caribbean to help protect American investments and personnel against “revolutionary” agitations. The constabularies became converted into (para)military forces once local control took over. In Nicaragua, the armed forces of the Somoza government, which engaged in a protracted war with the Sandinista Revolutionary Front to try to keep the government in power, were drawn mainly from that constabulary and were supported by illegally funded paramilitaries (the contras) by the USA. US police assistance under the aegis of OPS (Office of Public Safety), in the late 1960s and early 1970s, stressed counterinsurgency over democratic norms and roles which were easily picked up by local police forces in Southeast Asia and Latin America, the recipients of the majority of OPS funding and mentoring (Huggins 1987). Colonial policing had few attributes that one would characterize as civil or democratic policing. The police in colonies were used mainly by the colonial administrators to “pacify” the restless native, engage in military-style campaigns to punish local groups which resisted the imposition and demands (pay taxes, conscripted work) of colonial rule, protect tax collectors and the persons and property of commercial enterprises and missionaries, and suppress local riots and Police and the Military Nexus sabotage. There was no pretense that the police were to serve the population in any meaningful way; their job was to enable and protect colonial rule and all its activities, privileges, and laws. The modification of imposed policing system after decolonization has been slow and incremental, and much of the occupational cultures and priorities of the police have not been responsive to demands for reforms. For example, the most populous democracy in the world, India, still uses the colonial Police Act, passed in 1861, as the basis for defining the jobs of the police which, despite numerous constitutional, ideological, and legal statements, still shape the way in which state and federal police understand their job (Verma 2011). In Morocco, military officers still occupy the commanding positions in the gendarmerie, the police force which patrols the roads and services the rural areas of the country. In short, democratic policing, operationally defined as being available and willing to be of service to people in need, has been a rare policing model in history or is currently across the globe. Still, democratic policing as practiced by developed countries, currently in the guise of some form of community policing, has become the goal of police reforms promoted through international assistance programs. Militarization is seen as threatening progress toward that goal. Reforms of policing systems in countries where policing and justice systems have collapsed increasingly include the institutional separation of the police from the military and argue for the demilitarization of the occupational culture of the police. For example, the Chapultepec Peace Accords, signed in 1992, which ended the civil war in El Salvador, dissolved the National Police, then under the control of the military, and reconstituted a National Civil Police with detailed instructions on the organization, tasks, recruitment, training, and democratic responsibilities. Reform and democratic governance were deemed not possible unless the police were reconstituted and removed from the organizational authority of the military. Yet one must be careful when drawing a distinction between the organizational home of “policing agencies,” such as the gendarmerie, Police and the Military Nexus which are housed within the armed forces, and organizational and occupational cultures. Being under the administration of the military does not prevent democratic policing, nor does removing them from military administrative oversight create more democratic policing. The police can be quite forceful and abusive whether they work under military or civilian organizational umbrella. What matters are the organizational and occupational norms and cultures which are the guiding doctrines and “recipe rules” for the police. Constabularization of the Military The military, in its various institutional divisions, has been increasingly drawn into what used to be considered “policing” work in a variety of ways: assisting in border controls, intelligence sharing with domestic law enforcement agencies, counterinsurgency strategies to reach the hearts and minds of local populations, United Nations or regionally authorized peacekeeping operations which include military and police contingents, and “nation-building” after multilateral and regional interventions in failed and conflicted-ridden states. These trends undermine the traditional restrictions of the armed forces to war-fighting and war-ending work by involving them in tasks for which they have little training, few skills, and limited willingness (Friesendorf 2010; Friesendorf and Kempel 2011; Perito 2011). Training for military and police being deployed in international interventions, and increasingly for public order policing domestically, is conducted in a language which blurs traditional lines, which has led to both the constabularization of military goals and cultures and the paramilitarization of policing ideologies (Moelker 2010), and which will continue to undermine the bright line between police and military organizational cultures and practices and the distinction between domestic and external authority to exercise coercion. This convergence is not by design but forced by the nature of current international and domestic security climates. For example, the explosion of transnational crimes which affect domestic security (drugs, human trafficking, arms trade) 3565 P requires that police now work in other countries, in cooperation with local police, militaries, and intelligence agencies to control crime. Preventing convergence, or alternatively ensuring a continued separation and distinction between police and military work, will be difficult to maintain. Beyond Dichotomies: Theorizing the Police-Military Nexus How to theorize the new security structures? The most promising theoretical approach is the notion of a security sector or system (SS) and corresponding conceptualizations of reform (SSR) and governance (SSG). The security sector, in its leanest definition, includes the armed forces, police, border guards/police, and intelligence agencies as the core state security providers. In more expansive conceptions, the SS includes the criminal justice system, legal aspects of security, and non-state providers (Bryden and H€anggi 2004; OECD Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development 2007). Security sector theorizing stresses the interconnectedness of the four core state security agencies. Reforms of the security sector, or specifically the police, to establish more democratic professional and accountable norms and actions cannot be simply focused on the police but must take their connections to other state-based security and private security providers into account. Security is provided by many actors, and that requires that they cooperate and work together domestically and internationally. The political nature of policing, and other security policies, is central to the notion of a security sector and its governance. In addition to demilitarizing the police, reformers argue that the police be de-linked from centralized, political control of operational policies and tactics. Concluding Comments Concerns about militarizing the police are not illusory. Civil policing would change P P 3566 significantly if military cultures, norms, and practices began to infiltrate democratic cultures and styles of policing. At the same time, militarization is not the greatest threat to democratic policing. More serious is the involvement of the police in secretive intelligence gathering, often along stereotypical categorizations of terrorist, transnational crime groups, or local “troublemakers,” such as “suggestions” from the FBI to local police to map the distribution of mosques in their communities or efforts by the antiterrorist unit in the New York Police Department to infiltrate and keep tabs on Islamic leaders. The police who conduct such secret invasions and information gathering of people’s normal, and legal, activities by the justification of local and national security will loose, once their police activities become known, political support and legitimacy. The secret gathering of intelligence is just as likely to change the norms and cultures of policing as does militarization. The loss of transparency in collecting intelligence about normal activities disconnected from actual criminal threats and the convergence of domestic and international work from both the police and the military perspectives, both driven by political and national security justifications and the changing global world, are the historical and current reality which will not disappear. For example, President Reagan declared, by his authority, international drug trafficking a national security threat, not just a crime, thereby authorizing crime control and intelligence collecting actions which were legally prohibited to domestic police. The militarization of the police happens for diverse reasons, be it by the promotion of that style of defining their work by police themselves; by the acceptance of a frustrated public fed up with disorder, crime, and fears which beset their lives and willing to give up some rights for greater protection; by depictions in the mass and entertainment media which portray armed police tactics as the normal response to increasingly dangerous situations in normal police work; and by the exploitation of risks and threats by political polemicists. Police and the Military Nexus The issues are whether the militarization of policing and the constabularization of the military will become dominant norms and ideologies and whether the in-creeping of military styles into democratic policing will move that style permanently way from its service and order protection goals. It seems an unlikely possibility, as democratic policing is promoted worldwide, as part of larger political changes, by reformers, police officials, and progressive political leaders and also demanded by populations, as long as effectiveness levels are maintained sufficient to keep populations willing to grant legitimacy to democratic styles which balance crime control with justice. In the end, the greater threat to democratic policing is not militarization but the politicization of policing even in democratic countries, of which militarization is only one piece of evidence, and the increasing closure of the police to public knowledge and oversight linked to an increasing disregard for the rights of people and due process. Related Entries ▶ Conceptualizing of Police ▶ Democratic Policing ▶ Policing of Peacekeeping Recommended Reading and References Andreas P (2009) Border games: Policing the U.S.-Mexico divide, 2nd edn. Cornell University Press, Cornell Bayley DH (1985) Patterns of policing. A comparative international analysis. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick Bayley DH, Perito R (2010) The police in war. Fighting insurgency, terrorism, and violent crime. Lynne Rienner, Boulder Brodeur JP (1983) High policing and low policing: Remarks on the policing of political activities. Soc Probl 30:507–520 Brodeur JP (2000) Cops and spooks: the uneasy partnership. Police Pr Res 1:299–321 Brogden M (1987) The emergence of the police – the colonial dimension. Brit J Criminol 27:4–14 Bryden A, H€anggi H (eds) (2004) Reform and reconstruction of the security sector, Baden-Baden. Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, Germany Police Corruption Caparini M, Marenin O (eds) (2006) Borders and security governance. Managing borders in a globalised world. LIT Verlag, Vienna Della Porta D, Reiter H (eds) (1998) Policing protest. The control of mass demonstrations in western democracies. The University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis den Boer M, Janssens J, Vander Beken T, Easton M, Moelker R (2010) Epilogue. Concluding notes on the convergence between military and police roles. In: Easton M, den Boer M, Janssens J, Moelker R, Vander Beken T (eds) Blurring military and police roles. Eleven International, The Hague, pp 223–228 Dunn TJ (1996) The militarization of the U.S.-Mexico border, 1972–1992. Texas University Press, Austin Easton M, den Boer M, Janssens J, Moelker R, Vander Beken T (eds) (2010) Blurring military and police roles. Eleven International, The Hague Friesendorf C (2010) The military and law enforcement in peace operations. Lessons from Bosnia-Herzegovina and Kosovo. Geneva Centre for the Democratic Control of Armed Forces, Geneva Friesendorf C, Kempel J (2011) Militarized versus civilian policing: problems of reforming the Afghan national police. Peace Research Institute, Frankfurt (PRIF Report No. 102) Goldsmith A, Harris V (2010) Police-military cooperation in foreign interventions: Timor-Leste and the Solomon islands. In: Lemieux F (ed) International police cooperation. Emerging issues, theory and practice. Willan, Cullompton, pp 221–237 Greener B (2009) The new international policing. Palgrave Macmillan, New York Huggins MK (1987) U.S.-supported state terror: a history of police training in Latin America. Crime Soc Justice 2728:149–171 Husain S (2007) Those who die in war are not innocent (‘Na Guerra, quem morre Na˜o E´ innocente): human rights implementation, policing, and public security in Rio de Janeiro. Rozenberg, Brazil/Amsterdam Integrated Border Enforcement Teams (IBETs). http:// www.rcmp-grc.gc.ca/ibet-eipf/index-eng.htm Kaldor M (2001) New & old wars. Organized violence in a global era. Stanford University Press, Stanford Kraska PB (1997) The military as drug police. Exercising the ideology of war. In: Gaines LK, Kraska PB (eds) Drugs, crime, and justice. Contemporary perspectives. Waveland, Prospect Heights, pp 297–320 Kraska PB (ed) (2001) The militarizing of the American justice system. The changing roles of the armed forces and the police. Northeastern University Press, Boston Kraska P (2007) Militarization and policing – its relevance to 21st century police. Policing 1:501–513 Kraska P, Kappeller VE (1997) Militarizing American police: the rise and normalization of paramilitary units. Soc Probl 44:1–18 Moelker R (2010) Cultures converging upon constabularization. In: Easton M, den Boer M, Janssens J, Moelker R, Vander Beken T (eds) Blurring military 3567 P and police roles. Eleven International, The Hague, pp 151–169 Oakley RB, Dziedciz MJ, Goldberg EM (eds) (1998) Policing the new world disorder: Peace operations and public security. National Defense University Press, Washington, DC OECD (Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development) (2007) OECD handbook on security system reform. Supporting security and justice, 2007 Edition. OECD Publishing, Paris. www.oecd.org/ dataoecd/43/25/38406485.PDF OSCE (Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe) (2006) Guidebook on democratic policing. Author: Vienna Perito RM (2011) The Iraq federal police. U.S. police building under fire. Washington, DC, United States Institute of Peace, Special Report 29x Tilly C (1990) Coercion, capital and European states, AD 990–1990. B. Blackwell, Cambridge, MA Verma A (2011) The new khaki. The evolving nature of policing in India. CRC Press, New York Police Corruption Sanja Kutnjak Ivkovic´ School of Criminal Justice, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI, USA Overview Police corruption is a form of police misconduct or police deviance typically defined through the motivation to achieve personal gain. Police corruption includes many heterogeneous forms of behavior that could be classified on the basis of several criteria, including the motivation for corruption (i.e., economic corruption v. noble-cause corruption), regularity of payments (i.e., pads v. scores), consequences (i.e., distortive v. non-distortive corruption), and the level of aggressiveness (i.e., grass-eaters v. meat-eaters). Barker and Roebuck developed a typology of police corruption which recognizes corruption of authority, kickbacks, opportunistic theft, shakedowns, protection of illegal activities, the fix, direct criminal activities, and internal payoffs. Punch added flaking (i.e., planting of evidence) or padding (i.e., supplementing of evidence) as the ninth type of corruption. P P 3568 Theories explaining the causes of police corruption could be classified into four larger groups: (1) theories oriented toward individual police officers and their characteristics (i.e., “individualistic theory” or “rotten apple theory”), (2) theories examining the relation between opportunities for corruption and police corruption (“occupational theories”), (3) theories focusing on the relation between the characteristics of a specific police agency and police corruption (“organizational theories”), and (4) theories concerning the relation between the society at large and police corruption (“social structure theories”). Despite the existence of extensive literature on the theories of police corruption, research that tests the theories is very limited. Police corruption could be measured using several different methodologies. A relatively simple, yet very inaccurate way of measuring corruption is through the official data such as the arrest rates, complaint rates, and conviction rates. Somewhat more promising attempts to assess the actual level of corruption are public opinion surveys, police officer surveys, field studies, and investigations by independent commissions. Police Corruption Definition Police corruption is a form of police misconduct or police deviance typically defined through the motivation to achieve personal gain (e.g., Barker and Carter 1986; Goldstein 1975; Klockars et al. 2000; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2005; Sherman 1974). The definition contains several essential elements. First, corrupt behavior could be defined as a violation of the penal codes, administrative agency rules, or the codes of ethics. Like other citizens, police officers could violate norms of federal and state criminal codes. In addition, federal and state codes establish certain crimes which only public officials can commit (e.g., bribery of public officials and witnesses, Title 18 of the U.S. Code, Chapter 11, Section 201, 1999; extortion by public officials, Police Corruption Title 18 of the U.S. Code, Section 872, 1999; deprivation of civil rights, Title 18 of the U.S. Code, Section 242, 1999). Police agencies, particularly large municipal agencies, have administrative rules and policies compiled in the standard operating procedure manuals. These administrative rules channel the use of discretion, describe appropriate conduct of police officers, prohibit inappropriate conduct, instruct officers to complete written reports after critical incidents, and require supervisory oversight (see, e.g., National Research Council 2004). Even in the agencies with extensive rules, the rules could be ambiguous or fail to regulate certain aspects of corruption. Lastly, the International Association of the Chiefs of Police has developed the code of ethics for the US police officers, which explicitly asks of police officers to promise that they would not engage in corruption, bribery, or gratuities themselves nor condone such conduct by their fellow police officers. Second, while corruption is typically viewed as corrupt behavior (thus suggesting that something is being actively done), corruption can include both active (i.e., act) and passive (e.g., omission) forms. A police officer who fixes a felony ticket in exchange for a bribe provides an example of an action, while a police officer who does not write a ticket in exchange for a bribe from a motorist caught speeding provides an example of omission. Third, various definitions discuss the gain resulting from corrupt activities in terms of explicit personal gain (e.g., Goldstein 1975; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2005; Moore 1997) or implied personal gain (i.e., the definition rests on the idea that the money/goods from the corrupt act are to be consumed by the individual officers; e.g., Barker and Wells 1981; Roebuck and Barker 1974). Several authors (e.g., Bracey 1995; Carter 1990) included organizational gain in their definitions as well. The goal typically has a monetary value; it typically involves “some tangible object, either cash, services, or goods that have cash value” (Barker 1996, p. 25). However, it is also possible that the gain is nonmonetary. While monetary value could usually be attached to, or calculated Police Corruption for, most of the items, in some instances it is difficult, or borderline impossible, to determine it. For example, fixing a speeding ticket for a sergeant’s niece could have different price tags attached to it, depending on the extent of sergeant’s gratitude and the ways in which he is ready and willing to express them. It can potentially lead to preferential treatment by the sergeant and the early promotion, thus yielding thousands of dollars in gain. The size of the gain may be an important factor. The discussion in the literature about the minimum amount, that is, the amount below which the gifts of this value would not be considered as corruption, is intense. The Code of Ethics is explicit in prohibiting the acceptance of gratuities (“. . .never accepting gratuities”; 2011). Although the value of these gratuities may be small in each individual case, if such gifts are given on a regular basis (e.g., Ruiz and Bono 2004) and/or to a large number of police officers (e.g., Pennsylvania Crime Commission 1974), their total value vastly increases their individual value. Furthermore, the purpose of the gratuities may be to influence the police officers’ decisions, as was illustrated on the examples uncovered by independent commissions (e.g., Knapp Commission 1972; Mollen Commission 1994; Pennsylvania Crime Commission 1974). Barker and Wells (1981, p. 11–12) argue: Police corruption for many officers often begins with the shared belief among the police peer group that “policemen have a right to a break,” and the progression along the continuum of corruption is often so gradual that an officer is deeply involved before he realizes it. The acceptance of gratuities could start “the slippery slope of corruption,” leading from the less serious forms of corruption toward the more serious ones; “. . . [i]t is claimed that the acceptance of small gratuities such as free cups of coffee by police officers will increase the likelihood of, or lead by degrees to, or is not significantly different from, corruption of the worst kind (Kleinig 1996, p. 174). There are several steps in the process of “becoming bent,” as Sherman describes it (1985), from the acceptance of minor “perks” and free drinks to regular 3569 P payoffs and the involvement in the distribution and use of narcotics. As Michael Dowd (a former NYPD police officer who stole money and drugs, participated in larger drug rings, became a drug dealer, and was eventually caught, tried, and sentenced to 14 years in prison) emphasized in his testimony before the Mollen Commission, he would test the new officers with initial temptations which were but trivial violations of the NYPD’s policy (Mollen Commission 1994). Once the officers crossed the line between the allowed and the forbidden, it was easier for them to continue and justify to themselves their further involvement in various violations of the Department’s policy. Proponents of the acceptance of gratuities (e.g., Kania 1988, 2004) argue that the acceptance of gratuities contributes toward the development of a friendly bond between the police and the citizens. Kania (1994, p. 2) continues that, although the “cheerful waves, warm greetings and welcome smiles,” and letters of appreciation may result in better service just as likely as may the free drinks, police administrators obviously do not want to discourage such friendly gestures. Typology of Police Corruption Police corruption is a group of heterogeneous activities, from the acceptance of a bribe for not issuing a speeding ticket to leaking the information about the upcoming raid to the drug dealers. Literature has used several different ways of classifying these diverse activities. Economic v. Noble-Cause Corruption Corruption described in this entry is economic corruption or material-reward corruption. Its primary motivation is the material reward, be it in the form of money or other goods and/or services. Noble-cause corruption is different; it is defined as “corruption in the name of the moral rightness of good ends” (Crank and Caldero 2000, p. 5). When police officers behave in a manner consistent with noble-cause corruption, their actions are no longer regulated by the law; instead, they “act if they are the law” (Crank and Caldero 2000, p. 75). Police officers attempt to P P 3570 rationalize this “noble-cause corruption” as follows (Moore 1997, p. 63): I did something wrong, but justice demanded it, not tolerated it but demanded it, because I could put the guy away who otherwise wouldn’t be successfully prosecuted. I, the police officer, wouldn’t gain personally from it; I didn’t get anything from it. I only acted for the community in the community sense of justice to accomplish this goal. The relation between the police and the law changes in the case of noble-cause corruption (e.g., Crank and Caldero 2000). Police officers violate the law to achieve higher purposes or ends of policing. The causes of economic corruption and noble-cause corruption are different, as are the efforts used to control them. Pads v. Scores In terms of the regularity of the payments, corrupt activities could be divided into “pads” and “scores.” If the payment takes place just once, as the opportunity presents itself, it is called a “score.” The Knapp Commission (1972, p. 66) described the “score” as “a one-time payment that an officer might solicit from, for example, a motorist or a narcotics violator. The term is also used as a verb, as in ‘I scored him for $1,500.’” On the other hand, if there is an established arrangement between a citizen and a police officer and the payments occurs on a regular basis, they are called “pads.” The Knapp Commission (1972, p. 66) described “pads” as “regular weekly, biweekly, or monthly payments, usually picked up by a police bagman and divided among fellow officers. Those who make such payments as well as policemen who receive them are referred to as being ‘on the pad.’” Distortive v. Non-distortive Corruption This classification focuses on the outcome of the police officer-citizen interaction. If, compared to the interaction without corruption, the outcome of the interaction with corruption is different, then such corruption is called “distortive corruption.” For example, a police officer stops a motorist for speeding and wants to write a speeding ticket. If the citizen does not offer a bribe, the police officer will write the ticket. Police Corruption If, on the other hand, the citizen offers a bribe and the police officer accepts it, the police officer will not write the ticket. Thus, the outcome of the interaction (i.e., ticket v. no ticket) is different, depending on whether the bribe was offered and accepted. In cases of distortive corruption, the police officer does something that he was not supposed to do (e.g., revealed an undercover operation to a drug dealer, issued a permit to a nonqualified applicant) and does not do something he was supposed to do (e.g., did not arrest a citizen caught violating the law, did not issue a license to a qualified applicant). If the outcome of the interaction is the same, regardless of whether the bribe was given or not, then such corruption is called “non-distortive corruption.” For example, a police officer issues a passport or a liquor license to a qualified applicant. The police officer does what he is supposed to be doing or does not do something that he is not supposed to be doing. The reason for the bribe is that the citizen wants to secure something that he has a legal right to but may need to speed up the bureaucratic machine (hence the “grease money” term used for this type of corruption). Grass-Eaters v. Meat-Eaters According to the Knapp Commission (1972, p. 4, 65), dishonest, corrupt police officers can be classified as either “grass-eaters” or “meat-eaters.” “Meat-eaters” are police officers who aggressively misuse their police power for personal gains, while “grass-eaters” simply accept the payoffs the circumstances of police work throw their way (Knapp Commission 1972, p. 4). A police officer like Michael Dowd who beats up drug dealers and steals their money and drugs (e.g., Mollen Commission 1994) would be a clear example of a “meat-eater.” A police officer who is on the pad and who accepts the money that the bagman is giving him every 1st of the month (see, e.g., Knapp Commission 1972) would be an example of a “grass-eater.” A strong support of the code of silence and reluctance of honest police officers to report their corrupt colleagues, on the one hand, and an aggressive misuse of police powers by “meat-eaters,” on the other hand, provide an Police Corruption atmosphere in which it is very easy and natural for “grass-eaters” to accept payoffs. The Knapp Commission (1972, p. 65) suggested that “grass-eaters” continued to accept the gain from corrupt activities out of their feeling of loyalty to their fellow officers and that the “grass-eaters” are “the heart of the problem” since “[t]heir great numbers tend to make corruption ‘respectable’” (Knapp Commission 1972, p. 4). According to the Knapp Commission (1972, p. 65), unlike “meat-eaters,” “grass-eaters” are not willing to take considerable risks in order to obtain illegal gains, and their behavior is considerably more likely to be affected by a change of atmosphere/ attitudes in the department. Barker and Roebuck’s Typology The most frequently used typology of police corruption has been developed by Barker and Roebuck (1973; Roebuck and Barker 1974). In their joint work, Barker and Roebuck (1973; Roebuck and Barker 1974) point out that corruption takes many forms. Based on several dimensions (e.g., acts and actors involved, norms violated, support from peer group, organizational degree, police department’s reaction), they specify eight types of corruption: corruption of authority, kickbacks, opportunistic thefts, shakedowns, protection of illegal activity, the fix, illegal criminal activity, and internal payoffs. The first type involves cases of corruption of authority. Barker and Roebuck (1973, p. 21) describe it along the following lines: “the officer’s authority is corrupted when he receives officially unauthorized, unearned material gain by virtue of his position as a police officer without violating the law per se.” Thus, the actions are not violations of criminal law, but they do violate departmental policies. Examples of such activity would include acceptance of free drinks, free food, discounts on merchandise, or providing property protection for a fee. According to the findings of the Knapp Commission (1972) and Barker and Roebuck’s study (1973, pp. 22–23), the practice seemed to be widespread (31 % of the businessman in a study openly acknowledged providing favors to the police), and the corruptors, typically respectable citizens, according to 3571 P Barker and Roebuck, give these gifts for a reason. Police officers perceive these gratuities as informal rewards and approve of and support them within the peer group; police officers who refuse such gifts are perceived by their fellow officers as deviant. The second type of police corruption involves kickbacks. They are defined as the acceptance of goods, services, or money for referring business to various businesses and service providers, including towing companies, ambulances, garages, lawyers, and doctors (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 24). These activities do not violate criminal laws, but they do violate departmental policies. According to Barker and Roebuck (1973, pp. 24–25), the corruptors are legitimate businessmen and professionals whose purpose is to develop and maintain a good working relationship with the police. These payments are perceived by police officers as clean and are, therefore, supported by the peer group (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 25), whereas the departments typically either condone or overlook these kickbacks, provided that they are made by legitimate businesses discreetly. In the case of goods and services, the department’s reaction ranges from acceptance to mild sanctions, with cash rewards resulting in a more severe punishment. The third type of police corruption involves opportunistic theft from arrestees, victims, crime scenes, and unprotected property (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 26). These behaviors violate both the departmental rules and the criminal rules. The disciplinary measures vary from mild to very serious (including criminal charges and dismissal). The fourth type of police corruption involves shakedowns. Shakedowns occur upon the police officer’s discovery of both the criminal violation and the violator, and they result in the police officer’s acceptance of a bribe in exchange for not making an arrest (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 27). One of the characteristics of shakedowns is that the victim is rather unlikely to complain, because the victim and the police officer could be found guilty of another crime – bribery. These actions are, of course, violations of both the departmental rules and the criminal codes. P P 3572 The peer culture and the department itself may react differently to the “clean” money than to the “dirty” money, which are distinguished by the source of the money. Officers who are publicly exposed receive severe punishment, including potentially dismissal, and may face a criminal prosecution (Barker and Roebuck 1973, pp. 28–29). The fifth type of police corruption involves protection of illegal activities. Individuals involved in illegal activities reward police officers in order to be able to operate without police harassment (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 29). The corruptors may be citizens with long criminal records, as well as legitimate businesses operating illegally. Some of the activities protect the illegal services and goods which citizens desire or perceive as necessary. This form of police corruption involves a high degree of organization; police members must be coordinated and know which places enjoy police protection. Departmental reaction depends on the “degree of its own involvement with criminal organizations or legitimate businesses that operate illegally, informal definition of clean money, identity of the corruptor, and whether or not there is public disclosure of flagrant violations” (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 33). The sixth type of police corruption involves the fix. The fix may include “the quashing of prosecution proceedings following the offender’s arrest and . . .the taking up (disposal of record) of traffic tickets” (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 34). The corruptors are arrestees who want to avoid the court action in their case, and the police officer involved typically “fails to request prosecution, tampers with the existing evidence, or gives perjured testimony” (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 34). The peer approval depends on whether the case to be fixed is a felony, misdemeanor, or a traffic case. Departmental reaction to the fixing of criminal cases is generally severe (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 35). The seventh type of police corruption is the police officers’ involvement in direct criminal activities. Barker and Roebuck (1973, pp. 35–36) argued that “policemen directly commit crimes against the person or property of another for Police Corruption material gain, acts which are clear violation of both departmental and criminal norms.” Because the profit coming from this transaction is perceived to be “dirty” money, the fellow police officers would typically provide very little support for this type of police corruption and even the departments that may tolerate other forms of police corruption, will react severely by firing the police officers and pressing criminal charges (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 36). Some organization is typically required for this type of police corruption to be carried out, and it involves small groups of police officers. The last, eighth type of police corruption involves internal payoffs. In the case of internal payoffs, both the corruptors and the corrupted are police officers who sell or buy assignments, offdays, holidays, promotions, etc. (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 36). Peer groups either do not support this type of police corruption or perceive it as necessary and inevitable if they are engaged in other forms of police corruption (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 37). In the departments in which other forms of police corruption flourish, this form exists as well and is highly organized. Possible reactions by the departments may range from informal approval to dismissal and pressing criminal charges (Barker and Roebuck 1973, p. 38). Punch (1985) added flaking (i.e., planting of evidence) or padding (i.e., supplementing of evidence) as the ninth type of corruption. According to Punch (1985), this type of corruption is particularly evident in drug-related cases. In a nationwide study of more than 3,000 police officers from 30 diverse US police agencies, Klockars and colleagues (2000) found that shakedowns and opportunistic thefts were evaluated to be the most serious types of corruption in all 30 agencies, while the acceptance of gratuities – be it on a regular basis or only for the holidays – was viewed as the least serious form of corruption in all 30 agencies, with the cases of internal corruption and kickbacks lying somewhere between these two extremes. These results are very consistent with results of surveys of police officers from 13 other countries as diverse as Croatia, Finland, Japan, Pakistan, and South Africa (Klockars et al. 2004). Police Corruption Causes of Police Corruption The National Research Council (2004, p. 271) points out that “[t]he research literature [on causes of police corruption] is long on theory and short on evidence about what causes police corruption.” The existing literature proposes several different approaches toward understanding why police officers engage in corrupt behavior, ranging from police officer individual characteristics to characteristics of the police agency itself and its larger social environment. The first group of studies focuses on individual police officers and their characteristics (e.g., Muir 1977). The literature in this area tries to ascertain the features which make police officers prone to corruption, such as their prior criminal record and weak moral values. The Knapp Commission (1972) called this the “rotten apple approach.” Over time, scholars discovered that psychological screening tests, traditionally used to prevent future “rotten apples” from entering the police organization, are not accurate predictors of future behavior. The second group of studies examines the relation between opportunities for corruption and police corruption. By its nature, policing is viewed as an occupation rife with opportunities for corruption (Klockars et al. 2000). Crank and Caldero (2000, p. 63) provide an example: When we think of police corruption, graft typically comes to mind. The police, in their day-to-day pursuits, are exposed to great temptations, and there are few observers to watch what they do. Imagine this. You’re a street officer. You’ve just made an incredible drug bust. Your reputation in the department is assured, and you’re feeling charged! There’s a pile of money on the floor. All you have to do is reach down, scoop up a handful, and put it in your pocket, and you can put your kid through college. The opportunities for corruption vary assignments, ranks, units, and police agencies. Detectives, particularly those assigned to narcotic units, have especially extensive opportunities for corruption (General Accounting Office 1998), as do police officers in charge of laws without moral consensus and vague-defined laws (Knapp Commission 1972). 3573 P The third group of studies analyzes the relation between the characteristics of a specific police agency (“rotten barrels” or “rotten orchards,” Punch 2009) and police corruption. This approach argues that police agencies have the dominant role in addressing police misconduct by creating systems that establish rules, enforce rules, detect corruption, and control the code of silence (e.g., Klockars et al. 2000; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2005; Sherman 1974; 1978). The police chief and his top administrators have critical roles (e.g., Goldstein 1975; Knapp Commission 1972; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2005; Pennsylvania Crime Commission 1974), while the roles of first-line supervisors (e.g., Knapp Commission 1972; Mollen Commission 1994) and peers (e.g., Chen 2003; Klitgaard 1988; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2005; Stoddard 1974) are not negligible either. The fourth group of studies examines the relation between the society at large and police corruption. The police agency is part of the larger environment and is influenced by the legal norms (e.g., Knapp Commission 1972) and public expectations (e.g., Goldstein 1975; Sherman 1977). Sherman (1977) proposed that communities differ greatly in their expectations, from “communities with a more public-regarding ethos” (like Charlotte, North Carolina, Kansas City, Missouri, and Portland, Oregon) to communities with more “private-regarding” (like New York City and New Orleans, Louisiana). The same argument could be used to explain differentiation in corruption rates across the world; in the study of International Crime Victim Surveys, Kutnjak Ivkovic´ (2003, p. 612) reveals that “the countries with the reputation in the international business community of being more corrupt, as indicated by a low score on the 1999 Corruption Perception Index (CPI) . . . appear also to have a higher percentage of the respondents who said that they had been asked to pay a bribe to a police officer last year.” Measuring the Extent of Police Corruption The measurement of the extent of police corruption could be attempted at different levels (Fig. 1). P P 3574 Police Corruption, Fig. 1 The funnel of police corruption and the data collection methods. source: Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003 Police Corruption Offenders sent to prison • Prison records • Court records • Prosecutor’s records Offenders sentenced • Court records • Prosecutor’s records Offenders prosecuted • Prosecutor’s records Offenders referred for prosecution • Prosecutor’s records Offenders known to internal formal system of control in the police agency Actual extent and nature of corruption The data sources seeking to assess the actual level of police corruption include citizen and police officer surveys. The results of citizen surveys portray a heterogeneous picture of the extent of police corruption across the country; in the 1960s, fewer than 2 % of Caucasian respondents nationwide perceived that most of the police were corrupt (President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice 1067b), in contrast to 93 % of New Yorkers in the 1990s who perceived corruption to be widespread (Kraus 1994). The public opinion surveys indicate that, on the one hand, the public tends to have a relatively positive opinion about police honesty, while, on the other hand, the public perceives that police officers frequently engage in corruption. A 1987 survey of Philadelphia citizens (Moore 1997, p. 62) revealed that the public provided very positive ratings of the police service, although one-third of the respondents thought that police officers often took bribes. Similarly, a 1994 • Complaints • Disciplinary records • Surveys: police officers, payers, citizens, experts • Observations • Interviews • Case studies • Investigations survey of New York citizens showed that, while 93 % of the surveyed citizens perceived that corruption is either “widespread” or “limited,” about one-half of these same citizens estimated that the police are doing a “good” or an “excellent” job (Kraus 1994). On the comparative front, the International Crime Victimization Survey asked the respondents whether they have paid a bribe and, if so, who the recipient of the bribe was. About one percent of the respondents or fewer from Western democracies, including the USA, reported paying a bribe to the police, while the corresponding percentages were dramatically higher (between 10 % and 20 %) in some East European, Asian, and Latin American countries (Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003). In addition, the Gallup International 50th Anniversary Survey (1996) reports that approximately one-third of the respondents in the West European countries and Israel, and more than two-thirds of the respondents in the East European countries, the Far Eastern countries, and the Police Corruption Central and South American countries assessed that police corruption was widespread in their countries. According to the results of the police officer surveys, it seems that the perceived frequency of occurrence of corruption was negatively related to perceived severity of corruption. In the 1994 Illinois study (Martin 1994, p. 33), fewer than 0.4 % of the respondents said that they saw a police officer accepting a bribe, stealing property, or purchasing stolen merchandise in the past year, while 81 % of the police officers said that they saw a police officer accepting free coffee or food from a restaurant. Similarly, Ohio police officers participating in the 1996 survey (Knowles 1996) reported observing serious types of police corruption (acceptance of a payment to overlook illegal activity, purchase of stolen merchandise for personal use or gain) very infrequently (less than 0.6 % observed it last year; less than 4.7 % observed it during their careers), while they reported observing police officers accepting free coffee or food from restaurants quite frequently (71 % observed it over the course of the last 12 months; 87.3 % observed it during their careers). Surveys of citizens and police officers alike are burdened with the methodological problems (see, e.g., Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003; National Research Council 2004, p. 269). For various reasons, neither police officers nor citizens (participants or potential witnesses) have motives to report a corrupt transaction; in fact, they have motives not to report it (e.g., Klockars et al. 2000; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003; Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2005; Stoddard 1974). In addition, most of the existing surveys focus on one country and are conducted locally, usually with the purpose of surveying the population of a particular city. Another source includes independent commission report. While providing the results of an indepth investigations, these independent commissions are limited because they refer to a specific police agency, time period, and are bound by the resources and powers granted to the commission. The Knapp Commission (1972) and the Pennsylvania Crime Commission (1972) find widespread corruption in the NYPD and Philadelphia Police 3575 P Department, respectively, and the presence of a strong code of silence. In contrast, the Mollen Commission (1994) reports that most police officers in the NYPD are honest but still found pockets of police officers aggressively seeking opportunities to obtain money and drugs. A potential source of information about corruption includes field studies of the police. Typically, they focus on a small number of police agencies and involve a combination of methods (e.g., observation, interviews, analyses of documents). The President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and the Administration of Justice made a push for field studies of the police in the 1960s. Reiss’s study of the police (1971), originating as one of the studies submitted to the President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and the Administration of Justice, also contained the data about the frequency with which police officers engage in police misconduct. The rates of corrupt behavior per 100 police officers, based on the observations by the researchers, self-reports by police officers, and allegations of misconduct by others (calculated from the data provided in Reiss’s study 1971) were 22.8 in City X, 20.5 in City Y, and 15.6 in City Z (see Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003). Another level of measuring corruption is through the official data, be it arrest rates or the complaint rates. At the federal level, there were between 83 and 150 officers convicted annually in the period from 1993 to 1997 (General Accounting Office 1998, p. 11). A comparison of the official data with the reports by independent commission implies that official data may be just the tip of the iceberg. When the Knapp Commission (1972) reported widespread corruption n the NYPD, the prosecutors filed charges in only about 30 cases of corruption annually (Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003). Similar problems could be expected for the police agency’s internal records of corruption complaints. At the same time when the Knapp Commission (1972) discovered widespread corruption in the NYPD, the complaint rate in the NYPD was less than 1 per 100 officers. The most novel approach is to measure the extent of police integrity instead. Developed by P P 3576 Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ (Klockars et al. 2000), it measures the level of police integrity and avoids the methodological problems associated with the direct measurement of police corruption. A study of 30 police agencies (Klockars et al. 2000) revealed that police agencies varied considerably in the contours of their police integrity. Related Entries ▶ Control of Police Misconduct ▶ Law of Police Searches ▶ Law of Police Seizures and the Exercise of Discretion ▶ Law of Police Use of Force ▶ Police and the Excessive Use of Force ▶ Police Culture ▶ Police Discretion and Its Control ▶ Police Integrity ▶ Police Lying and Deception Recommended Reading and References [Mollen Commission] New York City Commission to Investigate Allegations of Police Corruption and the Anti-Corruption Procedures of the Police Department (1994) Commission report. Mollen Commission, New York Barker T, Carter DL (1986) A typology of police deviance. In: Barker T, Carter DL (eds) Police deviance, 3rd edn. Anderson Publishing, Cincinnati Barker T, Roebuck J (1973) An empirical typology of police corruption. Charles C. Thomas Publisher, Springfield Barker T, Wells RO (1981) Police administrators’ attitudes toward the definition and control of police deviance. FBI Law Enforc Bull 51(3):8–16 Bracey DH (1995) Police corruption. In: Bailey WG (ed) The encyclopedia of police science, 2nd edn. Garland, New York, pp 545–549 Carter DL (1990) Drug-related corruption of police officers: a contemporary typology. J Crim Justice 18(2):85–98 Commission to Investigate Allegations of Police Corruption and the City’s Anti-Corruption Procedures (1972) Knapp Commission report on police corruption. G. Braziller, New York Crank JP, Caldero MA (2000) Police ethics: the corruption of noble cause. Anderson Publishing, Cincinnati Gallup International (1996) Gallup international 50th anniversary survey. Unpublished manuscript. On file with the author Police Corruption General Accounting Office (1998) Law enforcement: information on drug-related police corruption. General Accounting Office, Washington, D.C Goldstein H (1975) Police corruption: a perspective on its nature and control. The Police Foundation, Washington, D.C Ivkovic´ SK (2003) To serve and collect: measuring police corruption. J Crim Law Criminol 93(2–3): 593–649 Ivkovic´ SK (2005) Fallen blue knights: controlling police corruption. Oxford University Press, New York Kania RR (1988) Should we tell the police to say ‘Yes’ to gratuities? Crim Justice Ethics 7(2):37–49 Kania RR (1994) Invalidating the ‘Dowd Test’. Ethics Roll Call 2(1):2–4 Kania RR (2004) The ethical acceptability of gratuities: still saying “Yes” after all these years. Crim Justice Ethics 1:54–63 Klitgaard R (1988) Controlling corruption. University of California Press, Berkeley Klockars CB, Ivkovic´ SK, Harver WE, Haberfeld MR (2000) The measurement of police integrity. Research in Brief. U.S. Department of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, National Institute of Justice. Government Printing Office, Washington, DC Klockars CB, Ivkovic´ SK, Haberfeld MR (eds) (2004) The contours of police integrity. Sage, Newbury Park Knowles JJ (1996) The Ohio police behavior study. Office of Criminal Justice Services, Columbia Martin C (1994) Illinois municipal officers’ perceptions of police ethics. Illinois Criminal Justice Information Authority, Statistical Analysis Center, Chicago Moore M (1997) Epilogue, Police integrity: public service with honor. U.S. Department of Justice. Available at https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles/163811.pdf Muir W (1977) Police streetcorner politicians. University of Chicago Press, Chicago National Research Council Committee to Review Research on Police Policy and Practices (2004) Committee on Law and Justice, Division of Behavioral and Social Sciences and Education. In: Skogan W, Frydl K (eds) Fairness and effectiveness in policing: the evidence. The National Academies Press: Washington Pennsylvania Crime Commission (1974) Report on Police corruption and the Quality of Law Enforcement in Philadelphia. Pennsylvania Crime Commission, Saint Davids President’s Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice (1967) Task force report: the police. GPO, Washington, D.C Punch M (1985) Conduct unbecoming. Tavistock, London Punch M (2009) Police corruption: deviance, accountability and reform in policing. Willan Publishing, Portland Reiss AJ Jr (1971) The police and the public. Yale University Press, New Haven Roebuck JB, Barker T (1974) A typology of police corruption. Soc Probl 21:423–437 Sherman LL (1974) Becoming bent: moral careers of corrupt policemen. In: Sherman L (ed) Police corruption. Anchor Press, Garden City Police Culture Sherman LL (1977) Police corruption control. In: Bayley D (ed) Police and society. Sage, Thousand Oaks Sherman LL (1978) Scandal and reform. University of California Press, Berkeley Stoddard ER (1974) A group approach to Blue-Coat crime. In: Sherman LW (ed) Police corruption: a sociological perspective. Anchor Press, Garden City Police Culture Eugene A. Paoline III Department of Criminal Justice, University of Central Florida, Orlando, FL, USA Synonyms Occupational culture; Organizational culture; Police styles; Police subculture Overview The job of a police officer can be both mentally and physically exhausting. As such, officers rely on one another for emotional and physical support. Terms like brotherhood, thin blue line, and blue code of silence are common illustrations of the cultural bond that officers share. Most often connotations of police culture (or police subculture to some) are negative. For example, when officers misuse their coercive power, it is often police culture that gets blamed (for endorsing a no nonsense aggressive approach to dealing with citizens). When organizational reforms, like community policing, are met with officer resistance, the culture is cited as the primary barrier to soft policing innovations brought on by “out of touch” administrators. At the same time, police culture can operate as a powerful positive mechanism in helping officers mutually buffer the various tensions of their job. Unfortunately, a great deal of vagueness comes with the concept of police culture. That is, if you asked people to define and explain it, you are liable to receive 100 different responses from 100 different people. The most popular 3577 P depiction of police culture views it as an occupational phenomenon shared by all police no matter where (or for whom) they work. As such, there is more of a focus on the commonalities across police personnel over the differences. Even among those who endorse the occupational view, there is a great deal of variation in describing the facets of police culture. Cumulatively, this is problematic because it limits our ability to fully understand, and comprehensively research, this important aspect of policing. In illustrating the ways of conceptualizing police culture, consider the occupation of criminal justice professor. Undoubtedly, across the various universities that house professors, there are commonly shared cultural ways of handling the work-related strains created by students as primary clientele (e.g., class size and preparation, advising, grade appeals, plagiarism) and administrative supervisors (e.g., expectations for peerreviewed publications, procuring funded research, service). At the same time, it is reasonable to expect that such demands, and subsequent ways of coping, vary depending on the type of institution where one works (e.g., large researchoriented university versus small private teaching college). Moreover, these strains might be met differently based on the working style of the professor (e.g., pro-research versus proinstructor). Even among criminal justice professors housed within the same institution, concerns and demands might be interpreted differently across the ranks of assistant, associate, and full professor. Relatedly, for those in the upper tiers, cultural variation might also be a function of changing assignments (e.g., research coordinator, departmental chair, associate dean, dean). One’s background (e.g., gender, race, educational experiences) might also work to produce differences in the ways in which criminal justice professors deal with the pressures of their work. If one could effectively tease out the various influences, across these divergent conceptualizations, it would undoubtedly produce a deeper comprehension of criminal justice professor culture(s). A similar approach is taken in this chapter in understanding police culture. P P 3578 The Occupational Culture of Policing: The Monolithic Model The foundation for understanding police occupational culture dates back to the seminal work of William Westley (1970) who, in the 1950s, conducted one of the first sociological studies of policing. In doing so, Westley highlighted important themes of the police occupation. More specifically, he found that the police he studied were a secretive tight-knit group that often faced violence on the streets in performing their duties. In detailing these informal aspects of policing, Westley was painting the first picture of its kind. In essence, the message delivered was that cops believed they have to stick together in their interactions against potentially dangerous and hostile citizens. The other significant contribution to our initial impressions of police culture was the research of Jerome Skolnick (1966), who explained how the occupation actually worked to shape a distinct police personality. Similar to Westley (1970), Skolnick detailed life on the streets for the police officer as a dangerous endeavor, one where officers wield a tremendous amount of authority over citizens. Skolnick also tapped into a third primary feature that helped form the police personality, the need to appear efficient to superiors, which introduced an equally dangerous and hostile work environment – the police organization. Both of these ethnographic accounts of police work highlighted many of the informal aspects of the job while also providing a loosely defined template for scholars in comprehending the occupational culture of police. More specifically, these two studies started the process of thinking about the ways in which police officers collectively cope, via their attitudes, values, and norms, with the strains created by their work – which is precisely what defines an occupational culture (Paoline 2001). Unfortunately, unlike foundational explanations of crime causation that tended to clearly (and parsimoniously) posit sets of interrelated propositions, full accounts of police occupational culture have been as vague as the concept of love. That is, you tend to know it when you see it but can mean different things to Police Culture different people. From a theoretical and empirical standpoint, this can be both confusing and frustrating. The works that followed Westley (1970) and Skolnick (1966) described and analyzed several different components of culture that tapped various dimensions of the street and organizational environments. What was lacking though was a clear comprehension of how these individual elements, that research identified, contributed to an overall understanding of the police culture process. That is, what exact features are police dealing with in their primary work environments that are in need of occupational collectiveness? In addition, what are the so-called collective responses that officers utilize to manage the strains of these environments? Finally, what are the consequences of the strains of the work environments and the coping mechanisms that are used to deal with such concerns? While the elements for such an understanding were present in the volumes of research (e.g., an explanation of police loyalty, the crime fighting mandate, citizen danger), a concise roadmap of these correlates, in explaining exactly what a police culture entails, was not readily existent. The monolithic model of police culture, presented by Paoline (2003), helped clarify these concerns. Paoline’s (2003, p. 201) description of the monolithic occupational culture of policing presents, based on extant research, a way to conceptualize the stressful factors of the work environments that operate to produce collective coping mechanisms and outcomes. In a path-like presentation, he identifies interactions on the street with citizens (i.e., occupational) and those with supervisors in the department (i.e., organizational) as the two primary work environments of the police. As a starting point for understanding what produces the coping mechanisms of the monolithic culture, the occupational street environment is described as dangerous, with the defining mandate to display one’s coercive authority over citizens. The model also details the organizational environment as being characterized by uncertain supervisor scrutiny of police decisions (i.e., watchful and punitive superiors) and role ambiguity whereby officers are expected Police Culture to perform all police functions equally yet really only recognized for crime fighting duties. Both the occupational and organizational environments produce equally intense stress and anxiety that is relieved through the collective coping mechanisms found within the occupational police culture. In illustrating the second principal feature of the monolithic police culture model, Paoline (2003) identifies suspiciousness (in dealing with danger) and maintaining the edge (in properly displaying coercive power) as the primary coping mechanisms that officers employ in handling the strains created on the street with citizens. In terms of dealing with supervisors within the equally hostile organizational environment, the culture prescribes that officers lay low/c.y.a. (from watchful and punitive superiors) and embrace the crime-fighter orientation (in minimizing role ambiguity). These prescriptive coping mechanisms of the police occupational culture are transmitted across officers via a socialization process that begins in the training academy and continues throughout one’s career (Van Maanen 1974). The final stage of the model highlights the consequences of the strains of the work environments and the coping mechanisms prescribed by the culture, which include a socially isolated occupational group that is extremely loyal to one another. Collectively, the work that helped produce this model paints a caricature sketch of police as a socially isolated group that are distrustful and suspicious of their primary clientele, as they continually attempt to maintain the upper hand in utilizing their coercive authority. Moreover, officers approach police work solely in crime fighting terms while laying low from supervisors, choosing to only trust their immediate peers. While this is the dominant portrayal of police culture, other research points to important ways in which the occupational group may be fragmented. Sources of Variation in Police Culture The preceding discussion regarding a police culture rests on the assumption that the strains 3579 P that police face on the streets and within the department are the same across the United States and therefore officers’ responses should be similar as well (Crank 1998). By contrast, there are other lines of research that cast doubt on the notion of homogeneity among police by pointing out important sources of cultural variation and segmentation. Organizations Although often used synonymously, occupational and organization cultures are not the same phenomenon. As opposed to a universally shared set of responses to the internal and external strains of the job (for all police) that make up occupational accounts of culture, organizational cultures represent ways that police deal with specific concerns from the various places where they are housed. A principal difference between occupational and organizational accounts of police culture lies within the locus of influence. Occupational cultures are usually formed and maintained by lower level personnel (Van Maanen and Barley 1984), while organizational cultures are created by upper level management and imposed downward through the ranks (Schein 1992). Irrespective of such nuances, this suggests that police organizations, embedded within the overall occupation, exert cultural influence over police officers. James Q. Wilson’s (1968) seminal study accentuates such points. Wilson’s (1968) examination of organizational culture, which he believed was indicative of a departmental style, was based on research conducted in eight communities. Wilson identified three organizational styles that differed in terms of their priorities toward core role orientations of enforcing the law and maintaining order. The author asserted that it was the top police administrator that defined the given style of the department based on their interpretation of the primary needs of the community being served. According to Wilson (1968), some departments are situated within urban environments characterized by greater crime concerns, and thus the agency will embrace more of a formal P P 3580 crime fighting detached approach to police work. In such legalistic style departments, arrests and tickets will be more frequent compared to other organizational styles. By contrast, Wilson’s watchman style departments are more common in low crime rural areas, focusing primarily on maintaining public order. Watchman style departments are less likely to formally respond to citizen transgressions unless they are serious in nature. Wilson asserted that the relational distance between the police and the public in watchman areas would be much smaller than that found in legalistic style departments. Finally, service style departments are described by Wilson as those where law enforcement and order maintenance is not an overall priority, but would be handled as needed. These departments focus on providing assistance and are more likely to be situated in suburban areas with less crime and disorder. Wilson explained that service style departments are closely connected with citizens, choosing to intervene frequently (when needed) but not formally (i.e., arrests and tickets). Wilson’s (1968) research suggests that organizational environments vary, and as such, it highlights the fact that individual police responses to different work conditions might also vary. Interestingly, the legalistic style department he identified comports closely to the organizational environment found in explanations of the monolithic occupational culture. By contrast, the watchman and service style organizational environments represent vastly different internal work arenas where intense supervisor scrutiny and role ambiguity (noted in the occupational account) would be much less common. Likewise, Wilson’s work also points out rather stark variation in the occupational/street environments, as watchman and service style areas are not characterized as overly hostile and crime ridden. As such, cumulative coping mechanisms where officers are suspicious of (and maintain the edge over) citizens, strictly endorsing the crime-fighter image, while covering their ass from supervisors might be functional in a legalistic style department but certainly would be out of place (and probably not tolerated) in both watchman and service style agencies. Police Culture Recent empirical inquiries have provided additional support for the ways in which policing functions and philosophies differ across organizations embedded in urban, rural, and suburban contexts (Crank 1990; Liederbach 2005). This line of research casts doubt on occupational accounts of culture that suggest that all organizations are the same while also acknowledging that management can impact police culture. Rank Occupational accounts of police culture focus heavily on the homogeneity of officers’ attitudes, values, and norms. The socialization process transmits the culture across occupational members and is often described as intense, especially for new personnel (Van Maanen 1974). Because all police at some point in their career are assigned to patrol functions, the supposition is that culture originates at the lower ranks. This is understandable given that patrol officers are those most likely to deal with citizens on the streets and with supervisors in the department. What is much less clear is the role that culture plays in officers’ lives once they move beyond entry level positions. Does the occupational culture still buffer the strains of the work environments for sergeants, lieutenants, captains, majors, deputy chiefs, and chiefs the same way(s) that it did when these officers were assigned to patrol, or does culture change by rank? The works of Reuss-Ianni (1983) and Manning (1994) help answer such questions. Reuss-Ianni (1983), based on research conducted in the NYPD, asserts that there are two distinct cultures in policing. The street cop culture, which Reuss-Ianni delineates in a series of codes, concentrates on the “here and now” in policing and embodies many of the values outlined previously as part of the police occupational culture. Street cops are found at the patrol level and tend to rely on their developed craft, as well as their loyal peers, in surviving on the street and controlling crime at the local level (i.e., beat and precinct). By contrast, management cop culture focuses on city-wide long-term concerns (e.g., crime control, citizen responsiveness, organizational efficiency), taking into account Police Culture political, social, and economic factors. Importantly, Reuss-Ianni believes that temporal changes in the dynamics of policing (e.g., officer composition, resource competition, accountability concerns) have contributed to a weakening of the street cop culture of the “good old days” when organizational leaders could still utilize the codes of the street in running police departments. The importance of Reuss-Ianni’s (1983) work lies in her recognition that rank contributes to differences in police culture. This makes sense given that duties and concerns do change as one moves upward from patrol with the organization. This might also help explain some of the tension noted between officers and their supervisors in the occupational account of police culture. While it is clear that street cop culture originates and protects occupational members at the patrol level, the author fails to inform the reader exactly when police enter management cop culture. That is, it is easy to deduce that top commanders are embedded in the management cop culture, but what about ranks like sergeants and lieutenants (i.e., middle managers), who are in organizational limbo between the very bottom and the very top. Manning’s (1994) work helps alleviate such concerns. Manning (1994) agrees that police culture is hierarchically segmented, although he differentiates rank in a three-tiered manner based on a series of themes and meta-themes. At the first tier are lower participants (i.e., patrol and street sergeants) whose culture, like Reuss-Ianni’s (1983) street cops, focuses on the immediate aspects of “real” police work. The author’s second tier of culture focuses on middle management (i.e., some sergeants up to department brass) who emphasizes supervisory control but also concentrates heavily on buffering concerns of line members of the street (i.e., the first tier) and top police officials (i.e., the third tier). Finally, top command culture (i.e., commanders, superintendents, deputy chiefs, chiefs) represents the third tier. Here, there is a concentration on dealing with the politics of running a police department internally while also buffering the organization from external audiences. Interestingly, in terms of middle managers, Manning (1994) points out that sergeants 3581 P assigned to street functions can rest within the first tier (i.e., lower participant culture), while middle managers with other responsibilities beyond patrol may be part of the second tier. Here, the author allows for behavioral freedom for sergeants who, as supervisors, might still align more with the line level versus management. Although not addressed by Manning, the same argument can be made for first tier lower participants, who depending on their assignment (or aspirations) might differentially align with police culture(s). For example, those who have jobs with duties that are based on more traditional aggressive crime fighting mandates (e.g., criminal investigations, tactical, K-9, anti-street crimes, SWAT, emergency response units) might be more apt to orient themselves with the lower participant culture. By contrast, those in positions that focus more on long-term solutions to controlling crime with increased officer participation (e.g., crime prevention, community outreach, school resource, community policing, victim advocate, homeland security, tourism units) might orient themselves more like upper ranking officials. Both Reuss-Ianni (1983) and Manning (1994) highlight the dynamic nature of police culture as changing and adapting to insulate group members’ issues and concerns unique to their position in the organizational hierarchy. As such, their work suggests that police culture is not monolithic, but instead comprised of multiple cultures based on rank. Style Yet another way that police culture can be segmented is by the style of the officer. In a series of studies published in the 1970s, researchers constructed typologies of the police based on their orientations toward various features of their occupational/street and organizational environments (Broderick 1977; Brown 1988; Muir 1977; White 1972). Of interest is the fact that these researchers were utilizing different dimensions to construct their typologies and were working independent of one another across various departments, areas, and time – yet they concluded with almost identical P P 3582 types/styles of officers. This was evidenced by Worden’s (1995) synthesis of American police typology research into five distinct officer styles. Reiner (1985) also summarized typology research, utilizing some of the studies that Worden (1995) included (i.e., Broderick 1977; Muir 1977), although he incorporated work done on British and Canadian police. Interestingly, both authors concluded with very similar syntheses of officer types. Worden (1995) provides a thumbnail sketch of the five primary styles of police officers. Worden’s tough-cop approaches police work in a cynical fashion, often conflicting with citizens and supervisors in their aggressive approach to selectively fighting serious crime. These officers do not want to be bothered with trivial police matters (e.g., maintaining public order or providing service), and they place a premium on their street experience over formal college education. This style of officer would be your stereotypical gruff “cop’s cop” that is often portrayed in television and movies, as one that is not afraid to push (or perhaps even exceed) the limits of police power if deemed necessary. A second style, clean-beat crime-fighter, resembles the tough cop in their cynical approach, strong orientations toward crime fighting, and conflicting relationships with supervisors. What separates this style of officers from the former is their undying pursuit of enforcing all laws, not just the serious ones (in keeping a clean beat), and their belief that police should follow the procedural rules (i.e., not violate citizen rights). Avoiders are described as a cynical group that, as their name implies, avoid as much work as possible. This style of officer has a very narrow approach to police work, as they take “laying low” to extremes. Their orientations toward all aspects of the job are rather detached, as they attempt to just do their time. Problem solvers are those officers with very favorable attitudes toward citizens and the service style of policing. Problem solvers are the group that is least oriented toward crime fighting and aggressive policing tactics. As opposed to traditional ways of handling Police Culture situations, problem solvers focus on outcomes, desiring to see the problems they are called upon to deal with through to their resolution. To many traditional police officers, the approaches endorsed by the problem solver would appear as “soft.” Professionals embody the values of the professional reform movement and are characterized as the most positive of the five policing styles. Officers in this group hold favorable orientations toward all aspects of their street and organizational environments. Professionals are portrayed as the most well-rounded group in terms of performing multiple functions (i.e., broad role orientation) in a manner in which citizens are not treated aggressively and where supervisors are pleased. Police typology research illustrates that there are a variety of ways in which officers cope, via their style, with the demands of their job. Interestingly, Worden’s (1995) tough-cop orientation comports closely to the attitudes and values associated with occupational accounts of culture, as well as Reuss-Ianni’s (1983) street cop culture and Manning’s (1994) lower participant culture. The other four styles summarized by Worden suggest the type of ideological differentiation that forms the basis for occupational subcultures (Van Maanen and Barley 1985). While research has yet to empirically validate these working styles, one thing is clear – there is more than just a single way for officers to deal with the strains of policing. Officer style research illustrated cultural fragmentation among police during a time when officers were relatively demographically homogenous (i.e., White males with a high school education). Changes in the overall composition of police (i.e., more females, non-Whites, and college educated), as well as policing philosophies (i.e., community policing), in recent decades prompted reexaminations of police culture(s) (Paoline et al. 2000). Moreover, recent empirical approaches have utilized advanced statistical classification techniques, such as cluster analysis and discriminant function analysis, to examine more than the two or three attitudinal dimensions that were used for Police Culture previous police typology inquiries (Cochran and Bromley 2003; Jermier et al. 1991; Paoline 2001). Similar to the research that produced evidence of policing styles, studies that utilized quantitative classification schemes also found multiple groups of officers with varying alignment to a single occupational culture. Because much of this (and typology) research is based primarily on officers’ attitudinal orientations, it begs the question as to the applicability of such approaches on explanations of officer behavior. The age old attitude-behavior link has stymied social scientists for decades, as empirical connections have failed to verify intuitive expectations that one’s attitudes affect one’s behavior (Frank and Brandl 1991). Paoline’s (2001) classification scheme provides one of the few exceptions. Paoline (2001) utilized survey data collected as part of the Project on Policing Neighborhoods (POPN) to analyze several prominent attitudinal features of prior police culture research. Paoline identified seven groups of officers with varying cultural orientations. Five of the groups very closely resembled those Worden described in the framework he presented in 1995: tough cops (i.e., traditionalists), clean-beat crime-fighters (i.e., law enforcers), avoiders (i.e., lay lows), problem solvers (i.e., peacekeepers), and professionals (i.e., old pros). The other two officer groups were anti-organizational street cops, who were distinguished in terms of their strong negative views of supervisors and their strong favorable views of citizens, and dirty harry enforcers, who were distinguished in terms of their strong beliefs in aggressively fighting crime and disorder, even if it meant violating the rights of citizens. Although Paoline’s (2001) seven groups were attitudinally and empirically distinguishable from one another, there was no genuine way to rank order them (for comparison purposes) in terms of a continuum of police culture commitment. The groups did provide the author with a conservative manner in which to categorize them in terms of positive orientations toward culture (i.e., pro culture), negative outlooks or antithesis of cultural expectations (i.e., con 3583 P culture), and those that fell somewhere in the middle of the two extremes (i.e., mid culture). Paoline’s trichotomized classification scheme of police has been utilized to empirically examine the connection between cultural attitudes and theoretically related behaviors of citizen searches (Paoline and Terrill 2005) and the use of force (Terrill et al. 2003). In both instances, statistically related differences were noted between officers’ cultural alignment and their behavior. More specifically, those who held attitudes that were strongly congruent with the traditional police culture (i.e., pro culture) or mixed (i.e., mid culture) searched citizens more often during traffic stops and used force more frequently (and at higher levels) than those who ardently resisted cultural attitudes (i.e., con culture). Background Characteristics Besides the organization, rank, and policing style, officer background represents another potential source of cultural variation. As previously mentioned, the foundation for understanding the monolithic occupational account of police culture was built during a time when policing was largely a demographically homogenous occupation (i.e., made up almost exclusively of high school-educated White males). Researchers have detailed the integration struggles and resistance that female (e.g., Martin and Jurik 1996), non-White (e.g., Bolton 2003), and gay/lesbian (e.g., Miller et al. 2003) officers have faced in a male-dominated masculine occupation. To a lesser extent, college-educated officers have been chided for their “book smarts” over the preferred “street smarts,” in learning the craft of policing (Fielding 1988). The idea here is that those with different backgrounds from the modal officer are excluded from the broader occupational culture. As departments continue to diversify their personnel in terms of their individual characteristics (Hassell and Brandl 2009), it is certainly reasonable to expect that these previously excluded policing members will, in some manner, contribute to a less cohesive occupational group. To date, we lack a concrete understanding of how such advancements in officer P P 3584 diversity affect police culture(s). That is, despite qualitative (and detailed case study) accounts of cultural dissociation, background characteristics of police provide limited power in explaining cultural perceptions among police (Paoline et al. 2000). In fact, the impetus for some of the recent officer classification schemes, in revisiting working styles, was built on the notion that diversification of personnel should produce differences in cultural alignment (Paoline 2001). Even among these studies that utilize advanced statistical techniques with larger sample sizes, there is little (if any) systematic connection between officer background characteristics and their group membership. In the end, such work suggests that cultural variation may have little to do with one’s background. The lack of a strong empirical connection between officer characteristics and alignment with police culture(s) could be a function of a couple of factors. It could be that demographic changes that are occurring are still too recent, and thus, we have yet to see the full cultural effects of such transitions in membership. A second explanation could be that the forces of cultural socialization as so strong, as some traditionalists would assert (Van Maanen 1974), that individual differences (via one’s sex, race, education, sexual orientation, etc.) are washed away as officers collectively deal with the strains of the occupation. As such, the primary environments of policing are what shape the culture or subcultural styles, irrespective of what officers bring to the job. Conclusion and Future Research Police culture has been a topic of study for over half a century. Although the monolithic depiction still tends to dominate popular conceptions, this chapter illustrates that police culture is a multidimensional concept that is molded and shaped at various levels (i.e., organization, rank, style, assignment, background). Police scholars, in attempting to understand this police phenomenon, have wrestled with such complexities. At the same time, police culture is not just an academic Police Culture concept, as practitioners recognize its power, vagueness, and malleability. As noted by the Community Relations Service of the United States Department of Justice’s (2002, p. 9) handbook on “Police Use of Excessive Force,” in order to change police culture, “one must analyze and understand the currently existing culture.” While this chapter summarizes many of the advancements in detailing the pathways and contours of police culture, much more work is needed. As Fielding (1988, p. 185) accurately contends “if occupational culture is to serve as an empirically satisfactory concept as well as theoretically necessary one, the sense of its internal variations and textures must be brought out in the same fashion as have conceptions of culture in relation to delinquency.” What follows are a few suggestions for future research inquiries. Ideally one would want a totally comprehensive study, which would require starting at the occupational level and working through differences between and among organizations, ranks, styles, assignments, and backgrounds. Simply put, this may be asking way too much at this point. A more reasonable request starts by considering the various sources of influence on police culture. The monolithic account of the police culture was created based on early ethnographic studies interested in capturing themes across officers. It is not surprising then that cultural similarities were the focus over cultural segmentation. Even if we acknowledge the sources of cultural variation, typology (and recent officer classification scheme) research did find one style of officer that deals with the strains of the primary work environments in the same manner presented by monolithic characterizations. Paoline (2003) presented a model for understanding this monolithic version of culture, and while parts of it have been researched, the entire model has yet to be empirically tested. As a logical starting point, it would be interesting to gather baseline data regarding the extent to which this traditional culture model is endorsed among contemporary police. This is especially salient given that policing philosophies are revisiting more bottom line crime fighting goals (e.g., COMPSTAT) at Police Culture the cost of many community policing initiatives that have permeated agencies for the last 20 years. At the occupational level, we still do not have a firm empirical grip on the things that officers might share versus the exact points where they might be divided. Regarding the influence of the organization, researchers should continue efforts aimed at examining departmental style as it impacts police culture(s). In doing so, empirical work can be done to deduce whether organizational environments, via agency style, are similar or dissimilar from that noted by Wilson (1968). For example, the rural and suburban areas that made up the smaller watchman and service departmental styles might be organized and operating in different ways today as criminogenic forces (e.g., gangs, unincorporated areas for producing and distributing drugs) are not just reserved for legalistic urban areas. As such, the directives and goals espoused as part of today’s watchman and service organizational styles may look more similar to the legalistic style than that noted in the 1960s. With respect to officer styles, efforts should be made to examine the connected (or disjointed) way(s) in which individual level approaches to dealing with the strains of policing operate within organizational level, top command-driven, styles. Jermier et al. (1991) found differences between subcultural groups of officers and the legalistic style crime fighting official organizational culture. This begs the question – what about other departmental styles and potential organizational survival of officer styles? For example, the crime fighting approaches of Worden’s (1995) “tough cop” and “clean-beat crime-fighter” would certainly seem out of place compared to a “problem solver” or “professional” in a service style suburban department, as opposed to a legalistic style organization where the former would be more of a fit than the latter. Regarding rank-related sources of variation, disentangling officer assignment and formal designation within the police hierarchy would be useful in understanding how culture(s) differ across Manning’s (1994) three primary tiers. For example, can lower level participants, with assignments that call for increased officer 3585 P participation and long-term orientations, align more like middle managers and their culture than their own? Conversely, can captains that are assigned to aggressive crime fighting street duties orient themselves more like lower level participants? In addition, do officer styles differ across the three tiers or is the culture monolithic by rank? If policing styles, as proxies for subcultures, develop at the patrol level, how and when do they change as one advances through the organizational hierarchy? In what way(s) do supervisory styles impact the development and maintenance of subordinate styles? These are but a few questions whose answers would add greatly to our police culture knowledge base. Finally, despite the lack of consistent statistical associations, the demographic changes that have occurred in policing should continue to be part of police culture research. In doing so, racial (and ethnic) groups other than dichotomous White and non-White (predominantly comprised of African Americans) classifications should be part of such inquiries (e.g., Hispanic, Asian, Pacific Islander, American Indian, Alaskan Native). As such, previously excluded groups continue to populate police organizations, especially above the patrol level, cultural (and sub cultural) differences might be more visible. The same holds for those with divergent educational backgrounds and sexual orientations that differ from the traditional blue-collar aggressive crime fighting officer depicted in characterizations of the police culture “brotherhood.” Moving beyond descriptive accounts of the struggles of those with divergent backgrounds and focusing on quantitative multivariate modeling will enhance our understanding of the potential independent effects of such factors on police culture(s). The individual pieces of the multidimensional puzzle have been presented here in an attempt to detail the various intricacies of police culture. If scholars, practitioners, and funding agencies are serious about the overall importance of understanding (and possibly changing) police culture, it is high time to devote the empirical effort required to fully comprehend the way(s) in which officers deal with their work environments. P P 3586 Related Entries ▶ Communities and the Police ▶ Community Policing ▶ COMPSTAT ▶ Control of Police Misconduct ▶ History of the Police Profession ▶ Managing Innovation of Policing ▶ Minorities Within the Police Workforce ▶ Police and the Excessive Use of Force ▶ Police Corruption ▶ Police Discretion in Law Enforcement ▶ Police Integrity ▶ Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters ▶ Policing the Police ▶ Role and Function of the Police ▶ Women in Policing Recommended Reading and References Bolton K Jr (2003) Shared perceptions: black officers discuss continuing barriers in policing. Pol Int J Police Strateg Manag 26:386–389 Broderick JJ (1977) Police in a time of change. General Learning Press, Morristown Brown MK (1988) Working the street: police discretion and the dilemmas of reform, 2nd edn. Russell Sage, New York Cochran JK, Bromley ML (2003) The myth(?) of the police sub-culture. Pol Int J Police Strateg Manag 26:88–117 Crank JP (1990) The influence of environmental and organizational factors on police style in urban and rural environments. J Res Crime Del 27:166–189 Crank JP (1998) Understanding police culture. Anderson Publishing, Cincinnati Fielding NG (1988) Joining forces: police training, socialization, and occupation competence. Routledge, London Frank J, Brandl SS (1991) The police attitude-behavior relationship: methodological and conceptual considerations. Am J Police 58:83–103 Hassell KD, Brandl SS (2009) An examination of the workplace experiences of police patrol officers: the role of race, sex, and sexual orientation. Police Q 12:408–430 Jermier JM, Slocum JW Jr, Gaines J (1991) Organizational subcultures in a soft bureaucracy: resistance behind the myth and facade of an official culture. Organ Sci 2:170–194 Liederbach J (2005) Addressing the elephant in the living room: an observational study of the work of suburban police. Pol Int J Police Strateg Manag 28:415–434 Police Culture Manning PK (1994) Police occupational culture: segmentation, politics, and sentiments. Unpublished manuscript, Michigan State University Martin SE, Jurik NC (1996) Doing justice, doing gender. Sage, Thousand Oaks Miller SL, Forest KB, Jurik NC (2003) Diversity in blue: lesbian and gay police officers in a masculine occupation. Men Masc 5:355–385 Muir WK Jr (1977) Police: streetcorner politicians. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Paoline EA III (2001) Rethinking police culture: officers’ occupational attitudes. LFB Publishing, New York Paoline EA III (2003) Taking stock: toward a richer understanding of police culture. J Crim Justice 31:199–214 Paoline EA III, Myers SM, Worden RE (2000) Police culture, individualism, and community policing: evidence from two police departments. Justice Q 17:575–605 Paoline EA III, Terrill W (2005) The impact of police culture on traffic stop searches: an analysis of attitudes and behavior. Pol Int J Police Strateg Manag 28:455–472 Reiner R (1985) The politics of the police. St. Martin’s Press, New York Reuss-Ianni E (1983) Two cultures of policing. Transaction, New Brunswick Schein EH (1992) Organizational culture and leadership. Josey Bass Publishers, San Francisco Skolnick JH (1966) Justice without trial: law enforcement in democratic society. John Wiley, New York Terrill W, Paoline EA III, Manning PK (2003) Police culture and coercion. Criminology 41:1003–1034 U.S. Department of Justice (2002) Police use of excessive force: a conciliation handbook for the police and the community. Community Relations Service, Washington, DC Van Maanen J (1974) Working the street: a developmental view of police behavior. In: Jacob H (ed) The potential for reform of criminal justice. Sage, Beverly Hills, pp 83–130 Van Maanen J, Barley SR (1984) Occupational communities: culture and control in organizations. In: Staw BM, Cummings CC (eds) Research in organizational behavior, vol 6. JAI Press, Greenwich, pp 287–365 Van Maanen J, Barley SR (1985) Cultural organization: fragments of a theory. In: Frost PJ, Moore LF, Louis MR, Lundberg CC, Martin J (eds) Organizational culture. Sage, Beverly Hills, pp 31–53 Westley WA (1970) Violence and the police: a sociological study of law, custom, and morality. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA White SO (1972) A perspective on police professionalization. Law Soc Rev 7:61–85 Wilson JQ (1968) Varieties of police behavior: the management of law and order in eight communities. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Worden RE (1995) Police officers’ belief systems: a framework for analysis. Am J Police XIV:49–81 Police Discretion and Its Control Police Discretion and Its Control Gary Cordner1 and Michael S. Scott2 1 Department of Criminal Justice, Kutztown University, Kutztown, PA, USA 2 Law School, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI, USA Overview Police officers exercise a tremendous amount of discretion in carrying out their functions. That is, they make many choices from a range of possible actions or inactions available to them, and their choices are not specifically prescribed by law, policy, procedure, or rule. This simple notion, which seems self-evident to some and controversial to others, lies at the heart of many issues of policing in democratic societies. That the police do exercise discretion was only recognized and openly acknowledged beginning in the 1960s (J. Goldstein 1960; H. Goldstein 1963; LaFave 1965; Davis 1969). The conventional view prior to that time, and persisting among some long thereafter, was that the police function was entirely a ministerial one: that the police only took actions that were specifically authorized or mandated by legislative bodies. Under this view, policing was understood to be simply a matter of enforcing the laws on the books. But a number of pioneering research studies of policing in action found that the law was silent on many important matters involving police action and ambiguous on others, and police officers did not always adhere to what the law prescribed, even where the law was clear and specific (Banton 1965; Skolnick 1966; Wilson 1968; Westley 1970; Reiss 1971; Brown 1981). The exercise of discretion is nearly inevitable in policing (H. Goldstein 1977). Some laws are practically unenforceable because they are outdated, or widely unpopular, or unconstitutional, or lack enforceable sanctions. Legislatures pass laws, and fail to abolish others, for a variety of purposes, only one of which is to establish clear expectations and guidelines for enforcement 3587 P through police action. Moreover, the police seek to achieve various objectives in carrying out their duties, and at times, those objectives conflict with one another. In such instances, the police must decide which objectives take precedence over others. For example, during a public demonstration held in the streets, the police may find that the objective of keeping traffic avenues clear conflicts with the objective of safeguarding citizens’ rights to peaceful protest. Even absent conflicting objectives, police and other criminal justice resources are far too limited to allow the police to enforce all laws exhaustively. Most communities would not tolerate full enforcement of the law, even if resources would allow it, preferring a degree of police tolerance, especially for minor legal transgressions. The very capacity of the criminal justice system to continue functioning in many communities depends to a great extent on the police not fully enforcing the law. Sudden increases in police arrest activity can seriously challenge the capacity of the legal system to process the resultant cases. Discretion is exercised in policing at all levels of the police hierarchy. In contrast with other occupations and professions, the greatest amount of discretion in policing is exercised at the line level by patrol officers and detectives, but supervisors and policy makers also exercise large amounts of discretion. Fundamentals of Police Discretion Perhaps the most profound types of discretionary decisions made in policing are the decisions to use force and to arrest. In regard to the use of force, Bittner (1970: 46) famously described the core of the police role as “the distribution of nonnegotiably coercive force employed in accordance with the dictates of an intuitive grasp of situational exigencies.” What Bittner meant is that the police are regularly called to the scenes of trouble and sometimes find it on their own. These situations are often confusing, if not chaotic. In these situations, police officers are authorized to use reasonable force, if necessary, in order to quell the P P 3588 trouble. The decision about whether the use of force is necessary, and if so, how much force to use, is discretionary. The decision is made by the officer or officers on the scene, based on their “intuitive grasp” of the circumstances (the “situational exigencies”) as they unfold. Police decisions about whether to arrest are discretionary too. Generally, the police are authorized to arrest (1) with a warrant issued by a court, (2) whenever a person commits any crime in their presence, and (3) whenever they have probable cause to believe that a felony (serious) crime has been committed and that a particular person has committed it, even if the probable cause is based on secondhand or thirdhand information. In regard to warrantless arrests (types 2 and 3 above), which are the most commonplace arrest situations, law and official policy rarely say that the police must arrest. Most often the law says, or is interpreted as meaning, that the police may arrest, leaving discretion in the hands of ordinary police officers. Perhaps the most ubiquitous discretionary situations encountered by the police are the decisions whether to stop drivers who violate traffic laws and, when traffic stops are made, whether to cite the drivers and, further, to search the vehicle for evidence or contraband. Many observed traffic violations are minor in nature (such as driving 1 mile over the speed limit) and therefore frequently ignored by the police or, at most, addressed with a warning. By the same token, poor driving causes many deaths and injuries every year and a huge amount of property loss, so traffic policing, and its associated discretionary decision making, should not be dismissed as a trivial matter. As well, when officers decide to issue citations to drivers, fines are routinely in the hundreds of dollars today and can result in the loss of driving privileges, which in turn can have serious consequences for employment and income. Moreover, the police commonly engage in traffic enforcement as a method of more serious crime control: to locate illegal guns and drugs, to locate persons with outstanding arrest warrants, to disrupt illegal drug and prostitution markets, to deter burglars and thieves from prowling neighborhoods, and so forth. Police Discretion and Its Control There exists some research data about the frequency of these three major discretionary situations – use of force, arrests, and traffic enforcement. Clearly, the police frequently choose not to use force, or have no justification to do so – estimates are that the police use physical force (beyond handcuffing) in only about 20 % of all arrests (Terrill et al. 2008), in only 2–3 % of all encounters with the public (Friedrich 1980), and in less than 1 % of all traffic stops (Eith and Durose 2011). Similarly, the police often choose not to arrest – one study estimated that the police make arrests in about one-half of situations when it would be lawful to do so (Black 1980), and another study found that arrests are made in only 5 % of total police encounters with the public (Whitaker 1982). This still results in a large number of arrests though – 13 million in 2010, of which 2.2 million were for violent or property offenses, 1.6 million for drug offenses, and 1.4 million for drunken driving (FBI 2011). The picture is similar regarding traffic enforcement, with just over half (55 %) of 18 million drivers stopped in 2008 reporting that they were given a citation (Eith and Durose 2011). Beyond use of force, custodial arrests, and traffic citations, the police make many other types of discretionary decisions, including decisions about which laws to invoke when an arrest or other form of detention is made (e.g., whether to add a charge of resisting arrest when an offender does not come along peacefully); whether to refer matters to other agencies; what tactics to adopt in mounting proactive operations; what conduct to investigate, what investigative techniques to apply, and how intrusive those techniques are; what level of resources to commit to various activities, places, and problems; whether to secure prior authorization for certain actions (e.g., whether to apply for search warrants or other court orders); what level of urgency to give to various duties; whether to grant permission for certain activities to take place (e.g., where the police are responsible for issuing parade permits); and so forth. Many of these discretionary decisions are made by patrol officers and detectives, but some are also made by supervisors and commanders. Police Discretion and Its Control Variations in Discretion The range of choices open to police officers varies in different types of situations, as does the degree of latitude that they have in making those choices. So, for example, if an officer is dealing with a person experiencing a mental health crisis, it matters if there is a specialized unit that can respond and take over, or if there is a mental health crisis center to which the person can be taken, or a psychiatric unit within the local hospital. If none of those options is available, then the number of choices open to the officer is more limited – to perhaps not much more than curbside counseling or an arrest for disorderly conduct. In some jurisdictions, while the law may authorize the police to arrest for certain offenses, that option may not really be available. For example, the county jail may be completely full, causing the jail administrator or sheriff to advise local agencies not to make any arrests except in extreme cases. In this situation, police officers may still have the option to issue a citation to an offender, but the option of physical or custodial arrest would be severely curtailed. In another scenario, it is common for prosecutors to inform police departments that, because of heavy caseloads facing the court, arrests should not be made for particular categories of minor offenses. This situation would discourage even the issuance of a citation, unless the accused had the option of paying a fine in lieu of trial, thus preventing any additional workload burden on the court. Another real-world constraint on police discretion is the number of police officers available to handle other police matters should an officer take some action that removes him or her from the streets for an extended period. Whether in small agencies where there is only one police officer on duty or in larger agencies where police reinforcements are a long distance away, an officer might have to weigh the benefits of making an arrest against the costs of being tied up for several hours processing the arrestee, leaving no or few other officers to police the area. Both the public’s and any remaining officers’ safety must be taken into account. An added dimension could be that 3589 P the county jail, hospital, or other facility is many miles away, building even more processing time into the detention and literally taking the officer out of the jurisdiction. These kinds of practical constraints may narrow the real range of choices available to officers when handling various situations, thereby further constraining their discretion. In regard to the use of force, not all police officers and police departments have the same equipment available to them, which can affect their range of options in some situations. For example, conducted energy devices (e.g., Tasers) have become commonplace, but some officers do not have them and thus do not have one of the more effective less-lethal weapon options in confrontations with combative subjects. Similarly, when a high-speed pursuit is underway, the range of options is affected by whether the officers out ahead of the pursued vehicle have stop sticks or similar technology. Likewise, in a hostage or barricaded-person scenario, some police officers might have sophisticated communications, eavesdropping, or breaching technology available, while others might not, affecting the tactical choices open to them. From a comparative perspective, the 18,000 chief police executives in the United States probably have broader discretion than their counterparts in most other countries, because of the highly decentralized structure of American policing. A US police chief has the authority to choose the type of pursuit-driving policy to implement, whether to place a higher priority on drug enforcement or traffic enforcement, whether to require applicants to have a college degree, how to address various types of policing incidents and problems, and so forth. In a country with a unitary (national) police system, these and other decisions are usually made at the national level, leaving much less discretion in the hands of local commanders. Sheriffs in the United States may have the broadest executive-level discretion of all, since they are locally elected and are primarily accountable to the electorate rather than to other government executives. Differing legal systems may also affect police discretion. Within the United States, local and P P 3590 state police officers generally exercise wider discretion than do federal law enforcement officers, whose investigations, in particular, are guided to a larger degree by prosecutors (US attorneys) than is common at the state and local levels. Similarly, in countries that have civil law or inquisitorial legal systems, judges and/or prosecutors often direct investigations, reducing the degree of discretion available to police. In some countries, frontline police personnel (the equivalent of patrol officers in the United States or constables in the UK) do not have the same broad authority or discretion in the use of force, arrest, and investigation described in the previous section. The actual legal authority of ordinary police officers is more restricted, or organizational rules and procedures require them to get permission from superior officers before taking significant actions. Of course, it is also true that in some countries the authority of the police to detain, search, and interrogate is even broader (under the law or simply in practice) than discussed here, effectively increasing the amount of discretion available to those permitted to exercise the authority, whether it is frontline police personnel or superior officers. Factors That Affect Police Use of Discretion An important theme in police research has been the study of police decision making. Besides documenting the existence of discretion, as described above, many studies have looked for patterns and correlations in police decisions to use force, stop vehicles and pedestrians, make arrests, issue citations, and conduct searches. Factors affecting police decision making and the use of discretion by police officers fall into four general categories: situational characteristics, police officer characteristics, police organization characteristics, and neighborhood/jurisdiction characteristics. Consistent with the finding that the police exercise broad discretion and also consistent with Bittner’s (1970) argument that police behavior is guided by “situational exigencies,” characteristics of the situations in which the police Police Discretion and Its Control encounter the public have been found to have the greatest influence on police decisions to arrest, cite, and use force (Skogan and Frydl 2004). Among these, studies have found that the most influential are legal factors – the seriousness of the offense committed by the suspect, the suspect’s previous offending history, the amount of evidence available, and the degree of threat posed by the suspect toward the officer. This finding – that police use of discretion is affected more by legal factors than any others – is reassuring. A related quasi-legal factor that also has some influence is the stated preference of the victim, especially when the victim asks the officer not to arrest the suspect. Compared to these legal factors, a variety of extralegal situational factors have been found to have mixed and inconsistent effects on police use of discretion. These extralegal factors include the demeanor of the suspect and the suspect’s race, sex, and social class. Each of these factors has been found to influence police decision making in some studies, but not always in the same direction, plus many other studies have found no effects. Of these factors, the one that has gotten the most empirical support, especially in more recent studies, is race (Kochel et al. 2011). Studies of so-called racial profiling consistently find that people of color are disproportionately stopped by the police, whether as drivers or as pedestrians, and once stopped are more likely to be searched. The key question, of course, is whether these police decisions to stop and search people of color are made based on the extralegal factor of the race of the person, or whether they are based on legal factors such as the seriousness of the person’s behavior and the amount of evidence that is available. Unfortunately, research on racial profiling has not generally been able to answer that key question. Police decision making and use of discretion might also be influenced by the personal characteristics of the police officer, such as his or her race, sex, and level of education. However, the cumulative findings from many studies indicate that these factors do not have large or consistent effects on police officer behavior. Similarly, neither police officers’ general orientations toward Police Discretion and Its Control their role nor their levels of authoritarianism, cynicism, or job satisfaction have been found to have any consistent influence on their use of discretion. A third set of factors that might affect police officer decision making is organization-level characteristics. For example, officers in small police departments might use their discretion differently than officers in larger departments, officer decision making might vary between different types of agencies (e.g., municipal police departments versus sheriff’s offices), or decision making might be influenced by the degree to which a police organization is centralized, specialized, or formalized. The internal climate or culture of a police organization might also lead to variations in police behavior, including decision making. While a good case can be made that organizational characteristics such as these ought to affect the use of discretion by organization members, the kinds of multiorganization studies that would be needed to verify such effects have simply not been conducted. It has also been argued that police use of discretion varies according to characteristics external to the police, such as between rural, suburban, and urban communities, or between poor neighborhoods and affluent ones. Once again, a theoretical case can be made that community characteristics should influence police behavior, including decision making in discretionary situations, but relatively few studies have been able to incorporate multiple neighborhoods and/or multiple jurisdictions, and the results from those few studies have not been consistent (Varano et al. 2009). As was true for officer characteristics and organizational characteristics, community characteristics have not been found to have as much impact on police officers’ use of discretion as situational characteristics, and within the latter, legal factors seem to have the greatest influence. Consequences of Police Discretion As discussed above, police discretion seems inevitable given the broad mandate of the police, the 3591 P incredible variety of situations that the police encounter, the tendency of legislatures to pass laws that no one expects will be fully enforced, the limited capacity of jails and courts, and numerous other philosophical and practical considerations. So the police have broad discretion, though more in some situations than others. Also as noted, studies indicate that situational legal factors affect police officers’ decisions more than any other factors, although future studies using better methodologies may reveal that extralegal factors (such as the race of the suspect) and the characteristics of police organizations and communities have more influence than can presently be demonstrated. Given the existence of police discretion, what are its consequences? The most obvious immediate result is that the police often choose not to enforce the law, thus softening the impact of the criminal law on people’s lives. With discretion, officers get to choose how to handle various situations, and at least half the time when an arrest could be made or a citation issued, they choose under-enforcement or some other version of leniency. Because of discretion, officers’ actions can be affected by sympathy and empathy, and officers have the opportunity to choose what they consider to be the most fair or just resolution of the situation, even if that entails not enforcing the law. Discretion enables the police to treat people as people, taking into consideration a person’s circumstances, motives, intent, remorse, and promises – many would say that discretion allows the police to humanize the application of the criminal law. This phenomenon of under-enforcement enabled by discretion might be a cause for more serious concern if it reduced the deterrent effect of arrest and punishment, emboldening potential offenders and creating a sense of impunity within society. Such a concern is less warranted though, since the police exercise their discretion mainly in response to minor crimes and disorders. It is generally the person caught drinking in public, driving 10 miles over the speed limit, or shoplifting a small item who benefits from an officer’s decision to handle a matter informally, not the burglar, robber, or murderer. With that P P 3592 said, however, it is also true that detectives and prosecutors have discretion in making “deals” even with serious crime suspects, as when they offer to reduce or drop charges in return for confessions, incriminating evidence or testimony against codefendants, and other types of cooperation. The exercise of discretion by detectives has not been studied as closely as the discretionary arrest and use of force decisions made by patrol officers. Concern about the consequences of underenforcement and leniency cannot be ignored, despite the evidence that the police have been making lots and lots of arrests. “Zero tolerance” campaigns remain very popular, at least in the United States. It is not usually necessary to declare zero tolerance for murder or robbery – rather, zero tolerance campaigns usually target such lesser offenses as street prostitution and panhandling, or else they define a specific geographic area within which all criminal laws will be enforced, no matter how minor. In the public forum and in police strategy circles, zero tolerance is most commonly presented as a strict crime-control policy, leading to debates about whether it is fair, sustainable, and effective in reducing crime. However, zero tolerance is also a direct assault on police discretion. A zero tolerance policy takes discretion away from police officers since it eliminates every option other than enforcement. In light of the concern that police discretion might result in too much leniency, it is ironic to note that, at least in the United States over the last 20 years, jails and prisons have been full, if not overflowing. In other words, the police have had broad discretion, and the evidence indicates that they have regularly used it to avoid making arrests – and yet, court dockets are crowded and jails are full. One might wonder what the situation would be if not for police discretion. There is one aspect and consequence of this discretion/leniency phenomenon that deserves special consideration. Police discretion sometimes extends to deciding whether a reported event counts as a crime, whether to record it as a serious crime or a lesser crime, whether to thoroughly investigate it, and whether to recommend it for prosecution (Lum 2011). If the victim Police Discretion and Its Control of a reported crime is perceived by an officer as unworthy of serious concern, the crime might be discounted or ignored. For example, this might occur to a woman domestic violence victim or sexual assault victim if the police officer identifies more with the other party involved, or if the officer believes that the victim somehow contributed to her own misfortune. Similarly, an officer might fail to act in response to a reported crime if the victim is someone whose status is not fully respected, such as a recent immigrant or a person whose sexual orientation is considered deviant by the officer. In these examples, discretion allows the police to act leniently toward offenders in situations in which their victims are held in low regard. It can be argued that these are simply more examples of discretion enabling the police to pursue justice and fairness rather than mandatory enforcement, but it is at least equally possible that, in these types of cases, discretion allows officers to act on the basis of their own stereotypes and biases to the disadvantage of deserving victims. Another potential problem with discretion and under-enforcement/leniency arises if the police are more lenient toward majority groups and higherstatus individuals than others. The police might seem lenient if they only arrest 30 % of the people they stop for drinking in public, or if they only conduct searches in conjunction with 10 % of their traffic stops. Analyses often indicate, however, that members of minority groups are disproportionately arrested for minor offenses and disproportionately subject to searches following traffic stops. In other words, the overall picture is one of under-enforcement, but often the enforcement that is undertaken is differentially applied to persons of color. As explained above, this pattern of police discretionary decision making, often called racial profiling, might still be accounted for by situational legal factors, but it might also be a reflection of conscious or unconscious bias. The inherent and most fundamental challenge associated with discretion is simply inconsistency. Discretion gives police officers leeway in deciding how to handle encounters and confrontations based on an “intuitive grasp” of each situation. Ultimately, some people caught with Police Discretion and Its Control a marijuana cigarette get arrested and some do not; some drivers who fail to signal their turns get citations and some do not. This brings into focus two competing conceptions of justice and fairness – one perspective says that fairness is treating every rule breaker the same, while the other perspective says that fairness is treating each person as a person, according to their unique circumstances. Many of us subscribe to the first viewpoint as long as it is applied to others, but want the second approach taken when we are the ones against whom the rules and laws might be applied. Guiding and Controlling Police Discretion While police discretion may be inevitable, it is widely accepted that it should not be unfettered: that it needs to be guided and controlled in order to avoid the kinds of negative consequences discussed above, including inconsistency, undue leniency, and discrimination. State statutes and local laws can and do guide police discretion to a certain degree. For example, some legislatures have sought to restrict police discretion in specific types of cases, notably in the realm of domestic violence through laws mandating arrest of offenders (Phillips and Sobol 2010). Such efforts sometimes merely shift the locus of discretion, however. If the law requires the police to arrest whenever they have probable cause to believe that a domestic assault has occurred, but officers in some situations do not think that arrest is the best response, they may become more likely to decide that the evidence falls short of probable cause, or that no crime has occurred at all. In some cases this kind of decision making may also be driven by a victim’s stated preference for no arrest or by knowledge that the prosecutor is only willing to take certain kinds of cases into court. This is not to say that mandatory laws have no impact on police discretion and decision making, but it is important to recognize that the police and other criminal justice decision makers tend to react in ways that preserve their discretion (Green and Kelso 2010). 3593 P The supervising authority of the courts, including specific court rulings and the risk of civil liability, also has the potential to influence the exercise of police discretion, at least at the margins. The US Supreme Court’s Tennessee v. Garner (1985) decision is a case in point. Prior to Garner, the police had the discretion to use deadly force in situations in which a fleeing or escaping felon could be captured only by shooting them as they fled. The Supreme Court ruled that this authority was too broad and effectively revoked the “fleeing felon rule,” thus narrowing police discretion in the use of deadly force. By themselves, however, laws and court decisions are generally inadequate for guiding and controlling police discretion. As noted, often they merely shift the locus of discretion to another point in the process. Also, court decisions typically resolve one specific issue but leave others unaddressed. The Garner case, for example, eliminated one ancient common law justification for police use of deadly force, but did not posit a new rule in its place or seek to clarify other justifications for police use of deadly force. Moreover, one of the key legal principles underlying police use of force, including deadly force, is “reasonableness” – the police can use any level of force that is reasonable to defend themselves or others from serious threats of bodily harm or to carry out their other lawful responsibilities, such as enforcing the law. While the Garner case ruled that deadly force was unreasonable in one particular set of circumstances, the reasonableness standard remains and it is inherently vague and subjective. An inevitable consequence is that the police have significant discretion in deciding whether to use force and how much force to use. In large part because of these limitations of the law, written policies and procedures are increasingly used by police agencies to set out the parameters of officers’ discretion in certain types of cases and to provide contextual guidance for the proper exercise of it. In the case of domestic violence, for example, police department policies often reinforce and tighten legal requirements by (1) articulating limited exceptions to mandatory enforcement, (2) requiring written justification whenever nonenforcement P P 3594 is chosen in an applicable situation, (3) identifying decisions that require supervisory approval, and (4) specifying penalties for failing to adhere to legal and policy mandates. Similarly, in the case of deadly force, police department policies frequently define an even narrower range of justifications than anything found in the law, they usually caution officers about the sanctity of human life, and they invariably specify elaborate processes that must be followed in the aftermath of any incident in which the police exercise force that could lead to death, regardless of whether anyone dies or is even injured. In neither case, domestic violence nor use of force, do written policies completely eliminate discretion, but they constrain and guide it more thoroughly than is accomplished by law alone. Somewhat less common, but no less important, are written policies that provide guidance for the exercise of discretion in general. One example policy identifies factors that officers should and should not take into consideration when deciding whether to make an arrest (Scott 1995): In general, police officers, using sound professional judgment, may take the following factors into consideration when deciding whether or not to arrest a citizen: (a) the seriousness and nature of the offense (generally, the more serious the offense, the more likely arrest is the preferred course of action); (b) the potential that arrest will effectively resolve a conflict; (c) the availability of legal alternatives to arrest that would adequately resolve the conflict or problem; (d) the likelihood that the citizen will be deterred from future violations by warning and education; (e) the officer’s belief that the citizen made an honest mistake in violation of the law; (f) the victim-witness’s interest in prosecution; (g) the likelihood of formal prosecution of the offense; (h) the potential that arrest will create more serious breaches of the peace or other problems (e.g., inciting riot); (i) legitimate competing priorities for police resources. The following factors are among those that are improper for a police officer to consider in deciding whether or not to make an arrest: (a) the citizen’s economic status, race, ethnicity, gender, or other status for which the law prohibits legal discrimination; (b) the revenue likely to be generated by fines or penalties imposed upon conviction; (c) the personal or professional relationship that the citizen has to the police officer or to other influential citizens; (d) the personal advantage to the officer Police Discretion and Its Control for processing or avoiding processing of the arrest (e.g., overtime compensation, desire to finish tour of duty, avoidance of paperwork, etc.). Police organizations utilize several other methods of guiding officers in the exercise of discretion. Police agency accreditation standards, while not typically dictating the substance of most discretionary judgments, can help create an organizational structure that supports administrative rule making. Police training programs are essential for improving officers’ decision-making skills in the application of policies and procedures. The development of a body of professional and scientific knowledge, grounded in research and practice, about how the police can effectively and fairly address public safety problems also holds promise for shaping important discretionary decisions (Weisburd and Neyroud 2011; Center for Problem-Oriented Policing 2012). In addition, many police agencies are increasingly looking to citizens to provide them with guidance on a range of discretionary matters, from what public safety problems to focus on to what means to use in addressing them. Citizen input can be provided at the policy-making level as well as through systematic input to line officers (Livingston 1997). Years ago, Jerome Skolnick (1966) observed that the police, like members of most organizations, are affected by the need to appear productive. Thus, officers’ discretionary decisions about whether to arrest or issue citations may be influenced by supervisory or command-level expectations about how much “activity” a productive officer should generate. While not new, these pressures seem to be greater today in the era of “metrics” and heightened accountability. Many police departments now use some form of Compstat, a system designed to help top-level executives use crime analysis and statistics to hold mid-level commanders accountable for targeting and reducing crime in their areas of responsibility. These mid-level commanders often press their subordinates to increase enforcement in order to show that they are doing everything possible to reduce crime. The net effect is to reduce discretion at the lowest levels in order to Police Discretion and Its Control satisfy pressures from above. Another effect, perverse and unintended, may be to encourage officers to use their discretion to downgrade or ignore some reported crimes, thus making it appear that crime reduction is occurring even if it is not (Eterno and Silverman 2012). Modern technology is also affecting police discretion. Thanks to mobile radios, cell phones, in-car computers, and automatic vehicle locator systems, today’s police supervisors and commanders can keep track of their subordinates more closely than was the case a decade or two ago. Even more intrusive are in-car cameras and body cameras (not to mention the ubiquitous cell phone cameras in the hands of the public) that record everything that police officers do, thus magnifying the potential for after-the-fact review. While these surveillance technologies may not directly narrow the discretion that officers have in making their decisions, they probably have a substantial indirect effect, since officers must give more consideration to how their decisions will look and be judged in retrospect. In the near future, this technological impact is likely to be magnified further when the feeds from in-car and body cameras go “live” back at police headquarters. When that time comes, supervisors and commanders will have a greatly expanded opportunity to direct officer decision making in the field. This is likely to shift the locus of some discretionary decision making away from police officers and onto the managers back in the electronic control room. This kind of technological breakthrough could produce a fundamental change to our traditional understanding of police work and the centrality of street-level police discretion. It will be quite interesting to see whether it actually does have this profound effect, or if, once again, it merely causes some shifting in the forms and locus of police discretion. Related Entries ▶ Biased Policing ▶ Order Maintenance Policing ▶ Police Discretion in Law Enforcement 3595 P ▶ Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance ▶ Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters ▶ Role and Function of the Police Recommended Reading and References Banton M (1965) The policeman in the community. Basic Books, New York Bittner E (1970) The functions of the police in modern society. GPO, Washington, DC Black D (1980) The manners and customs of the police. Academic, New York Brown MK (1981) Working the street: police discretion and the dilemmas of reform. Russell Sage, New York Center for problem-oriented policing (2012) POP Guides. Online at http://www.popcenter.org/guides/ Davis KC (1969) Discretionary justice. Greenwood Press, Westport Eith C, Durose MR (2011) Contacts between police and the public, 2008. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington, DC, Online at http://www.bjs.gov/ content/pub/pdf/cpp08.pdf Eterno JA, Silverman EB (2012) The crime numbers game: management by manipulation. CRC Press, Boca Raton FBI (2011) Crime in the United States: 2010. Federal Bureau of Investigation, Washington, DC, Online at http://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/ 2010/crime-in-the-u.s.-2010/persons-arrested Friedrich RJ (1980) Police use of force: individuals, situations, and organizations. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 452:82–97 Goldstein J (1960) Police discretion not to invoke the criminal process: low-visibility decisions in the administration of justice. Yale Law J 69:543–589 Goldstein H (1963) Police discretion: the ideal versus the real. Public Admin Rev 23:140–148 Goldstein H (1977) Policing a free society. Ballinger, Cambridge, MA Green T, Kelso C (2010) Police discretion in domestic violence incidents. Am Behav Social Sci J 14:24–44 Kochel TR, Wilson DB, Mastrofski SM (2011) Effect of suspect race on officers’ arrest decisions. Criminology 49:473–512 LaFave W (1965) Arrest: the decision to take a suspect into custody. Little Brown, Boston Livingston D (1997) Police discretion and the quality of life in public places: courts, communities, and the new policing. Columbia Law Rev 97(3):551–672 Lum C (2011) The influence of places on police decision pathways: from call for service to arrest. Justice Quart 28:631–665 Phillips SW, Sobol JJ (2010) Twenty years of mandatory arrest: police decision making in the face of legal requirements. Criminal Just Policy Rev 21:98–118 P P 3596 Reiss AJ Jr (1971) The police and the public. Yale University, New Haven, CT Scott MS (1995) Lauderhill (Florida) police department policy manual. Personal files of the author Skogan W, Frydl K (2004) Fairness and effectiveness in policing: the evidence. National Academies Press, Washington, DC Skolnick J (1966) Justice without trial. Wiley, New York Tennessee v. Garner. (1985). 471 U.S. 1 Terrill W, Leinfelt FH, Kwak D-H (2008) Examining police use of force: a smaller agency perspective. Policing Int J Police Strat Manag 31:57–76 Varano SP, Schafer JA, Cancino JM, Swatt ML (2009) Constructing crime: neighborhood characteristics and police recording behavior. J Criminal Just 37:553–563 Weisburd D, Neyroud P (2011) Police science: toward a new paradigm, New perspectives in policing. National Institute of Justice, Washington, DC Westley WA (1970) Violence and the police. M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, MA Whitaker GP (1982) What is patrol work. Police Stud 4:13–22 Wilson JQ (1968) Varieties of police behavior. Harvard University, Cambridge, MA Police Discretion in Law Enforcement Robert E. Worden1,2 and Sarah J. McLean2 1 School of Criminal Justice, University at Albany, State University of New York, Albany, NY, USA 2 John F. Finn Institute for Public Safety, Inc., Albany, NY, USA Overview Coercive authority is central to the police role, and the discretionary use of police authority is a decision-making process, as officers evaluate the situations in which they intervene and choose a course of action from among a set of alternatives. This entry approaches the study of police discretion from this decision-making perspective. It is concerned with several forms of authority: stops, frisks and searches, arrests, tickets, and the use of physical force. Police authority is infrequently invoked, as a proportion of all police-citizen contacts. Police Discretion in Law Enforcement Officers consider their authority as a resource in “handling” situations, and often they are able to handle situations without resorting to the use of formal authority. Research has illuminated to a degree the circumstances under which authority is used, from which inferences are drawn about the influences on police decision-making, but research has not for the most part formed the basis for normative judgments about the discretionary use of authority – when it has been used well or poorly. Explaining the police decision-making process can be approached like any decisionmaking process. Behavior can be predicted or explained when the premises for decision are known. Police officers’ decisions turn on factual premises, which concern the consequences of alternative police actions and the nature of the situation from which the consequences can be projected, and value premises, about the goals of police intervention and the desirability of alternative sets of consequences. Explaining police decision-making is, however, complicated by the ambiguity and uncertainty of police officers’ task environments. Many different elements of police-citizen encounters have been analyzed as hypothesized influences on police behavior, but only a few of them have been consistently found to affect the use of police authority. Several of those are legal factors: the seriousness of the offense, the strength of evidence, and the preferences of complainants for disposition. Among extralegal factors, only the demeanor of suspects has emerged as a fairly consistent predictor of police action. The discretionary exercise of police authority varies across individual officers. It is fairly clear that this variation is patterned by officers’ length of service and also by officers’ outlooks and personality traits. The influence of other individual factors, such as educational background, is undetermined. The use of police authority is subject to regulation by departmental policies, but the circumstances under which policy regulation can have maximum impact are seldom realized in policing. The use of deadly force can be Police Discretion in Law Enforcement successfully restricted. Other uses of police authority are probably less susceptible to policy guidance. Among the many open questions about police use of their authority are three addressed in this entry: the influence of citizens’ race, modeling police decision-making, and how research might contribute to improvements in the quality of police decision-making. 3597 P next section, the entry discusses the forms of authority that police exercise and how they have been analyzed; then it explains how a decisionmaking framework can be applied to police discretion in their use of authority. In the following section, the entry summarizes what is known about the explanations of officers’ discretionary choices. Then several open questions are addressed. Introduction Police Authority and Discretionary Decision-making Coercive authority is central to the police officer’s role; it is a unique occupational prerogative that enables police to “handle” urgent situations. The situations may be crimes, with clear and serious violations of criminal law, the response to which is the apprehension of perpetrators, or the situations could be disorders, with ambiguities stemming from whether the law applies, who bears how much responsibility for the situation, and what should be done about it. But all of these situations share an element of urgency, in that prompt action is needed, whether it is a burglary in progress, a drunk driver, a loud party, a domestic conflict, or a blocked driveway (see especially Bittner 1974; Muir 1977). In each instance, police exercise discretion, which is the capacity to choose among courses of action based on one’s judgment. Police officers typically work outside of direct supervision and often in private settings in which only the officer(s) and the parties directly involved have knowledge of the circumstances and the actions, if any, that police take. So while thick books of policies and procedures exist in many agencies, in practice, officers are left to define the situation and fashion a response, thus determining whether and, if so, which policies and procedures apply. The exercise of police discretion is a decisionmaking process, as officers evaluate the situations in which they intervene and choose a course of action from among a set of alternatives; if their involvement is not at the request of a citizen, they also make decisions about whether to intervene. This entry approaches the study of police discretion from this decision-making perspective. In the Police Authority Police exercise several forms of authority. An officer may stop and detain someone when he/she has reasonable, articulable suspicion that the person has committed, is committing, or is about to commit a crime. An officer may frisk, or pat down, an individual if she/he has reasonable suspicion that the person might be armed. An officer may conduct a more extensive search of a person incident to that person’s arrest and may conduct a warrantless search of a person, a vehicle, or even a building under some other circumstances. An officer may take someone into custody for the purpose of charging them with a crime; if the suspected offense is a felony, an officer needs only probable cause to believe that a crime was committed, while for most offenses of lesser seriousness, the officer may act only if she/he witnesses the offense or a citizen signs a complaint. For some types of offenses, officers may issue a summons that directs the alleged offender to appear in court, rather than make a custodial arrest; this is of course common for traffic violations and also for some other less serious offenses (such as public drinking). Finally, police may use the physical force that is reasonably necessary to perform their duties; the US Supreme Court ruled in Tennessee v. Garner that police may even use deadly force if an “officer has probable cause to believe that the suspect poses a threat of some physical harm, either to the officer or others.” The forms of physical force that police may use has multiplied with the development and adoption of less-lethal weaponry, such as pepper spray and conducted energy devices, in the last 10–20 years. P P 3598 Social science has focused mainly on the exercise of authority by patrol officers, and it has normally conceived, measured, and analyzed these forms of police authority one by one – that is, some studies examine arrest, while others analyze the use of physical force, and still others analyze stops, etc. In most instances, officers’ use of police authority consists of a discrete act – making an arrest, conducting a search; the main exception is the use of physical force, which is commonly broken down into forms of force that vary in their seriousness, such as physical restraint, impact methods (punches or kicks), and the use of weapons. These are not mutually exclusive forms of behavior, of course; to the contrary, an officer might well stop and detain, frisk, arrest, and physically restrain an individual in a single encounter. One effort to form a single scale of authority weighted the individual components, but empirically it was not much different from an arrest/no arrest dichotomy. In general, police authority is infrequently invoked, as a proportion of all police-citizen contacts. Many years ago, James Q. Wilson (1968) observed that the tendency of the police is to underenforce the law, declining to take legal action even when the circumstances authorize them to take legal action. Thus it was not uncommon for police to release in the field offenders about whose culpability police had evidence sufficient to warrant arrest. Wilson pointed out that police see their authority as a resource in accomplishing their objectives, such that the application of their authority is not an end but a means, and in many instances their objective is merely to “handle the situation” – that is, to restore order and to prevent immediate violence. When an arrest was made, the “formal charge justifies the arrest but is not the reason for it” (Bittner 1974, p. 27); the reason for such an arrest is that the situation could not be handled in some other, informal fashion. Similarly, studies of the use of force have found that police seldom use physical force, and some research has found that police frequently refrain from using physical force when they could legally do so or use less physical force than the citizen’s resistance would justify. Sometimes police presence by itself is Police Discretion in Law Enforcement sufficient to restore order. And even if presence alone is not enough, police may be able to resolve matters by talking: persuading, cajoling, exhorting, negotiating, or mediating. Since Wilson made his observation, with changes in the (semiprofessional) status of police, criminal procedure, and civil liability, the view of the police may be somewhat different, but not dramatically different. Even far into (and perhaps beyond) the “community era” of policing, authority is central to the police role. Police may now supplement their use (or threatened use) of authority with other approaches, but even when they perform problem-oriented policing, authority remains a resource on which they can and often do draw. In addition, the difficulty of reorienting police to a more community- and problem-oriented role – getting officers to think in terms of groups of related incidents rather than individual incidents and to consider unconventional solutions to those problems – suggests that the use of coercive authority has not changed dramatically in the last 40–50 years. Arrest and physical force remain infrequent acts. Police proactivity – contacts with citizens initiated by the police – is almost certainly at a higher level now, however, and it has occasioned some controversy about its benefits and the social distribution of its costs. Another change over time might lie in the public’s expectations for police effects on social conditions. In the early 1970s, Egon Bittner could say that police are “empowered and required to impose or . . . coerce a provisional solution upon emergent problems . . .” (1974: 18; emphasis added), suggesting that the solution extended no further than the immediate situation. Yet we evaluate the police in terms of more – for example, research on policing spouse assault assessed police interventions in terms of recidivism by assailants over a 6-month post-intervention period, not in terms of more “provisional” solutions. Aside from hypothesized biases in the use of authority, to be discussed below, research has tended not to address the normative dimensions of police authority, that is, whether an arrest or the use of physical force was a good choice or Police Discretion in Law Enforcement a bad choice. The situations that police handle are complex, and so a normative judgment about the use of police authority is contingent on many factors. Moreover, the criteria against which such a judgment should be made are not at all clear. Officers’ choices could be judged in terms of immediate outcomes, such as whether agitated citizens are calmed, or in terms of longer-term outcomes, such as whether a domestic assailant recidivates. None of these have been much considered in research on police use of authority. Another potential criterion is a professional one of “workmanship.” Bittner (1983) distinguishes legality from workmanship as standards against which to judge police performance. The former involves the application of “explicitly formulated schemes of regulation,” while the latter is concerned with officers’ “ability to call upon the resources of knowledge, skill, and judgment to meet and master the unexpected within one’s sphere of competence.” Bittner goes on to explain that the standard of workmanship would subject officers’ performance to the scrutiny and critique of others authorized to assess their work after the fact: peers, who are subject to the same review, and the community, on whose behalf the work is done. Similarly, Klockars (1996) proposes a “craft standard” against which the use of force could be compared, that is, what a skilled police officer would have done under the circumstances. A skilled police officer would take all possible steps to structure the situation into which she/he intervenes in such a way that either resistance will not be offered or the resistance can be overcome with a minimum of force. Few efforts have been made to develop such standards conceptually or empirically, however. As a general proposition, social scientists seem agreed that authority is a resource that police should use sparingly. Muir (1977) describes a “good” officer as one who is morally comfortable with the use of coercive power as needed but who uses it only as needed. Moore (2002) allows as how police are more efficient when they use a minimum of authority. The use of police authority, he points out, depletes the “stock of private liberty” (2002: 26) that the public enjoys, and the “net value” of policing 3599 P must take account of not only the crime and disorder that police prevent but also the costs of policing, one of which is the use of authority. In the last 10 years or so, research has reflected a better appreciation for how the quality of police performance might have as much (or more) to do with how authority is exercised as it does with what form of authority is exercised. Surveys of citizens have repeatedly shown that they are more satisfied with their contacts with the police when they believe that police treated them with dignity and respect, gave them an opportunity to explain their situations and listened to what they had to say, and explained what police have done and/or will do, so that it is clear that officers are taking account of people’s needs and concerns and basing their decisions on facts. Moreover, these patterns hold even for people who experience unfavorable outcomes, such as being ticketed. Unfortunately, however, research on police behavior has only scratched the surface in its examination of the behavioral manifestations of procedural justice. Decision-Making The discretionary use of police authority is a decision-making task, as officers must make choices – numerous choices – in their encounters with citizens. Among their choices, the uses of their authority are prominent: to stop and question, to frisk or search, to arrest, to cite, and to use any of a variety of forms of physical force. As an encounter with a citizen unfolds over time, the choices may recur. Explaining this decision-making process, and the behavior that ensues therefrom, can in principle be approached like any decision-making process. Behavior can be predicted or explained when the premises for decision are known. Police officers’ decisions turn on factual premises, which concern the consequences of alternative police actions and the nature of the situation from which the consequences can be projected, and value premises, about the goals of police intervention and the desirability of alternative sets of consequences (see Worden and Brandl 1990, pp. 302–303). Most research on police behavior has, in effect, treated as hypothesized P P 3600 decision premises the characteristics of policecitizen encounters, such as the nature of the offense, the demeanor of suspects, and the preferences of complainants for a disposition. Several studies have also examined as potential influences the characteristics of police organizations; organizational policies, procedures, and informal norms may serve as decision premises. Some research has, in effect, allowed for variation in decision-making among classes of decisionmakers, for example, male and female officers, novice and experienced officers, and collegeeducated and less-educated officers. Explaining police decision-making in terms of situational and organizational cues is complicated by the ambiguity and uncertainty of police officers’ task environments. Situational cues are ambiguous in that the meaning or significance of any cue, or set of cues, is subject to different interpretations. The credibility of citizens’ testimony (which often is contradicted by other citizens’ testimony), the severity of injuries, the degree of citizens’ sobriety, and many other features of police-citizen encounters are all matters of officers’ judgment, and these judgments can vary from situation to situation and from officer to officer. The same cue can be interpreted differently across multiple events or even ignored as irrelevant in some of them. The meaning and significance even of readily recognizable cues is ambiguous, subject to different interpretations by different officers. Similarly, organizational policies and group norms are ambiguous, requiring that officers interpret them as they are applied in individual cases. Explanation is further complicated by uncertainty about cause-and-effect relationships. Once an officer interprets the meaning of situational cues and the applicability of organizational policies, she/he must choose a course of action based partly on the projected consequences of those alternatives, but no body of scientific or other technical knowledge guides officers in making such projections, and even if there were, they would be in any case only probabilistic. Officers may be socialized into some common working rules, but they also learn through their own idiosyncratic experiences, drawing from them some equally idiosyncratic Police Discretion in Law Enforcement lessons for practice. Thus we can posit that the meaning and also the implications of situational and organizational cues are heterogeneous across officers, which would attenuate the explanatory power of situational and organizational variables. Prior research on police decision-making, for the most part, takes one of two approaches: ethnographic inquiry and quantitative analyses of decision outcomes (e.g., police decisions to arrest or to use force) in terms of situational factors that are the hypothesized stimuli to which decisionmakers respond. The former have been very illuminating, though they are limited in their generalizability. The latter are scientifically rigorous, exploiting numerical data on the characteristics of the immediate decision task to estimate (often through regression analysis) their independent effects on decision outcomes. Researchers draw inferences about the forces that shape decisionmaking from the regression coefficients, treating the process by which informational inputs are interpreted and judgments are made to reach decisions as a “black box.” But these analyses are limited in their explanatory scope to factors that are of a priori significance, and we know that these factors fall far short of explaining police decisions. Moreover, much of the research has been oriented not to explaining discretionary decision-making as such, but rather to determining whether and to what extent the application of police authority is influenced by “extralegal” factors, such as race, sex, and age. Thus, the analyses seek to control for the legal factors that legitimately shape police behavior, whereupon a determination can be made about whether residual variation is related to extralegal factors. Influences on Discretionary Decision-Making Most of the factors that have been analyzed as parts of an explanation of discretionary decisions by police have been classified into one of several sets, each a different level of explanation. As noted above, some of these factors, and those at the lowest level of explanation, are features of Police Discretion in Law Enforcement the police-citizen encounters in which the discretionary decisions are made; these are often referred to as situational factors. A second set, and the next higher level of explanation, are comprised of the characteristics and outlooks of individual officers. A third set, and a still higher level of explanation, are characteristics of the neighborhoods that form the immediate social context of police-citizen encounters. The fourth set include characteristics of police organizations, including both the formal, structural features of police agencies – rules, regulations, and specialization – and the informal organization: the peer culture(s) and norms. Finally, some research has attended to another, still higher level of organization: the requirements and constraints of the law, especially that of criminal procedure. This entry concentrates on three of these sets: situational, officers, and organizational. Situational Factors Situational factors are external to the decision-maker and form the immediate decision environment. The most succinct statement of this explanatory perspective is Bittner’s, who asserts that “the role of the police is best understood as a mechanism for the distribution of non-negotiably coercive force employed in accordance with the dictates of an intuitive grasp of situational exigencies” (1970: 46). Situational factors represent these exigencies. A more conventional sociological formulation is that of Black and Reiss (1967), who posit that police action turns on the social status, situational status (e.g., as complainant, suspect), and “subversive capability” of citizens. Most research of this genre, however, has been less theoretically driven in its assessments of situational exigencies. Many different elements of police-citizen encounters have been analyzed as hypothesized influences on police behavior, but only a few of them have been consistently found to affect the use of police authority. Several of those are legal factors: the seriousness of the offense, the strength of evidence, and the preferences of complainants for disposition. Among extralegal factors, only the demeanor of suspects has 3601 P emerged as a fairly consistent predictor of police action; the estimated effects of sex and age have been mixed, as have those of race, to which the entry returns below. It should come as no surprise that the use of authority by American police is affected by legal factors, but research confirms that police are more likely to use their authority when they have evidence of criminal offending – and the stronger the evidence, the more likely is the use of authority – and when the offense is more serious. It is perhaps remarkable, however, that the effects are not stronger still. Certainly, police use of authority is not determined by legal factors; as noted above, police often do not take legal action even when they have grounds for legal action. Furthermore, when complainants articulate a clear preference for or against legal action, police tend to comply, especially when the preference is for lenience. This tendency “gives police work a radically democratic character,” as Black (1971) points out, and as a result, police apply a standard of justice that varies with the moral standards of complainants, not a uniform standard of justice. However, as Mastrofski et al. (1995) observe, the cooperation of complainants is likely to affect prosecution, and so when complainants prefer that police not take legal action, police might reasonably treat that as an “instrumental” legal consideration. The frequency with which victims of domestic violence are reluctant to cooperate has, given concerns that these complainants are not exercising choice freely, prompted changes in laws and policies that are intended to attenuate the effect of complainant preference in such cases. Both qualitative and quantitative studies have found that police are more likely to respond punitively to suspects who display disrespect toward the police. Empirical support for this relationship is nearly uniform in research on police behavior, even in the absence of a single, widely accepted definition and operationalization of demeanor, and notwithstanding whatever random measurement error has been contained in indicators of demeanor. This relationship is open to one or both of two interpretations: police penalize P P 3602 people who flunk the “attitude test” with arrest, ticketing, or a “thumping” (Van Maanen 1978), or police often give “breaks” to deferential suspects but seldom to those who are hostile or disrespectful. Some support can be found for both of these causal mechanisms. Klinger (1994) questioned this “criminological axiom”, arguing that demeanor had been improperly conceived and measured in previous research and also that previous research had failed to control (adequately or at all) for crime committed by suspects during their encounters with police, including especially assaults on police officers. However, reanalyses of thenextant data, using measures that took account of Klinger’s critique, affirmed the previous conclusions, and other elements of Klinger’s argument have also been disputed (Worden et al. 1996). But Klinger’s critique surely revealed shortcomings and inconsistencies in the conceptualization and measurement of demeanor, and subsequent studies have exhibited the greater care that Klinger’s critique demanded. Even so, theoretical ambiguity remains. Research now differentiates “resistance” from “demeanor,” yet many forms of (especially passive or only verbal) resistance are entirely legal, and we have reason to believe that many forms of (both legal and illegal) resistance are interpreted by police as failures of the attitude test, such that we should interpret their effects as the effects of demeanor (see Worden et al. 1996). So long as research is interested in explaining the discretionary use of police authority, and not merely in forming post hoc judgments about its propriety, conclusions about the effects of demeanor must turn on how officers interpret the various manifestations of disrespect. More generally, the theory (such as it is) and much of the empirical analysis of situational effects has been based on a sociological framework, and one that makes an implicit assumption that the effects are not contingent on the backgrounds or outlooks of individual officers. This assumption is not entirely without merit, inasmuch as early research on police emphasized the shared working conditions, experiences, values, and norms among police; hence assuming Police Discretion in Law Enforcement (albeit implicitly) that officers attend to the same cues, interpret them similarly, consider the same set of alternative courses of action, and choose based on the same criteria is not unreasonable. Furthermore, some results seem to suggest that, on some dimensions of decision-making, officers approach their choices similarly: the arrest decision is shaped by the seriousness of the offense, the strength of evidence, the preferences of complainants, and the demeanor of suspects, and while there may be individual differences on these scores, the differences are not stark, and across the board it appears that these variables have a substantial degree of explanatory power. In other choices, especially choices among informal responses, however, the effects of situational factors have not been so robust (Worden 1989), and the use of authority other than arrest may be more susceptible to individual differences. Several qualitative studies in the 1970s (e.g., Brown 1981; Muir 1977) showed that officers do not all see their occupational environment the same way and that they develop distinct “operational styles”; different studies using different frameworks nevertheless described a set of officer types that were broadly congruent Officer Characteristics and Outlooks While it is clear that officers’ discretionary choices are structured by the characteristics of the incidents that they handle, it is also clear that these situational elements do not completely determine officers’ responses, as much of the variation in their behavior is unexplained by situational variables. Because officers’ decisions are of “low visibility” to their superiors and to the legal system, scholars have sometimes speculatively attributed the unexplained variation in behavior to officers’ attitudes and values. This perspective directs attention to factors internal to decision-maker, which might affect how situational cues are interpreted and evaluated and how options are assessed. For example, Toch (1980) found that violence-prone officers are especially sensitive to citizens’ challenges to their authority. Such an account has intuitive appeal, and it is of more than theoretical significance, inasmuch as it underlies initiatives to Police Discretion in Law Enforcement change the composition of or otherwise “upgrade” police personnel, since it is supposed that minority officers, female officers, or collegeeducated officers have different outlooks and therefore perform the police role differently. It also underlies efforts to inculcate different outlooks through training. Systematic research has not always confirmed these intuitive propositions. One of the earliest and most striking findings from observational research on police was that, while many officers professed to be prejudiced against African-Americans, officers did not act on that prejudice in their encounters with citizens (Reiss 1971). A later and more general examination of attitude-behavior consistency (Worden 1989) found only weak relationships between officers’ occupational attitudes (for example, their conceptions of the police role, attitudes toward citizens, and attitudes toward legal restrictions) and their behaviors (for example, proactivity in field interrogation and dispute resolution). Such results perhaps should not be surprising, in view of the ambiguity and uncertainty of police work. The ambiguous situations into which police intervene are subject to different interpretations, and they are not governed by well-established causeand-effect relationships between police actions and desired outcomes, so officers’ choices among alternative courses of action may be only loosely structured by their attitudes and values. Officers with the same occupational outlooks might judge a situation differently, reading the informational cues in a situation in different ways, or perceive different ways of reaching the same objectives. Be that as it may, analyses in several agencies have shown that small numbers of officers account for disproportionately large fractions of citizen complaints and use-of-force reports. Furthermore, Brandl et al. (2001) found that less experienced officers are disproportionately represented among officers with multiple complaints about the use of excessive force. Scrivner (1994) discovered five groups of officers among those referred to police psychologists due to their use of excessive force, including officers with personality disorders; officers whose job-related 3603 P experiences – for example, traumatic incidents such as police shootings – put the officers at risk for abusing force; young and inexperienced officers who were also “highly impressionable and impulsive”; officers who develop inappropriate patrol styles; and officers with personal problems. Harris (2010) showed that officers differ in their career “trajectories” of misconduct. Further, more recent findings have provided more support for the hypothesized effects of officers’ outlooks, mainly because it has analyzed attitudes as bundles in terms of which subsets of officers can be differentiated, rather than estimating the additive effects of attitudes one by one. For example, Terrill et al. (2003) found that officers whose occupational attitudes conform more closely to the tenets of the traditional police culture are more prone to the use of their coercive authority. Similarly, Paoline and Terrill (2005) found that such officers are more likely to conduct searches during traffic stops. Cuttler and Muchinsky (2006) found that personality traits and work history predict “dysfunctional job performance.” Other characteristics of officers – their race, sex, and educational background – have all been hypothesized to affect how officers do their jobs, though the evidence on these hypotheses is mixed and inconclusive (National Research Council 2004). Thus it is fairly clear that the discretionary exercise of police authority varies across individual officers. It is also fairly clear that this variation is patterned by officers’ length of service and also by officers’ outlooks and personality traits. The influence of other individual factors, such as educational background, is undetermined. Organizational Factors The hypothesized effects of organizational factors, and particularly the formal, structural characteristics of rules, regulations, standard operating procedures, and the hierarchical chain of command through which they are enforced, are central to common ideas about police accountability. Police departments are widely known as quasi-military organizations, with many of the trappings of such organizations (such as ranks P P 3604 and insignia), as well as the aura of a tight chain of command. The nature of police tasks, however, which makes discretion an inherent element of police work, also circumscribes the effects of these organizational factors on the use of police authority. One mechanism by which police departments might influence the use of force by their officers is, of course, through rules and regulations that set limits on when police may use force and how much force they may use. Research on the use of deadly force suggests that this mechanism can be effective, under some circumstances. In 1972, well in advance of the Garner ruling by the Supreme Court (in 1984), the New York City Police Department (NYPD) modified its policy about the use of deadly force, imposing much tighter restrictions, providing that “every other reasonable means will be utilized for arresting, preventing, or terminating a felony or for the defense of oneself or another before a police officer resorts to the use of his firearm” (quoted in Fyfe 1979). A study of the effects of this policy change showed that it had a substantial effect on officers’ use of their firearms (Fyfe 1979). The policy had an especially pronounced effect on what Fyfe (1988, p. 185) characterized as “elective” shootings, that is, situations in which officers could have chosen not to shoot at no risk to themselves or other parties. Furthermore, the reduction in shootings was achieved with no increase in officer injuries or deaths. The effectiveness of this policy almost certainly turned to a large extent on its enforcement. The NYPD established a Firearms Discharge Review Board to investigate and adjudicate all firearm discharges, holding officers accountable for their use of deadly force. Other research also found that restrictive deadly force policies are effective only if they are vigorously enforced. No one should suppose that departmental policies that regulate the use of nonlethal force are or can be equally effective, however. The circumstances under which nonlethal force is justified are more heterogeneous and also more ambiguous; thus policy prescriptions concerning nonlethal force cannot achieve equivalent clarity. Police Discretion in Law Enforcement Use-of-force continua and matrices specify different kinds and degree of force, and (sometimes) the degrees of citizen resistance to which forms of force correspond, but the resistance can take widely varied forms and the behavioral lines that conceptually demarcate different levels of resistance are far from clear in practice; ambiguity is inescapable. Moreover, the use of nonlethal force is probably less reliably reported by officers, and even if such force is infrequent as a proportion of police-citizen contacts, it happens with sufficient frequency that police superiors may not be able to routinely investigate every use of nonlethal force in order to determine officers’ compliance with policy. Furthermore, even when investigations can be conducted, one can anticipate that many will be inconclusive, with evidence limited to the contrasting accounts of the officer and the citizen against whom force was used. Thus the enforcement of such policies would almost inevitably lack the teeth associated with NYPD’s reviews of firearm discharges (where, as Fyfe points out, the population density is so high that one might reasonably suppose that few firearms discharges could be safely concealed). This is not to imply that policies would be altogether ineffective in limiting and guiding the use of nonlethal force, however; one recent study suggests that some types of policies are more effective than others – and presumably, better than no policy at all – in promoting the use of force that is proportional to citizen resistance (Terrill et al. 2011). Similar expectations might be formed with respect to policies that are intended to promote or even mandate arrest in cases of domestic violence. The situations are ambiguous, and so the applicability of policy is subject to officers’ interpretations in the field, and enforcement of policy requirements would be hindered by the cost and difficulty of determining whether officers complied with the policy in individual cases, which are numerous. Even so, some research indicates that pro-arrest policies yield increases in arrests in domestic assault cases, though examples of resistance and noncompliance can be found. Police Discretion in Law Enforcement Open Questions The open questions about police use of their authority are far too numerous to even list here, much less consider them. Three questions are addressed: the influence of citizens’ race, modeling police decision-making, and how research might contribute to improvements in the quality of police decision-making. Research on the police consistently finds that African-Americans are disproportionately represented among the people against whom police use their authority. It has inconsistently found that, other things being equal, race affects at the margin the application of police authority. The question of racial (and ethnic) bias in policing dates to at least the 1960s, when the grievances of urban minority populations against the police were cited as contributing factors to civil unrest. It has been especially salient in the aftermath of incidents in which police have been suspected of abusing their authority in their treatment of minority citizens, of which the Rodney King incident in 1991 may be the most widely known example. But since the mid-1990s, concerns about racial profiling by police – that is, the use of a drug courier profile that included race as a feature, and more generally stopping and searching African-Americans and other people of color based on their race or ethnicity – have been prevalent and sustained, even prompting many states and localities to mandate that police departments track the race of the people who are stopped. Unfortunately, the volume of analysis on this question has not been matched by its theoretical sophistication, and bedeviled by what is sometimes known as the benchmarking problem, the studies can seldom provide persuasive evidence about whether the disparities are or are not attributable to legitimate practices, and moreover, they are not oriented toward explanation and offer little insight into the role of race in police decision-making. The mixed findings on the role of race may reflect the complex, contingent nature of the effects of race, but they might also be symptomatic of drawbacks to the conventional approach to 3605 P analyzing police decision-making. This approach, described above, rests on an assumption that police decisions, like structural regression models, are a weighted sum of the postulated decision cues: legal seriousness, strength of evidence, complainant preference, suspect demeanor, and the like. It is unlikely that the process of police decision-making resembles this computational model, however. And the regression models seldom explain more than a small fraction of the variation in behavior. Different kinds of data and a different kind of model might yield deeper insights into the forces that shape police decisions. A different approach, that of “protocol analysis” or “process tracing,” promises to shed further light onto decision-making by opening the black box of police officers’ cognitive processes (see Worden and Brandl 1990, and the sources cited therein). For research based on protocol analysis, decision-makers are asked to think aloud as they perform decision tasks, or they might be asked to recount their thinking as soon as possible after performing a decision task. Research subjects’ verbal reports of their thinking are data on their decision processes. Protocol analysis of police has not been conducted often, but several studies demonstrate that it is both feasible and illuminating. For example, Stalans and Finn (1995) discovered that the perceptual and cognitive processes that officers apply in interpreting and evaluating domestic violence incidents vary by experience: less experienced (“novice”) officers tend to evaluate domestic violence situations in terms of blame, while their more experienced colleagues are more pragmatic, putting more emphasis on the sparing use of arrest (and their time) and on an assessment of the immediate potential for further violence and the prospects for prosecution. Both novice and experienced officers, however, tended to assess situations as typical or atypical. Stroshine et al. (2008) enumerate informal “working rules” that serve to guide officers in performing their jobs, and they observe that “different officers look for different things and respond to suspects and situations differently” (2008: 335). They describe the cues P P 3606 to which officers attend in forming suspicion (e.g., time and place, and citizens’ appearance and behaviors), the rules of thumb that they apply (e.g., with respect to the seriousness of violations, or the citizen’s demeanor), and more general approaches that they take to their work (seeking out or avoiding opportunities for traffic enforcement). The potential of protocol analysis might be best realized through the construction of process models, which resemble flow charts. Compared to the structural models that are normally estimated, process models are probably more accurate representations of how people make complex decisions, especially under conditions of ambiguity and uncertainty. Finally, an overriding question revolves around the normative dimensions of police decision-making and the use of police authority. Research has little to say about the extent to which, and the circumstances under which, police use their authority well. Even research on the use of physical force has, for the most part, lost a focus on the improper use of force. Research will be far more useful if and when it can draw empirically grounded conclusions about when police should use what authority and why. Research will also be more useful if and when it can establish the connections between what the police do – what authority they exercise and how they exercise it – and how it is subjectively experienced by citizens; survey research has dwelt on citizens’ perceptions, but it has not estimated the relationships between citizens’ perceptions and overt police acts. Recommended Reading and References Bittner E (1970) The functions of the police in modern society. National Institute of Mental Health, Bethesda, MD Bittner E (1974) Florence nightingale in pursuit of Willie Sutton: a theory of the police. In: Jacob H (ed) The potential for reform of criminal justice. Sage, Beverly Hills Bittner E (1983) Legality and workmanship: introduction to control in the police organization. In: Punch M (ed) Control in the police organization. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA Police Discretion in Law Enforcement Black D (1971) The social organization of arrest. Stanford Law Rev 23:1087–1111 Black D, Reiss AJ Jr (1967) Patterns of behavior in police and citizen transactions. In: Studies of crime and law enforcement in major metropolitan areas, vol II, Sec I. GPO, Washington, DC Brandl SG, Stroshine MS, Frank J (2001) Who are the complaint-prone officers? an examination of the relationship between police officers’ attributes, arrest activity, assignment, and citizens’ complaints about excessive force. J Criminal Just 29:521–529 Brown MK (1981) Working the street: police discretion and the dilemmas of reform. Russell Sage, New York Brown MK (1988) Working the street: police discretion and the dilemmas of reform. Russell Sage, New York Cuttler MJ, Muchinsky PM (2006) Prediction of Law enforcement training performance and dysfunctional Job performance with general mental ability, personality, and life history variables. Criminal Just Behav 33:3–25 Fyfe JJ (1979) Administrative interventions on police shooting discretion. J Criminal Just 7:309–323 Fyfe JJ (1988) Police use of deadly force: research and reform. Justice Quart 5:165–205 Harris CJ (2010) Pathways of police misconduct: problem behavior patterns and trajectories from two cohorts. Carolina Academic Press, Durham Klinger DA (1994) Demeanor or crime? Why ‘Hostile’ citizens are more likely to be arrested. Criminology 32:475–493 Klockars CB (1996) A theory of excessive force and its control. In: Geller WA, Toch H (eds) Police violence: understanding and controlling police abuse of force. Yale University Press, New Haven Mastrofski SD, Worden RE, Snipes JB (1995) Law enforcement in a time of community policing. Criminology 33:539–563 Moore MH (2002) Recognizing value in policing: the challenge of measuring police performance. Police Executive Research Forum, Washington, DC Muir WK Jr (1977) Police: streetcorner politicians. University of Chicago Press, Chicago National Research Council (2004) In: Committee to Review Research on Police Policy and Practices, Skogan WG, Frydl K (eds) Fairness and effectiveness in policing: the evidence. Committee on Law and Justice, Division of Behavioral and Social and Behavioral Sciences and Education. Washington, DC: National Academies Press Paoline, Eugene A. III, William Terrill (2005) The Impact of Police Culture on Traffic Stop Searches: An Analysis of Attitudes and Behavior. Policing: An International Journal of Police Strategies and Management 28(3):455–472 Reiss AJ Jr (1971) The police and the public. Yale University Press, New Haven Scrivner EM (1994) Controlling police Use of excessive force: the role of the police psychologist. National Institute of Justice, Research in Brief, Washington Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance Stalans LJ, Finn MA (1995) How novice and experienced officers interpret wife assaults: normative and efficiency frames. Law Soc Rev 29:287–321 Stroshine M, Alpert G, Dunham R (2008) The influence of ‘working Rules’ on police suspicion and discretionary decision making. Police Quart 11:315–337 Terrill W, Paoline EA III, Ingram J (2011) Assessing police use of force policy and outcomes. Michigan State University, East Lansing Terrill W, Paoline EA III, Manning PK (2003) Police culture and coercion. Criminology 41:1003–1034 Toch H (1980) Violent men, Revth edn. Schenkmen, Cambridge, MA Van Maanen J (1974) Working the street: a developmental view of police behavior. In: Jacob H (ed) The potential for reform of criminal justice. Sage, Beverly Hills Van Maanen J (1978) The asshole. In: Manning PK, Van Maanen J (eds) Policing: a view from the street. Goodyear, Santa Monica, CA Wilson JQ (1968) Varieties of police behavior: the management of Law and order in eight communities. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Worden RE (1989) Situational and attitudinal explanations of police behavior: a theoretical reappraisal and empirical assessment. Law Soc Rev 23:667–711 Worden RE, Brandl SG (1990) Protocol analysis of police decision making: toward a theory of police behavior. Am J Criminal Just 14:297–318 Worden RE, Shepard RL, Mastrofski SD (1996) On the meaning and measurement of Suspects’ demeanor toward the police. J Res Crime Delinq 33:324–332 Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance John D. McCluskey Department of Criminal Justice, Rochester Institute of Technology, Rochester, NY, USA Overview Consideration of police discretion as it relates to the provision of services to the public is an area of much speculation but little hard data. It is widely recognized that police are called upon to do much more than fight crime and enforce the law (e.g., Cumming et al. 1965; Guyot 1991). Patrol officers, for example, spend little time arresting individuals for crimes in any given work shift and are often observed not arresting under circumstances when authorized to do so 3607 P by the law. Nevertheless, the academic literature focuses heavily on the decision to arrest and the decision to use force, because they address issues that are at the core of democratic governance: How does the state use its coercive power? This leaves a substantial gap in understanding what police choose to with regard to offering help and assistance as necessary and as directed by the public. The gap is especially apparent with regard to enumerating and explaining the actions police undertake outside the scope of their legally mandated and more clearly authorized law enforcement duties (Skogan and Frydl 2004). The issues surrounding police discretion in helping and serving the public will be discussed along several dimensions. First, the history of police and their role, particularly in the United States, will be considered. The mandate of police, as a social control mechanism, offers an opportunity to understand broader patterns of police behavior over the long term and how police relate to and define their work. Second, service and helping behaviors will be defined. Since service and helping constitutes, in the most rigorous analysis, a variable, it is necessary to locate reasonable boundaries and dimensions upon which service and helping can be arrayed. No precise definition will be offered, as technological changes and task requirements continuously shape police work, but a set of considerations will be explored. Third, measurement of service including attempts and future directions will be considered. Fourth, a set of preliminary propositions regarding police exercise of discretion in allocating or engaging in helping behaviors will be outlined. Fifth, the transformation of the police mandate toward recognition, if tacit, of the importance of service activity is examined in light of problem-oriented policing and the community policing movements and the influence on discretion regarding helping behaviors. Sixth, the service and help behaviors of police will be related to the specific client population of mentally ill citizens whom which they very frequently encounter. Finally, the entry is summarized and future directions for consideration in the areas of service and helping behavior and police discretion are offered. P P 3608 History US municipal police forces, according to some historians, were established as general service provision agencies and had wide-ranging responsibilities including dealing with lost children, inspecting boilers, and feeding and housing the homeless. Lane (1967) documents the primary role that the Boston police, for example, played in running soup kitchens and providing temporary lodging for the homeless. This service was based on the observation that “misery bred crime and soup helped to prevent it” (Lane 1967: 193). Data gathered by historians also indicate that activities involving lost children, for example, were recorded with some care, thus illustrating the important nature of that task. Monkonnen (1981: 119) argued that the centralized communication capacity of the police made them the primary agency in assisting citizens with their problems. Others have argued, more cynically, that police were more easily understood as paid agents of the dominant order than a public agency aimed at help and service (Harring 1983). Historical analysis derived from a Boston, MA police officer’s diary entries in the year 1895 indicates the panoply of service provided to constituents and the rarity of activity that explicitly involved legal channels (Von Hoffman 1992). Rather daily work would more closely resemble regulatory attention to maintaining social order and largely via service. Even crime-related entries represented mobilizations by citizens who desired the service of the officer in maintaining security or apprehending wrongdoers. The focus on service is likely due in part to some problems not being easily defined as legal or criminal problems and the cost that is borne, in terms of time lost, when an officer has to take the time to invoke arrest, especially on foot. Nevertheless it is imperative to recognize that police have traditionally been asked to address a wide variety of problems as a general service agency, which was probably cast best by Egon Bittner’s (1990) hyphenated summary of what becomes police business: “something-that-ought-not-to-be-happening-andabout-which-someone-had-better-do-somethingnow.” Thus, there is an expansive definition, Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance broadly shared among the public, of what constitutes a situation that police ought to handle, even if among the police some of those tasks are seen as not police work or treated with disdain. Kelling and Moore (1988) make a cogent argument that three eras of US policing, the political, the reform, and the community problemsolving eras, can be mapped to changes in the authorization and the function of the police. In the political era, in which municipal police agencies were formed, the police derived their legitimacy from the community and their function was to serve that community’s needs. In the reform era, the authorization of the police was narrowed to matters of law, and the police function was dominated by formal law enforcement. In the community and problem-solving era, which Kelling and Moore were forecasting, it was expected that there would be a return to service in the community and recognition of community needs as authorizing police actions. Clearly, service and helping is at the root of much police work, but its emphasis has undergone dynamic change as agencies have grappled with the role of police in a changing society. In some ways, these differing emphases of police agencies represent discretion writ large, as managers have defined, refined, and redefined “what police do” over time. Such institutional variation over time foreshadows contemporary interorganizational differences in coming to grips with what services should be provided to the public. Fundamentals Definition: What Is Service, Help, and Assistance? How to define police service and helping behaviors is a fundamental question that confronts police researchers and police managers alike. Perhaps it is useful to consider what is not service: Arresting a wrongdoer or using force against a suspect, for example, do not appear to be service. However, under careful scrutiny, this quickly turns on an issue of perspective. If police are acting at the behest of another when applying an arrest or forcefully evicting an agitated spouse Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance from a household, then clearly such actions constitute service, at least from the perspective of the requesting citizen. Mastrofski and colleagues (2000) did much to outline police helping behaviors, especially those in which police were mobilized to use their legal powers against another citizen. Furthermore, arrests of individuals who may injure themselves (e.g., the intoxicated or mentally ill) might, broadly defined, constitute service and help. The definition of service and help would seem to hinge on using police power or expertise to advance the well-being of a citizen or a community through formal and informal mechanisms. Service and help should not be understood as a strict and formal application of the law, law enforcement, or deterrence powers police possess. Rather service should be considered to be dominated by, but not exclusively, the informal application of police power. As noted above, however, helping and service is dependent upon perspective and can occasionally emanate from arrests, citations, and other enforcement actions. A second approach to defining police service and helping behaviors is to generate illustrations by way of examples. Police researchers, for example, have engaged in studies of how police spend their time and document what police do for citizens. These actions include taking reports; providing assistance to motorists; making referrals to agencies (such as a juvenile in need of supervision, mentally ill person in need of psychiatric care, victim in need of counseling, or other person in need of assistance outside of the police expertise), transportation (e.g., for juveniles out after curfew), and directed actions (banish, counsel, arrest) on behalf of a requesting citizen; attending to traffic accidents and directing traffic; counseling citizens about self-protection or self-help actions for crime prevention; and providing comfort and first aid to victims. The list is extensive, illustrates great variety, but it is certainly not exhaustive. Police agencies, however, spend little time measuring or systematically rewarding the extent to which police engage in such activities. Thus, little is known about the extent and variety of ways that the public engages the police in service. 3609 P A national snapshot, derived from the National Crime Victimization Survey’s sampling frame, has been collected periodically in the form of the Police Public Contact Survey (PPCS). The PPCS contacts approximately 60,000 citizens over age 18 and asks them about contacts with the police during the previous year. The survey has been administered most recently in 2008, where it was determined that police had approximately 40 million contacts with citizens aged 16 and older. Three categories of contact have broad overlap with police service activities: police response to a traffic accident (12 % of total), police contact involving the reporting of a crime or problem (21 % of total), and police contact emanating from a request for assistance (6 % of total). In all these, three contact types represent almost 16 million or 40 % of the police-citizen contacts estimated from the survey results (Eith and Durose 2011). Though ill-defined, these contacts represent a substantial proportion of the public investment in public safety, yet little is known about the content of these contacts. Measuring Service and Help What can be measured regarding police service and helping behaviors? This question requires a commitment to a level of analysis, and for current purposes, it would be prudent to consider face-to-face contacts between citizens and the police as the unit for consideration. This allows for aggregation to higher levels, such as neighborhoods and organizations for comparisons, and allows for a more thorough consideration of the encounter between police and the client as the unit of work or service delivery. This level of analysis leads to consideration of two aspects of helping behavior, one quantitative, the other qualitative. With respect to quantitative help, clearly one is required to count the presence or absence of a report taken, a referral made, a citizen given first aid, or a child given transportation to his family’s home. The quality of help (service with a smile?) is less amenable to counting but perhaps more influential in how citizens experience police service. That one P P 3610 aspect of service is amenable to counting makes the complex appear deceptively simple. What should be counted? Mastrofski and colleagues (2000) examined how police respond to requests for help in terms of not fulfilling, partially fulfilling, and completely fulfilling requests by citizens asking police to control another person. Thus an enumeration of requests and whether they are fulfilled could be a measure of police reactive service to the public. However, much of what police do may in fact be proactive or at least self-directed service to, or in consultation with, the public. For example, police may follow up a case and refer a domestic violence victim to a legal service, a shelter, or some other services as necessitated by situational dictates, victim preferences, and available resources. This proactive approach to service speaks to both counting as something done in a particular case and also the variety of actions that an officer may take. Capturing variety requires deeper consideration than can be accommodated here, but knowing the possible referrals, resources available to be accessed, and the needs of the individual would be a useful starting point. Thus, accounting for individual instances of services rendered would require attention to both possibilities (referrals to agencies is a good example, since the proliferation and quality varies across cities and even neighborhoods) and appropriateness. Such an approach to measurement would depend on a needs assessment among the service population under study and would be onerous except in the most narrowly conceived execution, such as the services provided by a crisis intervention team to mentally ill individuals encountered. As a general approach to measuring service, it would appear to be too cumbersome to match what police did with what they should have or possibly could have done. Thus, only in specific and welldefined incident or client population types (e.g., the aforementioned provision of service to a mentally ill citizen) would this be a feasible approach. In most efforts to measure the quantity of help, it would appear that counting actions by the police (referrals, assistance offered, aid given) would be the extent to which help could be quantified. Questions of appropriateness and Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance whether needs were addressed become value questions, which would require researchers to know more about what a person needs than may be possible except in all but a few research settings. As Mastrofski (1999) has noted, the quality of service delivery is often as important as the outcome itself. A larger body of procedural justice literature points to quality of treatment and quality of decision-making as being vital elements for understanding police-citizen contacts as antecedents of legitimacy and cooperation. Thus quality of service delivery is separate from whether requests are fulfilled or appropriate referrals are made. Comfort of victims (Foley and Terrill 2008), for example, could be considered a qualitative aspect of the service that police offer to victims of crime. Similarly, respectful treatment of citizens (Mastrofski et al. 1996) is an important part of the quality of service delivery. Measurement of the quality of police-citizen interactions (whether police listen to citizens, whether they inform them of their decisionmaking thought process, whether citizens are allowed to participate in police decision-making, whether police are fair in their decision-making, and so on) has been conducted both via in-person observations and through post contact surveys. The burgeoning literature on the quality of treatment during police-citizen contacts, even when restricted to service type activities, indicates that more just treatment yields citizens who cooperate and comply with the police. Thus, although service contacts are little studied, they represent an important interface where quality policing can have substantial consequences for future support and cooperation with the police. Clearly there is variation in the nature, extent, quality, and variety of services that police can offer to citizens in their everyday encounters. The simplest way to conceive of the encounter is that a person was in need of something and police either did nothing or they did something to ameliorate the situation. As the preceding considerations illustrated, measuring help or service is more complex and opens questions of appropriateness, alternative courses of action, extent of help offered, and the manner in which services Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance are delivered. These dimensions should be considered when the measurement of service is undertaken. One may surmise that measuring service, at the encounter level, is difficult to do well and impossible to do perfectly. However, the challenge should not inhibit researchers or police managers, since this aspect of police work is extensive and a deeper understanding would aid in recognizing it, targeting it, explaining it, and making it a more productive aspect of policing. Explaining Service and Helping If one had a measure of service and help directed toward citizens, what might explain the choices police make in the delivery of services and help? Since the allocation of services by police, in some sense, represents a legal (if informal) intervention, the literature on how police allocate legal outcomes such as arrests or tickets will be considered as a background for understanding discretionary decision-making in the allocation of service. Service could then be understood as an extension of this behavior, and hypotheses developed to explain arrest, use of force, or police issuance of citations would provide a useful framework when extended to service. Thus, the discussion below adopts the following distinctions drawn from this more general literature: need, legal factors and situational factors, officer characteristics and attitudes, neighborhoods, and organizations. These are arrayed from proximal (at the encounter level) to the distal influences (neighborhood routines, organizational resources) and discussed below. Need Mastrofski and colleagues (2000) conducted an analysis involving 396 police-citizen encounters in which citizens requested police help dealing with another person at the scene. An important area of consideration, regarding whether police took actions, was the perceived need of the citizen. This research focused on youthful or elderly status, gender of the requestor, gender of the target, whether the target was intoxicated, and seriousness of the situation as indicators of 3611 P need. Interestingly, in the analysis of citizendirected police assistance, only whether the target was intoxicated had an impact on whether police fulfilled a citizen’s request. Regardless of these initial empirical results, several elements of need are considered here as imperative for discussing, generally, what may influence an officer’s decision to help a citizen. The seriousness of the situation has dual meanings as a motive for police helping behaviors. One is the seriousness related to legal standards, treated below. The second meaning of seriousness would entail the social or physical consequences or harms facing a citizen, which may have no relation to legal seriousness. Not precisely a “legal” variable, the police would likely tend to ameliorate serious problems via helping. Intoxication of citizens and apparent mental illness are thus likely indicia of need that would motivate help or service from the police. The mobilization of the police may be aligned with need as well and may be important for predicting the level of service received in an encounter. Predictions of greater service in proactive encounters or reactive encounters, holding other elements constant, are not straightforward. Where police are mobilized by citizens (i.e., reactive encounters), their presence has greater legitimacy for intervention, especially legal intervention (e.g., Reiss 1971). The reactive encounter may also signal a greater need for resolution in the form of help or service to the citizens. There does not appear to be a clear foundation for whether this legitimacy translates into more formal solutions or more service solutions. Proactive encounters, in contrast, may be more likely to yield services as police initiate such encounters to help, assist, or otherwise provide service to citizens in need. More simply, mobilization of police is likely linked with need, but it is unclear if mobilization has a clear relationship to whether police provide service. Legal and Situational Factors Several legal and situational factors likely shape whether police engage in helping or service behaviors in a particular instance. First, to the extent there is more evidence of wrongdoing, P P 3612 police likely feel activated and obligated to demonstrate a response. In work by Mastrofski and colleagues (2000), when there was greater evidence of wrongdoing, police tended to respond to requests made by citizens desiring a consequence for the wrongdoer. Second, with regard to more serious legal implication, police are likely to help, to a point, and at the highest level of seriousness, they are likely to have less discretion to bring informal sanctions or solutions to bear on the problems they confront. Thus one may speculate an inverted “u” response shape, whereby at low and very high seriousness police have little discretion. In the middle ranges where discretion is high, they likely would engage in more helping and assisting behaviors. Similarly, the prior history of an individual, in terms of misbehavior, would likely influence whether police engage in helping behaviors or revert to more formal handling of situations. In the modern age of technology, the requestor is likely to be “run” against computerized files and evaluated in terms of history as well, both as a complainant and as a potential target against whom which help is mobilized. Situational factors cover a wide variety of variables which may influence discretion. For purposes of this discussion, three are considered: race, social class, and demeanor of the target. Race and ethnicity may be linked with whether police offer more services or help to citizens. Research on arrests, for example, indicates that minorities are more likely to be arrested. In light of those findings, one might expect that minority citizens will receive less informal help and service from the police. Social class is also linked to criminal justice outcomes, and as such, we might expect that lower social class individuals are less likely to receive services relative to their more well-off counterparts. Clearly neither race nor class should matter, but research on other facets of discretionary police decisions lead to hypotheses regarding race and class influencing decisions to give services to individuals. Demeanor of the citizen who is seeking or is in need of service is likely more important than either race or social class. Demeanor refers to Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance whether a citizen is respectful or disrespectful toward the police. In many settings, across eras, demeanor has shown to be a relatively consistent and moderately strong predictor of what legal agents do, in the sense that those citizens with disrespectful demeanors tend to get more negative outcomes (more disrespect from the police, more likely to be arrested, and so on). Thus it is expected that citizens with disrespectful demeanor will receive less service from the police, especially if that service is conceived of as a reward such as provision of service or help. Individual Officer Characteristics Evidence regarding the effect of officer characteristics on discretionary decisions is mixed but certainly it points to no more than a modest to weak effect on legal outcomes. With regard to how officer discretion might be influenced by personal characteristics, we focus on four: education, experience, gender, and officer’s attitudes. Officer education has been shown to have limited effect on performance. With regard to service, it might be expected that officers with greater educational attainment might be more inventive and expansive in their approaches to problems requiring help or service as a possible solution. Research examining whether officers comfort citizens indicates, however, that officers with college degrees provided significantly less comfort to victims when compared to those without college degrees (Foley and Terrill 2008). Similar to the prediction regarding college education, experience, which is arguably the best teacher, should allow for more inventive and helpful behaviors to be routinely developed. These would manifest as possibilities for solving presenting situations and become routine for officers with longer times on the job. Again, however, the research of Foley and Terrill (2008) found officers with more experience less likely to comfort victims. Gender is controversial, in the sense that associating female officers with a greater capacity for helping appears, on its face, sexist. However, Foley and Terrill (2008) found that female officers were no more likely to comfort victims than their male counterparts. Nevertheless, gender may be a proxy for Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance attitudes regarding the expansiveness of the police mandate and reflect both socialization and attitudinal patterns. Officer attitudes toward work vary and would appear to be important for determining how individuals choose to execute facets of their work. For example, Michael Brown (1988) argued that selectivity and aggressiveness were two key dimensions for typifying officer styles. Among these styles some officers would be much more likely to narrowly define the appropriate tasks for “police work.” In fact, Brown argued that there was an identifiable “service style” in which some officers adopted a more helping role rather than strictly law enforcement roles. Similarly, William K. Muir’s observations of officers’ orientations toward service and helping, in the 1970s, found officers who defined some work as civil issues (e.g., landlord-tenant disputes) and explicitly sought to avoid such situations. The emergence of the community policing model in the 1980s and 1990s more broadly defined police mandates and thus provides cover for officers to adopt more helping orientations toward their work. Neighborhood Context The neighborhoods in which police encounter citizens provide the backdrop or setting for face-to-face interactions. Aspects of neighborhoods have been shown to influence what police do during encounters. Those neighborhoods that are characterized by higher poverty, often measured by researchers as concentrated disadvantage which combines indicators of race, poverty, and employment, have been linked with greater likelihood of police arrests and use of force against citizens in prior research. These same neighborhoods are likely to demand greater service from the police. In the aggregate they may receive greater numbers of police helping services. However, at the level of individual interactions between police and citizens, it is likely that those in disadvantaged neighborhoods receive less service relative to those in wealthier or more advantaged neighborhoods. In part this could be a consequence of police formal authority undermining many of the sources of local 3613 P social regulation. Or it could be that there is an absence of collective efficacy, upon which police can draw informal solutions that can be enforced by informal social control networks in these neighborhoods. In either scenario the literature leads to the prediction that police will, when confronted with similar situations, exercise less helping behavior in the more disadvantaged neighborhoods. Organizational Context In a classic study of police at the organizational level, James Q. Wilson’s Varieties of Police Behaviors examined how departments molded their responses to the political environment. It is telling that in low-crime, more wealthy locales, the police were considered primarily a service function. Though the research is more than 40 years old, the contrast between Oakland, CA, and Nassau County in Long Island and the legalistic style (defining work in terms of application of the law) and the service style (defining work in terms of what the police can do for the public and what the public wants) anticipated the movement toward community policing and the explicit recognition of “what the public wants.” This research also indicates that organizational commitment to service likely influences officers’ discretion in their day-to-day work. Contemporary organizational adaptation to servicing public needs may be most comprehensively studied in Chicago, IL, (Skogan 2006) where neighborhood policing was specifically aimed at understanding community needs and trying to accommodate them. The Chicago Alternative Policing Strategy (CAPS) explicitly tapped the community to assess needs and targeted police activity toward problems such as graffiti abatement projects and efforts at removing abandoned cars from neighborhoods. This menu of responses is a far departure from the strictly conceived law enforcement mandate and illustrates how variation at the organizational level is likely to influence police discretion. The mechanism by which this operates is the expanded mandate of what police should do coupled with an effort to understand community needs. Officers working under such regimes are P P 3614 likely to develop a larger palette of helping responses when compared to those working in more legalistic environments. At the organizational level, one could thus measure variations in how organizations array themselves across a legal/service continuum. Organizational commitment to service could be measured in a variety of ways including information sources collected in assessing needs, varieties of services offered by police, interfaces by police agencies with other service agencies, and the extent to which performance measures are guided by service roles of the agency (i.e., does the agency count “problems solved”). It should be clear that police managers and researchers alike have little direct experience in measuring service and predicting “who gets what.” For example, among those variables considered to be important characteristics of officers, experience and college education are both hypothesized to relate to greater levels of helping. However, at least with respect to comfort to victims, Foley and Terrill (2008) drew the opposite conclusion. In more recent research, Rossler and Terrill (2012) examined police responses to citizen requests to file reports, act on their behalf with an agency, provide information, or provide physical help. In these analyses, officers’ college education had no impact on whether or the extent to which officers fulfilled the request. But college-educated officers were less inclined to provide an explanation when denying a request. This is a sign that caution should be exercised in forecasting how police may exercise their ability to help in faceto-face encounters and a clear indicator for more data collection, measurement, and theory development. Although some propositions are introduced here regarding need, situational and legal factors, officer characteristics, and neighborhood and organizational context, none of them have been sufficiently tested against observations to a point where one could make statements of any empirical regularity with confidence. The absence of this knowledge is welcome territory for future scholarship but currently a barren landscape from which to make suggestions for police managers, policy for organizations, or to yield strong theory from which to begin analyses. Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance Current Issues Considering Problem-Oriented Policing, Community Policing, and Service Responsibilities Herman Goldstein (1990) observed that when the unit of work patrol for patrol was defined as a “case,” then police often missed larger problems that are frequently the underlying generator of calls for service. Such an underlying problem can generate many cases which are resolved by a response, a report, and perhaps an arrest. A drug market, for example, might generate calls of nuisance behaviors and police may respond and disperse suspected dealers, take a report from a complainant, or perhaps make an arrest of an individual for possession, then return to duty. If the unit of work is the call, then this call is satisfied. If the unit of work is defined as a problem, then the problem has not been addressed by the actions described. The problem-oriented policing approach outlines a variety of sources of problems such as homelessness, bar hours, public health hazards such as litter and trash, and a broader palette of incivilities both physical and social that may be considered within the sphere of problems. These larger categories may have an ambiguous relationship to the legal power of police and therefore are easy for organizations and officers to avoid, if so inclined. However, once engaged in problem-oriented policing that is consistent with the scanning, analysis, response, and assessment approach outlined by Eck and Spelman (1987), the likelihood that services and helping behaviors and referrals will be accessed increases. For example, interagency partnerships can form the backbone of these approaches as illustrated by the Beat Health program in Oakland, CA. Here the Oakland police department addressed decay and disorder via partnerships with other public agencies as well as private place managers such as landlords. In this case the service provided is creating a more ordered and civil public space in which conventional citizens may engage in legitimate daily pursuits. Conversely, confronting the problems in the local spaces discouraged the illegitimate use of spaces by, for example, street-level drug dealers. Thus a legal problem was solved by a service Police Discretion in Providing Services and Assistance approach. So the gray area between civil and criminal was straddled in the Oakland experiment as documented by Mazerolle and Roehl (1999), whereas, two decades earlier, Muir (1977) working with the Laconia (a pseudonym) department found that officers tended to deny responsibility for cases that were civil in nature. The blending of the civil and criminal authorities within local law enforcement, from a legal perspective, may be another area for future consideration. The nature of public regulation, compliance, and obedience is dramatically different in the 2010s than in the 1970s when the theoretical foundations for much criminal justice research on police and their behavior was being established (Reiss 1971; Brown 1988; Muir 1977). This transformation is undoubtedly related to the community policing movement and its explicit desire to deactivate the legalistic mindset that defined police work in terms of criminal law (e.g., Kelling and Moore 1988). More expansive definitions of police work will broaden what police can do and will also provide opportunities to study and understand why police make choices to help or provide service in some instances, but not others. Populations in Need of Services: The Mentally Ill Lurigio and colleagues (2008) have outlined the contemporary scene with regard to the extent to which police process the mentally ill and point out that the jail systems in Chicago, New York (Rikers Island), and Los Angeles represent the largest mental health facilities in the United States. Consideration of the mentally ill clients as persons in need of help mirrors some of the civil/criminal tension that has characterized the consideration of police service and helping behaviors. The police contact with the mentally ill is not a new subject for academic study as these contacts have long been considered an important part of police repertoire and a very difficult problem to handle with only legal tools such as arrest and coercion (Muir 1977). In many ways, bridging service and legal processing for this population has been a continuous challenge for streetlevel policing. Adoption of crisis intervention 3615 P teams, collaboration built around psychiatric services and police, and emphasis on training officers for the difficulties inherent in encounters of the mentally ill point to efforts to shape discretion with respect to this particular population. Interestingly the movement has first recognized that police are often the first line of contact for mentally ill individuals, and to handle this exigency, agencies have trained and developed resources targeted specifically toward this population’s needs. Equipping police with greater structure and resources shapes discretion but broadens possibilities of what police can do. Summary and Future Directions Police have always engaged in helping and service behaviors. Despite this, modern scholars and managers alike are hard pressed to measure, theorize, and evaluate the effectiveness of these actions. This stems from recognition that the mandate upon which helping behaviors rests is clearly not as strong as the law enforcement mandate, which is rooted in law and linked to fundamental issues involving the exercise and control of coercive force. Thus systematic study of helping has been largely overlooked, unmeasured, and, unfortunately, unrewarded. As the public comes to expect more service from police agencies, especially in times of economic hardship and social consequences that accompany it, there is likely to be greater pressure to systematically measure and evaluate this aspect of police work. Among police researchers, similarly, there is likely to be a movement to test propositions about “who gets what” from police in terms of services rendered. As noted here it is possible to speculate about how neighborhood characteristics, citizen race and ethnicity, and citizen social class relate to service delivery patterns; in truth, these are open research questions yet to be thoroughly addressed. Nevertheless, efforts to adopt the community and problem-solving approaches have driven police organizations and the officers within them to embrace a greater service role, absent information on how such service is delivered. Given this P P 3616 situation it is likely that much research will be targeted at best practices of service delivery, especially with regard to services targeted at special populations, such as the mentally ill. Related Entries ▶ Community Policing ▶ Measuring Police Performance ▶ Police Discretion and Its Control ▶ Police Discretion in Law Enforcement ▶ Police Family Violence Services ▶ Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters ▶ Policing Special Populations Recommended Reading and References Bittner E (1990) Florence Nightingale in pursuit of Willie Sutton: a theory of the police. In: Bittner E (ed) Aspects of police work. Northeastern University, Boston Brown MK (1988) Working the street: police discretion and the dilemmas of reform. Russell Sage, New York Cumming E, Cumming I, Edell L (1965) Policeman as philosopher, guide and friend. Soc Probl 12(1):276–286 Eck JE, Spelman W (1987) Problem-solving: problemoriented policing in Newport news. Police Executive Research Forum, Washington, DC Eith C, Durose MR (2011) Contacts between police and the public, 2008. Special report. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington, DC Foley T, Terrill W (2008) Police comfort and victims. Vict Offender 3(2):192–216 Goldstein H (1990) Problem-oriented policing. McGrawHill, New York Guyot D (1991) Policing as though people matter. Temple University Press, Philadelphia Harring S (1983) Policing a class society. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick Kelling GL, Moore MH (1988) The evolving strategy of policing. Perspectives on policing, vol 4. National Institute of Justice, Washington, DC Lane R (1967) Policing the city: Boston 1822–1885. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Lurigio AJ, Smith A, Harris A (2008) The challenge of responding to people with mental illness: police officer training and special programmes. Police J 81:295–322 Mastrofski SD (1999) Policing for people. Police Foundation, Washington, DC Mastrofski S, Snipes J, Supina A (1996) Compliance on demand: the public’s response to specific police requests. J Res Crime Delinq 33:269–305 Police Family Violence Services Mastrofski S, Snipes J, Parks R, Maxwell C (2000) The helping hand of the law: police control of citizens on request. Criminology 38:307–342 Mazerolle L, Roehl J (1999) Controlling drug and disorder problems: a focus on Oakland’s beat health program. National Institute of Justice, Washington, DC Monkkonen E (1981) Police in urban America, 1860–1920. Cambridge University Press, New York Muir WK (1977) Police: streetcorner politicians. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Reiss AJ Jr (1971) The police and the public. Yale University Press, Connecticut Rossler MT, Terrill W (2012) Police responsiveness to service-related requests. Police Quart 15(1):3–24 Skogan W (2006) Police and community in Chicago: a tale of three cities. Oxford University Press, New York Skogan W, Frydl K (eds) (2004) Fairness and effectiveness in policing: the evidence. The National Academies Press, Washington, DC Von Hoffman A (1992) An officer of the neighborhood: a Boston patrolman on the beat in 1895. JSoc Hist 2(Winter):309–330 Wilson JQ (1968) Varieties of police behavior: the management of law and order in eight communities. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Police Family Violence Services Robert C. Davis and Sarah Greathouse RAND Corporation, Arlington, VA, USA Overview In recent years a number of programs have been developed in which the initial police response to a family violence incident is followed by a visit from a trained team of officers or by an officer and a social worker. These “second responders” attempt to help victims find long-term solutions to recurring abuse (e.g. see Dean et al. 2000; Mickish 2002). Second responder programs are based on the premises that family violence often recurs and that victims are likely to be especially receptive to crime prevention opportunities immediately following victimization. That is, there is a “window of opportunity” during the first hours or days after a crime during which victims feel vulnerable and are willing to seriously consider behavioral and lifestyle changes Police Family Violence Services (Davis and Smith 1994; Anderson et al. 1995). The response often takes the form of a home visit but other times consist of a phone call to the victim. The team provides the victim with information on services and legal options and (in some models) may warn those perpetrators present at the follow-up of the legal consequences of continued abuse. The purpose of working directly with the victims is to reduce the likelihood of a new offense by helping them to understand the cyclical nature of family violence, develop a safety plan, obtain a restraining order, increase their knowledge about legal rights and options, and provide shelter placement or other relocation assistance. A secondary aim of the intervention with victims may be to establish greater independence for victims through counseling, job training, public assistance, or other social service referrals. The purpose of conversations with abusers is to ensure that they understand that assaulting an intimate is criminal and that further abuse will result in (additional) sanctions. Key Issues History of Family Violence Officers The role of police family violence services has evolved over time. Prior to the 1970s, law enforcement’s response to family violence was significantly limited. Departments rarely contained specialized teams to respond to incidents of family violence. Responses by general patrol to family violence incidents were often slow or nonexistent (Ford 1983; Manning 1988). When police did respond to service calls, departmental policies often dictated that officers should only attempt to diffuse the immediate situation and subsequently refer the individuals to social service agencies; arrests of the perpetrator were rarely made and follow-ups to the initial call for service were rarely conducted (Hutchison et al. 1996; Parnas 1967). This lack of attention to family violence issues by law enforcement reflected both societal beliefs about family violence and traditional law enforcement culture. Family disputes were commonly viewed 3617 P as private affairs, and it was believed that police’s role in handling family disputes should be one of mediators and references to social services (Breslin 1978). As such, police officers often viewed responses to domestic disputes as not “real” police work (Buzawa and Buzawa 2003). Surveys of police officers’ attitudes toward domestic violence, specifically, showed that police believed arrests to be futile because victims would rarely follow through to press charges and that arresting the male head of household would negatively impact the family as a whole. Police also endorsed the commonly held but incorrect belief that responses to domestic disputes placed the officer in greater danger compared to other calls (Buzawa and Buzawa 2003). As a result, law enforcement devoted little attention to family violence issues; even less attention and resources was devoted to taking actions that reduced further incidents of violence. The law enforcement response to family violence began to become significantly more proactive in the 1970s and 1980s. Several events were catalyst for the change. First, victim’s rights advocacy groups and feminist groups began to challenge the police’s lack of forceful responses to domestic disputes and their failure to protect female victims of domestic violence (Buzawa and Buzawa 2003). Second, a series of legal cases in the 1970s and 1980s ruled that police departments could be held liable and face financial penalties if they failed to protect victims of family violence (Bruno v Codd 1977; Tracey Thurman et al. 1984). Finally, empirical research around this same time began to demonstrate that the actions taken by police had the potential to reduce incidents of family violence. One of the most influential empirical studies of police response to incidents of family violence was an evaluation of police departments that employed violence family crisis intervention units (FCIU’s) (Bard 1975). Originally developed by psychologists, officers in this program received training in mediating and diffusing domestic disputes. While the officers still responded to all calls for service, they were specifically called in to handle family violence P P 3618 calls. The National Institute of Justice sponsored a training and demonstration program that employed 10 family crisis intervention units in police departments across the country. The evaluation of these programs reported some positive effects of FCIU’s, including decreases in arrests and officer injuries (Bard 1975). Although this evaluation also found that calls for service to family violence incidents increased, this finding was explained as evidence of the FCIU’s increasing victims’ faith in the ability of the police to effectively handle incidents of family violence. As a result of the reported success of these programs, many major US police departments began adopting either FCIU’s or specialized units comprised of law enforcement and social service workers (Liebman and Schwartz 1973). Often funded with federal funds, these officers were specially trained in handling victim needs and problems and in keeping themselves safe during home visits. However, responses to FCIU’s were not all positive. Liebman and Schwartz (1973) reported that New York City’s highly praised FCIU’s program had resulted in increased homicides and domestic disputes. Critical research findings, coupled with strategic difficulties in implementing specialized units, led many departments to completely cut or severely limit the role of family violence response units. In the 1980s, police departments shifted focus from specialized family violence policing services to arrest and punishment of those individuals that perpetrate family violence. Several research studies were major forces in changing the manner in which police responded to family violence. The most prominent of these studies was an experimental evaluation of police responses to domestic violence conducted in Minneapolis, Minnesota (Sherman and Berk 1984). In this study, police who responded to domestic violence calls were randomly assigned to handle the dispute in one of three ways: (1) separate the parties (2) mediate the dispute (3) make an arrest. The researchers reported that making an arrest resulted in significantly fewer further domestic disputes between the couple. Although the study received some Police Family Violence Services criticism from the scientific community (Binder and Meeker 1988; Lempert 1989), the results from this experiment were highly publicized and spurred mandatory arrest laws in many jurisdictions and arrest oriented policies in police departments across the country. This focus on deterring future violent behavior through arrest took precedent over employing specialized family violence units or secondary responder programs. Although the criminal justice system has been largely focused on reducing repeated incidents of family violence through arrest and prosecution, in recent years there has been recognition that these policies may not be enough to effectively address and reduce incidents of family violence. Research studies have not always reported positive effects for pro-arrest policies (Dunford et al. 1990; Hirschel et al. 1992). In addition, despite a strong emphasis on pro-arrest policies, prior research reports a high chance of revictimization for victims of domestic violence, particularly immediately after the original incident of abuse (Lloyd et al. 1994). This research raised recognition that more needed to be done to assist and empower victims of family violence. As a result, a growing number of police departments began to adopt or re-adopt specialized family violence service units that provide secondary responses to victims following the initial call for service. Although the total number of such programs is not known, we do know a number of specialized programs across the United States and Great Britain have been implemented and evaluated. The research examining the effects of these specific programs will be discussed later in this article. In recent years, law enforcement has also become increasingly aware of the need for specific units to address a special type of family violence, elder abuse. Traditionally, elder abuse was not considered a serious criminal problem. Law enforcement officers did not often receive specialized training to handle reports of elder abuse, and departments rarely seriously pursued elder abuse cases (Plotkin 1988). Recent research has demonstrated that incidents of elder abuse are much more prevalent than previously believed Police Family Violence Services (Tatara et al. 1997). As a result, a growing number of departments have established specialized units to handle cases of elder abuse (Heisler 2000). Because cases of elder abuse are often complex, specialized law enforcement often coordinates with local prosecutors and social service agencies to investigate reports of elder abuse and work with the victims. Training of Family Violence Officers Historically, police officers have received very minimal training about how to handle calls to incidents of family violence. A survey of law enforcement’s training practices during the 1970s revealed that most often police officers received a limited amount of training on handling family violence during a half-day to 1 day training on responding to calls with disturbed individuals (Buzawa and Buzawa 2003). This module of training addressed a variety of situations and didn’t solely focus on handling family disputes. Many of the training programs also simply reinforced the idea that police officers should only play a minimal role in handling incidents of family violence. Once on the job, officers rarely received continued training on handling family violence. The most common method of educating young officers came through observations of more experienced officers’ responses to incidents of family violence. Today, more structured training programs focusing on intervention strategies, arrest policies, and attitudes toward domestic/family violence are in existence. The International Chiefs of Police and other national organizations have produced recommended requirements for domestic violence training, and an increasing number of states are requiring their law enforcement officers to receive family violence training (Miller 1997). Although officer training on domestic violence may be more detailed, the amount of training officers typically received has not significantly increased. One survey found that on average officers receive 10 h of initial domestic violence training. Once in the field, most officers are not required to shadow officers who are experienced in handling family violence, 3619 P and the quality of on-going training programs can vary significantly, from short videos to in-class trainings with role playing activities (Buzawa and Buzawa 2003). A growing number of states are also requiring officers to receiving training on elder abuse (Heisler 2000). Although national organizations such as the Police Executive Forum have distributed recommended practices for training officer on elder abuse, little information exists on the training practices of specific departments. Little information also exists on the typical methods used to train individuals within any specialized family violence or secondary responder units. Because there are not standardized methods for operating specialized family violence service units, methods of training these team members vary by department. Functions of Domestic Violence Officers Redlands, CA Police Department had a robust domestic violence officer program that was the subject of an NIJ-funded evaluation. Consequently, detailed information on what these officers did are contained in the evaluation report. The following description of the functions of family violence officers draws heavily on the report by Davis et al. (2010). In Redlands, a team of officers, including a trained female domestic violence detective, attempted to visit households within either 24 h or 7 days of a domestic complaint depending on the severity of the incident. According to the officers conducting the second responses, contact was made with the victims at their homes in 84 % of the cases in which it was attempted. In cases where the home visit attempt was not successful, literature was left with information about community services. The visits typically lasted 30–45 min, depending on the victim’s receptiveness to assistance. The goals of home visits were to ensure that the victim had information about and access to resources and services, to answer any questions they had about the complaint or the justice process, and to encourage a sense of trust in the police and the criminal justice system as a whole. P P 3620 A written protocol guided the officer or officers making home visits. The visits began by the officer talking to the victim about the recent incident and any immediate safety concerns that she had. The officer discussed with the victim the nature of domestic violence and the very real possibility that the incident she experienced would recur if no action was taken. The officer tried to make the victim understand that the police department took the matter seriously and was there to assist her. She also asked the victim a series of questions about her relationship with the abuser, history of abuse, and the presence of children and weapons in the home. Once preliminaries were taken care of, the second response officer tried to ensure that the victim had information about resources and services; offered practical assistance; worked with the victim to develop a safety plan; and instructed the victim in how to document future abusive or stalking behaviors. Before leaving, the officer provided the victim with a written description of local resources to assist domestic violence victims, including housing relocation, counseling, domestic violence shelters, medical help, civil legal assistance, information about the criminal justice process, aid in applying for an order of relief, and emergency financial assistance. Referrals were most often made to counseling programs or parenting classes; smaller numbers of victims were referred to shelters, civil legal assistance, assistance in obtaining a restraining order, and district attorney victim advocates. One concern about conducting second response visits was that the visit might trigger anger in the perpetrator. To avoid this, there was an intentional practice to call ahead to make sure perpetrators were not present when the officers came to the home. However, since officers were not always able to reach victims by phone ahead of time, there were some instances in which the perpetrator was there when the officers arrived. While partners were home during just a handful of visits, nearly half (46 %) of victims said in subsequent interviews that their partners were aware that the visit occurred. Of these, Police Family Violence Services approximately one in four (28 %) reported that their partner had a negative reaction to the visit. The Chicago Police Department has a similar second responder program for victims of elder abuse. Each Chicago police district has a designated elder abuse officer whose job it is to provide services to those victims. During the course of their home visits, the elder abuse officers ensure that victims’ medical and physical needs (food and shelter) are being met. When they are not, officers arrange for temporary shelter. They make referrals to social service programs, including counseling, independent living services, Meals on Wheels, and programs for Alzheimer’s patients. Officers also enroll victims in emergency identification bracelet program so police responding to future incidents can quickly grasp history and information on victim, assist victims in completing forms to receive state compensation, and provide assistance getting to court. Finally, a report is made to adult protective services. Effectiveness There have been a number of high quality evaluations of second responder programs yielding conflicting results. Several randomized field trials of second responder programs were conducted in New York City public housing projects. Each tested the same intervention model: persons who reported family violence to the police were randomly assigned to receive or not to receive a follow-up visit from a domestic violence police officer and a social worker. This follow-up visit was not immediate, as is the case with most second responder programs, but occurred an average of 2 weeks later. The sample for one of the studies (Davis and Taylor 1997) included instances where someone had called the police in response to a family violence incident (this could be violence between romantic intimates, sibling violence, elder abuse, or other forms of violence between persons related or living under the same roof). The incidents were minor in nature (only 7 % of the incidents resulted in arrests and just 14 % of victims reported any form of injury). Police Family Violence Services Four hundred and thirty-five victims were randomly assigned to receive a home visit as a follow-up to the patrol response. The control group received only the initial police patrol response. Additional calls for police services were tracked for both groups over the next 6 months. At the end of the tracking period, researchers interviewed victims to ask about new abuse, about satisfaction with the police response, and about victims’ knowledge and use of social services. According to law enforcement records, households that received the home visit intervention were more likely to call the police during the subsequent 6 months than households that did not receive the interventions. Yet, according to victim survey data, there were no differences between the two groups in abuse during the 6 months following the trigger incident. In the literature on the effectiveness of arrest on curbing violence, victim reports and calls to the police usually are both treated as imperfect indicators measuring an underlying construct of actual violence. However, the two measures clearly are not synonymous. Many family violence victimizations are not reported to the police. Davis & Taylor interpreted this pattern of results to mean that the experimental interventions did not affect actual violence levels but did increase victims’ confidence in the police and made victims more willing to report violence when it occurred. A second experimental investigation (Davis and Medina 2001) of the same intervention was conducted several years later, this time using a sample of 402 public housing residents who had reported elder abuse incidents to the police. Like the cases in the first field test, incidents in this study were also relatively minor (5 % of the abusers were arrested, just 4 % of victims reported any injuries, and in only 22 % of the cases was a crime alleged to have occurred). Once again, law enforcement records for these households were tracked for the next 6 months. As in the first experiment, it was found that victims who received the home visit intervention called the police sooner and more often than controls. 3621 P Pooled analyses of these and a third unpublished experiment indicated that the interventions were associated with an increase in reporting of new abusive incidents not only to authorities (which could indicate simply greater confidence in the police), but also to research interviewers (Davis et al. 2006). The New York field tests suggested that second response programs might actually increase the likelihood of new abuse. Going into these studies, it had been assumed that the effects of the interventions would be to empower victims through information about their situation, available services, and legal options. The program logic model posited that new abuse would decline as victims extracted themselves from self-defeating relationships or worked with social services and criminal justice staff to develop strategies to end the abuse while staying in the relationship. However, researchers in the New York studies found no evidence that those who received the interventions were more likely to avail themselves of social or legal services, so the intervention could not have worked – at least not in the way intended. Some evaluations of other second responder programs found results similar to the New York field tests. A subsequent study by one of the authors of the New York evaluations, this one conducted in Redlands, CA, found that households that received a second response had worse outcomes on seven measures of new abuse, although the results were not statistically significant (Davis et al. 2010). Two studies conducted in New Haven, CT by Stover and her associates (Stover et al. 2009, 2010) found between them that persons who received a second response were more likely to call the police again, but less likely to report new abuse on victim surveys. A study by Hovell et al. (2006) found more reports of abuse to the police among victims who received a second response. Other studies however, reported a positive effect of second responder programs. Greenspan et al. (2003) found that victims who received a second response in Richmond, VA were less likely to report victimization on a subsequent P P Model 3622 Study name Davis and Taylor, 1997 Taylor, n.d. Davis and Medina, 2001 Davis et al., 2007 Pate et al., 1992 Casey et al., 2007 Hovell et al., 2006 Stover et al., unpublished (1) Fixed Random Police Family Violence Services Statistics for each study Std diff in means Standard error p-Value 0.10982 −0.07428 0.28159 0.02293 0.10586 −0.60351 0.29255 0.35616 0.11605 0.08162 0.10987 0.20002 0.12347 0.15211 0.09207 0.17643 0.10849 0.17587 0.04545 0.08813 0.31753 0.71036 0.02257 0.88015 0.25027 0.00062 0.00700 0.04286 0.01067 0.35438 Std diff in means and 95% CI -1.00 -0.50 0.00 Favours Control 0.50 1.00 Favours Treatment Police Family Violence Services, Fig. 1 Fixed and random effects models for reports of abuse to the police: experimental and quasi-experimental designs survey. Pate et al (1992) also found a decrease in subsequent violence reported on a survey following a second response in Dade County, FL. Casey et al. (2007) reported fewer calls made to the police among victims who received a second response in New Haven, CT. Davis et al. (2008) conducted a meta-analysis of second responder programs. The analysis concluded that the odds of reporting new abuse to the police were about 1-1/4 times higher for households assigned to a home visit treatment. The meta-analysis found no difference between treatments in reports of new abuse on research surveys (see Fig. 1 below). In sum, then, the weight of the evidence does not indicate that second responder programs reduce new instances of abuse and may, in fact, increase subsequent calls to the police – possibly because the intervention generates more actual abuse or possibly because people who receive a second response have more confidence in the police. Related Entries ▶ Domestic Violence ▶ Measuring Police Unit Performance ▶ Randomized Experiments in Criminology and Criminal Justice Recommended Reading and References Anderson D, Chenery S, Pease K (1995) Biting back, tackling repeat burglary and car crime. Crime Detection & Prevention Series Paper 58. Home Office, London Bard M (1975) Role of law enforcement in the helping system. In: Coffey AR, Renner JE (eds) Criminal justice as a system: readings. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, pp 56–66 Binder A, Meeker JW (1988) Experiments as reforms. J Crim Justice 16:347–358 Breslin WJ (1978) Police intervention in domestic confrontation. J Police Sci Adm 6:293–302 Bruno v. Codd, 396 N.Y.S. 2nd 974, NY Sup Ct (1977) Buzawa ES, Buzawa CG (2003) Domestic violence: the criminal justice response. Sage, Newbury Park Casey RL, Berkman M, Stover CS, Gill K, Durso S, Marans S (2007) Preliminary results of a police-advocate home-visit intervention project for Victims of domestic violence. J Psychol Trauma 61:39–49 Davis RC, Medina J (2001) Results from an elder abuse prevention experiment in New York City. National Institute of Justice Research in Brief. U.S. Department of Justice, Washington, DC Davis RC, Smith B (1994) Teaching victims crime prevention skills: can individuals lower their risk of crime? Crim Justice Rev 19:56–68 Davis RC, Taylor B (1997) Evaluating a proactive police response to domestic violence: the results of a randomized experiment. Criminology 35:307–333 Davis RC, Maxwell C, Taylor B (2006) Preventing repeat incidents of family violence: analysis of data from three field experiments. J Exp Criminol 2:183–210 Davis RC, Weisburd DW, Taylor B (2008) Effects of second responder programs on repeat incidents of family abuse. Campbell Collaboration Systematic Police in Nazi Germany Review. http://db.c2admin.org/doc-pdf/Davis_2ndresp_review.pdf Davis RC, Weisburd D, Hamilton EH (2010) Preventing repeat incidents of family violence: a randomized field test of a second responder program. J Exp Criminol 6:397–418 Dean CW, Lumb R, Proctor K, Klopovic J, Hyatt A, Hamby R (2000) Social work and police partnership: a summons to the village strategies and effective practices. A report of the Charlotte-Mecklenburg Police Department and the University of North Carolina at Charlotte. North Carolina Governor’s Crime Commission, Raleigh Dunford FW, Huizinga D, Elliot DS (1990) The role of arrest in domestic assault: the Omaha police experiment. Criminology 28:183–206 Ford DA (1983) Wife battery and criminal justice: a study of victim decision-making. Fam Relat 32:463–475 Greenspan R, Weisburd D, Lane E, Ready J, CrossenPowell S, Booth WC (2003) The Richmond/Police Foundation domestic violence partnership. Police Foundation, Washington, DC Heisler CJ (2000) Elder abuse and the criminal justice system: new awareness, new responses. Generations 24:52–58 Hirschel JD, Hutchison IW, Dean CW (1992) The failure of arrest to deter spouse abuse. J Res Crime Delinquency 29:7–33 Hovell MF, Seid AG, Liles S (2006) Evaluation of a police and social services domestic violence program: empirical evidence needed to inform public health policies. Violence Against Women 12:137–159 Hutchison IW, Hirschel JD, Pesackis CE (1996) Family violence and police utilization. Violence Vict 9:299–313 Lempert R (1989) Humility is a virtue: on the publicization of policy relevant research. Law Soc Rev 23:145–161 Liebman DA, Schwartz JA (1973) Police programs in domestic crisis intervention: a review. In: Snibbe JR, Snibbe JM (eds) The urban policeman in transition. Charles C. Thomas, Springfield, pp 421–472 Lloyd S, Farrell G, Pease K (1994) Preventing repeated domestic violence: a demonstration project on Merseyside, vol 49, Crime prevention unit paper. Home Office, London Manning P (1988) Symbolic interaction: signifying calls and police response. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA Mickish JE (2002) Domestic violence. In: Byers BD, Hendricks JE (eds) Crisis intervention in criminal justice/social services, 3rd edn. Charles C. Thomas, Springfield, pp 77–118 Miller N (1997) Domestic violence legislation affecting police and prosecutor responsibilities in the United States: inferences from a 50-state review of state statutory codes. Institute for Law and Justice, Alexandria Parnas RI (1967) The police response to the domestic disturbance. Wis Law Rev 2:914–930 3623 P Pate A, Hamilton EE, Anan S (1992) Metro-Dade spouse abuse replication project technical report. Police Foundation, Washington, DC Plotkin MR (1988) A time for dignity: police and domestic abuse of the elderly. American Association of Retired Persons (AARP), Washington, DC Sherman LA, Berk RA (1984) The specific deterrent effects of arrest for domestic assault. Am Sociol Rev 49:261–272 Stover CS, Poole G, Marans S (2009) The domestic violence home visit intervention: impact on police reported incidents of repeat violence over twelve months. Violence Victims 24(5):591–606 Stover CS, Berkman M, Desai R, Marans S (2010) The efficacy of a police-advocacy intervention for victims of domestic violence: 12-month follow-up data. Violence Against Women 16(4):410–425 Tatara R, Kuzmeskus MA, Duckhorn E (1997) Domestic elder abuse information series. National Center on Elder Abuse, Washington, DC Taylor B (n.d.) Do home visits reduce repeat domestic abuse calls to the police? Unpublished paper Tracey Thurman et al. v. City of Torrington, Connecticut, 595 F. Supp. 1521 (D. Connecticut 1984) Police Federations ▶ History of Police Unions Police in Nazi Germany 1 Herbert Reinke and Thomas Roth 1 Bergische Universit€at Wuppertal, Wuppertal, Germany 2 NS-Dokumentationszentrum der Stadt Ko¨ln, Ko¨ln, Germany P 2 Overview Dictatorial regimes, not only in Europe but in many other countries outside Europe as well, have used and still use today the police for terrorizing and for controlling political opponents and for maintaining the power of the regime. The Nazi movement went far beyond this when getting hold of the police after their seizure of power. P 3624 While the Nazi regime particularly at its beginning drew on traditional police forces and started from authoritarian goals and strategies of police work, it rapidly generated a radical new kind of police organization, with a specific corps of officers, committed to Nazi ideology, and a radical concept of policing, focused on racial categories and the goal of systematically cleansing society of all groups labeled as deviant. During the Nazi years, the maintenance of “law and order” and crime control and the persecution of political opponents became increasingly intertwined with policies of racial, often total, exclusion. A police force evolved not only supporting but promoting politics of genocide. Police in Nazi Germany: Institutional Contexts Since the beginnings of modern policing in Germany during the nineteenth century, and due to federalism as a core characteristic of the German political system, the police had always been under the command of the federal states. There has never been, except for the Nazi period, a large-scale and centralized national police. “Police” meant, and still means primarily, the polices of the L€ander, federal states (i.e., before 1933 Prussia, Bavaria, Saxonia, etc.). This institutional context remained unchanged until the end of the Weimar Republic. Although demands were put forward during the 1920s for more centralization, in particular for fighting crime more effectively, a centralized police apparatus did not emerge before 1933. In July 1932, the conservative German Reichsregierung, the national government, had the middle-left Prussian government on the basis of an emergency decree dismissed, constituting a kind of prelude to the institutional changes, which took place after the Nazi seizure of power. In 1932, a presumed incapacity for maintaining law and order was given as a reason for the replacement of the Prussian government (senior police officers included) by commissioners, installed by the national government. Police in Nazi Germany After the Nazi seizure of power at the end of January 1933, a leading and prominent figure of the Nazi party, Hermann Go¨ring, was commissioned to direct the Prussian Ministry of the Interior. This position served as a basis for getting hold of the Prussian uniformed police and the Kriminalpolizei (Kripo, Criminal Police) as power instruments for consolidating the Nazi regime. Two emergency decrees, issued in the weeks after the Nazi seizure of power, suspended the basic constitutional rights of the citizens, thus providing the Nazi regime with the capacities for prosecuting ruthlessly its political opponents. These two emergency decrees issued in February 1933 served until the end of the Nazi regime as a pseudo-legal basis for the unlimited police power of the regime. Another leading and prominent figure of the Nazi party, Heinrich Himmler, became head of the Bavarian Political Police soon after the Nazi seizure of power. Thereafter, until the first months of 1934, Heinrich Himmler gained the command of most of the political police departments of the L€ander and finally the command of the Prussian Political Police as well, which had been labeled since the end of November 1933 as “Geheime Staatspolizei.” In November 1934, all political polices, existing by that time in Germany, were collected under the directorship of Himmler. In a parallel process, the command over the polices was transferred from the L€ander to the national government. This development toward a centralized national police came to a central point, when Himmler was given in June 1936 the title of “Reichsf€uhrer SS and Chef der Deutschen Polizei,” indicating his dual directorship as head of the SS and the German police. In the aftermath of this entitlement, the centralization and the “Vereichlichung” (nationalization) of the different police branches were further enhanced; under Himmler, a national police apparatus had been established, which had not existed before. But the centralization of the police was only one aspect on the police agenda of the Nazi regime. A further, very important development was the merging of the police apparatus with the SS, in order to create a novel kind of security Police in Nazi Germany force effectively and vigorously serving the ideological ends of the Nazi regime. This meant a growing detachment of the police from its traditional institutional context, while it was more and more interleaved with the organizations of the Nazi movement. Under the organizational roof of the “Reichssicherheitshauptamt,” a sort of holding for the different security forces of the Nazi regime, which was established in 1939 after the beginning of the war, this merging of the police with the SS apparatus did find its institutional imprint (Topographie des Terrors 2010; Wildt 2009). Police in Nazi Germany II: From Dictatorial State Police to Ideological Security Force After the Nazi movement got hold of the police in 1933, it took them only a few years to establish a new approach of policing, clearly exceeding the politics of persecution and suppression known from other dictatorships and authoritarian regimes being in power in Europe at that time. Under the Nazis, the police’s functions were no longer focused on “traditional” target groups only, such as criminal perpetrators and political opponents. The police became instead increasingly, and in a growing proactive manner, focused on specific categories of people, who, based on racial (Jews, Roma, and Sinti) and to a significant extent on criminal-biological criteria (social outsiders, habitual criminals), were labeled as enemies of the racially defined ethnic community of Germans, the “Volksgemeinschaft” (Herbert 2011). Policing was conceptualized as a policy of social cleansing, meant to rid the “Volksgemeinschaft” of political and criminal “enemies of the people” (“Volksfeinde”) and of all “community aliens” (“Gemeinschaftsfremde”), not fitting into or not willing or capable to adapt to the racial and biological scheme of the Nazi regime. This conceptualization was expressed in the image of the police as a “doctor” cutting out all symptoms of sickness out of the “social body.” Racism, concepts of “racial hygiene,” and criminal 3625 P biology, increasingly popular since the 1920s, now penetrated nearly all layers of police work. The identification and persecution of members of “foreign races” and the stigmatization and exclusion of “hereditary” or habitual criminals and of other categories of people labeled as deviant became a core component of a police-driven, for those concerned increasingly deadly social engineering. The new police concept constituted the basis for an active participation of the police forces in the murderous and genocidal politics of the Nazi regime. Policing during the Nazi regime rested upon a familiar yet specifically radicalized division of labor: While the State Police (Geheime Staatspolizei, Gestapo) organized the repression of political opponents and took part in the elimination of “racial aliens,” such as Jews, Poles, or Russians, the Criminal Police (Kriminalpolizei, Kripo) became responsible for the prosecution and the elimination of criminals, social outcasts, and the group of Roma and Sinti. The uniformed police (since 1936 under the label Ordnungspolizei, Orpo), responsible for the overall maintenance of law and order in Nazi society, was involved in the surveillance of everyday life and played an important role in ensuring the populace’s conformity and identifying deviants. It thus provided essential assistance to the Security Police making a significant contribution to the Nazi regime’s political persecution and social exclusion. Phases of Development The historical research on the police during the Nazi regime has identified five phases for summarizing the growing involvement of the police in the Nazi regime. During the first phase, primarily during the months after the Nazi seizure of power, the efforts of the Nazi regime were much focused on getting hold of the police as a power instrument, indispensible for suppressing political opponents and for maintaining the Nazi regime during its first months of being in power. The second phase, consisting more or less of the years 1934 to P P 3626 1936, could be described as the phase when foundations for a merging of the police and the SS apparatus of the Nazi movement were laid. This merging was started by putting Heinrich Himmler, the head of the SS apparatus, and other SS leaders at the head of the German police; by linking the Kriminalpolizei and the Gestapo under the label of a national socialist Security Police (Sicherheitspolizei); and by placing the Security Police and the Security Service of the SS, the Sicherheitsdienst (SD), under a joint institutional roof. The third phase, that is, the years from 1936 to 1939, was very much marked by specific forms of radicalizations of police practices. During these years, the Kripo and the Gestapo began to implement the racialbiological ideologies of the Nazi regime into police work and started to select systematically those groups labeled as enemies of the “community” for special police measures, for new forms of confinement, and eventually for deportation into the expanding concentration camp system. With the beginning of the war in September 1939 and the establishment of the “Reichssicherheitshauptamt” in that year until late 1944, the police in its fourth phase of its involvement in the Nazi regime turned into the most important instrument for the completion of the Nazi racial ideologies: By its participation in the killing units of the “Einsatzgruppen,” the police engaged as main actor in the mass murder of the European Jews in Europe. So did the units of the uniformed police, especially after the war against the Soviet Union had begun (1941). And back home within Germany, it was the police which summoned the German-Jewish population of the cities and the countryside for the deportation into the concentration camps and which accompanied as guards the trains and transported the victims to the death camps. By the same time, the Kripo again radicalized its practices by sending in more and more people into concentration camps, thus occupying next to the Gestapo a central position in the overall strategy for the cleansing of the “community” from its enemies. When carrying out this, the Gestapo and the Kripo were not only instruments used by the Nazi regime but engaged in it beyond obeying Police in Nazi Germany orders by putting forward own initiatives for improving the efficiency of the cleansing of the “Volksgemeinschaft,” that is, of mass murder. During the fifth and final phase, which lasted from 1944 to the end of the war and the end of the Nazi regime in 1945, the radicalization of police practices intensified once again. During this final phase, the Security Police focused its control efforts on the foreign workers, who lived by that time in enormous number in Germany and had mostly been forced to work for the “Third Reich.” Moreover, indicators on increasing discontent and disloyalty among the Germans within the “Reich” turned into a major concern for the Security Police. Starting in the last months of the war and the regime and continuing in its final days, the Security Police tried to cope with the decreasing power of the regime and the increasing disloyalty of the population with a dramatically growing brutalization, resulting in the mass murders of foreign workers and political opponents and selected killings of ordinary Germans no longer loyal to the regime during the final days of the war. The Security Police and Its Personnel In order to turn the Security Police into the police of the “Volksgemeinschaft,” it became organizationally realigned, centralized, and provided with new hierarchical structures, guidelines, and standards. The transformation and renewal of the staff played a key role as well. While the personnel of the Kripo with about 13,000 employees was mainly transformed with the normal turnover of staff, the Gestapo was established fundamentally new. On the basis of the political police of the Weimar Republic, with its approximately 1,000 officers, the Gestapo grew to an apparatus with over 30,000 employees until the end of World War II. Senior positions within the Gestapo and the Criminal Police were held since 1933 by men who openly showed their loyalty to the Nazi regime or had even been active in the Nazi movement for a long time already. The few police officers, who had declared themselves against the Police in Nazi Germany Nazis and had represented a decidedly republican, democratic police during the Weimar years, were dismissed or demoted. New police recruits had to indicate, at least through membership in the Nazi party, that they were supporting the regime permanently. The police training combined political-ideological indoctrination and professional police instruction. Finally, with the inclusion of police officers in the SS, and with joint spheres of action and social contacts between the Security Police and the SS Security Service (SD), close relations between police and the Nazi apparatus emerged (Banach 1998; Browder 1996). In this way, the Sipo established the model of a new type of police officer, combining expert knowledge and professional ambition with ideological radicalism and the commitment of a “political soldier.” This new type of police officer became a dominating pattern inside the head office of the Gestapo and the Criminal Police in Berlin, as well as among the senior officers of the regional headquarters of the Sipo branches. This leadership group consisted mainly of younger cadres with middle-class background, well-educated, academically trained, often active in extreme right-wing organizations before 1933 and striving for implementing the societal models of the Nazi regime (Wildt 2009). Another form of “Nazification” took place among the lower ranks of the Security Police, particularly within the Gestapo, which, due to its growing staff requirements, recruited members of Nazi organizations with low-level formal education only and without specific police skills. These activists played an important part in the implementation of the Nazi movement’s political and racial stereotypes and its violence into police practice. Despite these fundamental changes, patterns of regular, traditional police work remained present in the Sipo (Dams and Stolle 2012; Roth 2010). Established procedures and routines of criminal investigation and administration were not abolished but pursued for the purposes of Nazi regime. In addition, older senior detectives, who had entered the police service during the German Empire or after World War I, played a significant role even after 1933. Although the Nazi leadership 3627 P had promised to purge the police of politically “unreliable” officers after the seizure of power, the rate of dismissals in 1933/1934 was relatively low (<5 %), partially due to the lack of candidates for replacing the officers to be dismissed. Thus, detectives, who were professionally trained and socialized in the Weimar Republic, had a significant impact on the apparatus of the Sipo, in particular during the early years of the Nazi regime. In the middle and lower ranks of the Sipo, the local posts, and particularly inside the Kripo, they remained an influential and supporting element until the end of the regime. With their experience and technical knowledge, they contributed significantly to the functioning and effectiveness of the Security Police. Reasons for Support and Initiative The support that the Nazi regime gained from various groups of police officers was due to political indoctrination, opportunism, and careerism; instead, shared values and professional expectations were key factors in that respect as well. Nationalism, antiliberalism and anticommunism, radically stereotyped views on political outsiders or marginalized groups, authoritarian conceptions of state intervention, and social order (“law and order”) had been part of the mainstream police philosophy during the 1920s. The rejection of parliamentary democracy and of the rule of law, demands for extensive and harsh control of political opponents, social outcasts and criminals, and the expansion, unification, and centralization of the police forces came upon a broad consensus within the police apparatus. The Nazis reacted positively on the demands and expectations circulating inside the police by suspending or abolishing existing legal restrictions and by giving the police the means for realizing their ideas of radical social control and social cleansing. In the “fight against criminality,” against “enemies of the Volksgemeinschaft” or against “antisocial elements,” the police and Nazi movement, senior detectives, and the new leadership of the Sipo shared the goals to pursue (Paul and Mallmann 1996; Wagner 1996). P P 3628 As far as the cultural integration of the police in the Nazi state was concerned, celebrations or public events played a role, too. Of particular importance was that the Sipo was given a new image, which was perceived positively by most police officers. While public criticism of the police nearly disappeared after the suppression of the free press, the Nazi regime and senior Sipo officers developed an image of the police, which depicted the detectives as modern, scientifically trained, effective investigators and provided the Gestapo with the myth of an omnipresent and omnipotent power apparatus. For the participation of Kripo and Gestapo officers in the terror of the Nazi regime, other factors and processes were important as well: increasing routine and familiarity with practices of exclusion and violence, the dehumanization of the victims through propaganda and bureaucratic procedures, and division of labor and responsibilities and social distance to those persecuted, but also the emergence of a specific Nazi ‘cop culture’ that was based on harshness and soldierly masculinity, camaraderie, and group pressure. The Security Police: Methods and Instruments of Power The alignment of the Sipo with the overall policies of the Nazi regime and the emergence of a concept of “racial policing” was accompanied by an expansion of instruments of power and a radicalization of police methods. Limitations of police work by legal bonds and external controls were abolished, and fundamental civil and human rights were suspended. Those affected were exposed to nearly unrestricted police arbitrariness. While the Gestapo and Kripo detectives continued to work as a part of the law enforcement process and as an investigative administration for the public prosecutor, an independent police penal justice steadily expanded since 1933. Its base was the introduction of an independent police custody, the so-called protective custody (Schutzhaft) used by the Gestapo and the “preventive custody” in the case of the Police in Nazi Germany Kripo. Both instruments allowed for detention without formal criminal justice proceedings and judicial review and resulted in permanent confinements of regime opponents and offenders in prisons or concentration camps. Those affected by these forms of confinement could be exposed to permanent drill, exhausting labor, hunger and disease, corporal punishments, and mortal danger. “Protective” and “preventive custody” enabled the police to punish, even on the ground of mere suspicion and poor evidence. Both forms of custody were used to “correct” court decisions and became instruments used massively for the intimidation and elimination of political opponents and people labeled as deviant. By applying this police custody, Gestapo and Kripo developed a policy of social exclusion that, until 1945, took several hundred thousand people into the concentration camps.The radicalization of police methods went even further within the Gestapo. While the use of physical violence against suspects by the Criminal Police was rather the exception, the Gestapo had the right to use violence for extorting statements. Against the backdrop of World War II, the Gestapo implemented its own prison camps, the so-called corrective labor camps (Arbeitserziehungslager), where prisoners were usually held for several weeks. In the 1940s, groups such as Jews, Poles, or Russians were completely removed from the realm of the judiciary and brought completely under the control of the Gestapo. Toward the end of the war, local and regional Gestapo offices were finally empowered to execute prisoners. Arbitrary arrests and deportations, penetrations of the private sphere, extensive surveillance measures, and the use of informers (V-M€anner) were the main features of the work of the Security Police, but routine police methods of investigation, detection, and forensic collection were continued as well, being the basis for the deployment of police terror. Despite the image of being omnipresent and omnipotent, the police force was dependent on the support of other institutions of the Nazi state. When heading for a comprehensive control of the “Volksgemeinschaft,” the Sipo’s own resources and personnel were insufficient (Gellately 1990; Police in Nazi Germany Paul and Mallmann 1996). But the Security Police could count on the cooperation of other instances of social control: Together with subunits of the Nazi party, the uniformed police, government and municipal administrations, health and employment services, the tax administration, postal and railroad services, as well as the customs authorities and large parts of the economic sector, a cooperative network for enhancing and enforcing the policies and the terror of the Nazi regime was created. Significant support came also from the public. For controlling and suppressing core political opposition groups such as communists, or for controlling so-called criminals, the Gestapo and the Kripo could fall back on their own investigative work, but for the discovery of small individual deviances and minor violations, for the observation of everyday life, for the penetration into the privacy of suspected people, and for the pervasion of so-called closed milieus, the Sipo had to rely on denouncers and informers. For the discovery of a spontaneous protest, for the exclusion of the Jews from the “German” society, and for the close observation of minorities, input from the population and party organizations was essential. The power of Gestapo and Kripo derived not only from the results of its own investigations but from a network of individual and institutional supporters. Key Aspects of Gestapo Work Central to the work of the Sipo were permanent dynamics of radicalization (Dams and Stolle 2012; Mallmann and Paul 2000). When heading for an overall cleansing of the “Volksgemeinschaft” by eliminating political opponents’ “racial enemies” and all sorts of deviance within the population, new enemy groups and accordingly new security requirements were continuously constructed. Initially the most important activity of the Secret State Police was the suppression of the left-wing workers’ movement, in which the regime saw the main potential for opposition and unrest. The Gestapo’s attack was directed primarily against communists, moreover against socialists, social 3629 P democrats, and representatives of the Free Trade Unions. By 1933, tens of thousands of opponents have been arrested, mistreated and tortured, handled by criminal courts, or transferred to – by that time – early forms of concentration camps. Other measures were repeated raids, searches, and the confiscation of literature, printing machines, and illegal publications; the ban of organizations and newspapers; and the closure of the workers’ movement’s associations. Although the left opposition was constantly trying to reorganize illegal groups, the Gestapo managed to dismantle their resistance until 1936/1937. Additionally, the Gestapo also developed a supporting role in the control of the Christian churches and religious groups. The aim was to stem criticism from the churches, to promote the adaptation of the believers to the Nazi ideology, to force the churches out of the public, and to reduce their impact on the population. Here, the repressive approach of the Gestapo was clearly more differentiated than toward communist resistance and was aimed mainly at integration into the “Volksgemeinschaft.” While in Protestant-dominated areas, the Gestapo only monitored a critical minority within the church; in Catholic areas, where the Gestapo suspected a widespread reluctance to Nazism, the State Police developed a wide range of measures: It reached from the observation of meetings and church services and larger propaganda campaigns against the church to the ban on Christian associations and the punishment of individual representatives of political Catholicism and dissident clerics. Another important field of Gestapo work was the control of public opinion. In addition to the suppression of critical statements from the labor movement and the churches, the communication of “ordinary” citizens should be regulated. Based on new decrees and laws putting the criticism of the representatives and actions of the government and the Nazi party under punishment as “treachery” (Heimt€ucke), the Gestapo initiated tens of thousands of investigations. Since the beginning of the war, expressing doubts about the Nazi propaganda or pessimistic statements about the war were persecuted more intensely P P 3630 and partly criminalized as “undermining of the military strength” (Wehrkraftzersetzung). The same was true of the media consumption of the population, as listening to foreign radio stations and distributing demoralizing information could be persecuted since 1939 under the label “radio crime” (Rundfunkverbrechen). Since the mid-1930s, the State Police exerted increased pressure on nonconformist juveniles who rejected national socialist cultural hegemony by insisting on their particular subcultures and by turning against the Nazi youth organization. In addition, the Gestapo initiated wide-ranging prosecution actions against homosexuals, whose behavior was considered a threat to Nazi population policy. It punished violations of economic policy and labor discipline as well and was responsible for criminal proceedings against deviant members of the Nazi movement. On all these fields, the Gestapo sometimes acted in competition but usually in close consultation with the Kripo. In several of these fields of action and against occasional violations of the norms of the community the Security Police, especially during the prewar years, acted selectively (Gellately 2001; Roth 2010). So it not only applied hard, negative sanctions but used warnings and lighter penalties to intimidate and discipline violators, in order to make them get in line with the “Volksgemeinschaft.” As far as the German-Jewish population was concerned, the police aimed at a radical marginalization and exclusion. While the political, social, and economic exclusion of Jews had been enhanced during the first years after the Nazi seizure of power very much by Nazi party subunits, the Gestapo thereafter took more and more the initiative. Since legislations in 1935, which turned German Jews into second-class citizens, the Gestapo went into organizing the discrimination, isolation, and exclusion of this population group. The police conducted the registration of German Jews, restricted their freedom of movement, were continuously involved in the criminalization of relations between Jews and non-Jews, and also contributed to the economic expropriation of Jewish citizens. Police in Nazi Germany As of November 1938, the Gestapo began with the systematic exclusion from German society. During and after the November 1938 pogroms, the Gestapo throughout Germany arrested more than 30,000 German-Jewish men and deported them into concentration camps, where the victims were released only when they had agreed upon abandoning their properties and upon leaving Germany. Just a few weeks earlier, in a nationwide campaign, the Gestapo had arrested about 17,000 Polish Jews and deported them over the German-Polish border – a test run for the mass deportations of the 1940s. From the spring of 1941, the Gestapo organized the final spatial segregation of the remaining Jews within Germany. In the cities Jews were evicted from “Aryan” houses and sent to special “ghetto houses” or local camps. People of Jewish origin, who were kept in asylums, prisons, and other institutions, were separated from other inmates and handed over to the Gestapo. From autumn 1941, the State Police organized the deportations from the “Reich” to the ghettos and death camps in occupied Eastern Europe. By 1943 some 150,000 people were deported from Germany, while only a few were able to survive as “Mischlinge” (crossbreeds), partners in so-called mixed marriages or in hiding. The Work of the Kripo Unlike the Gestapo, the Criminal Police was initially focused more on traditional police activities such as criminal investigation and crime detection. During the 1930s, however, its practice was more and more determined by the methods and goals of a police of the “Volksgemeinschaft” (Browder 1996; Wagner 1996). In late 1933, the senior ranks of the Kripo opened a new field of activity under the label of “preventive fighting against crime” (vorbeugende Verbrechensbek€ampfung). Under the pretext of reducing crime, the Kripo rendered recidivists into “preventive detention” by deporting them for an indefinite time into concentration camps, even in the absence of a specific offense or criminal court Police in Nazi Germany proceedings. Since 1934, the policemen were also enabled to subject known criminals to a “systematic observation” (“planm€aßige € Uberwachung”) and rigid rules of conduct. At the beginning, the policy of preventive fighting against crime targeted at a relative small group of a few thousand criminals, which should be kept from further criminal activity by deterrence and confinement. With the vision of a “Volksgemeinschaft” without crime in mind, the Kripo constantly enlarged its net. According to a nationwide campaign of arrests against 2,000 so-called professional and habitual criminals (“Berufs-” and “Gewohnheitsverbrecher”) in March 1937, the local Kripo offices started systematically detecting recidivists and sending them in very large numbers to concentration camps. The criminal deportations soon were directed not only against professional burglars and violent or sexual offenders but met more often petty criminals. At the same time, the persecution of homosexuals now shifted from the Gestapo to the Kripo. Even when acting against other social outcasts, the Kripo officers acted with increasing harshness. By doing so, the Criminal Police took up and radicalized the strategies and practices, pursued already by labor, social, and health administrations. As early as 1933, the Kripo had initiated numerous raids against prostitutes, beggars, and vagrants, demonstrating that social “disorder” and public “indecency” should no longer be openly tolerated. The next step came when the practice of “crime prevention” in December 1937 was extended to marginalized groups, and the Kripo was empowered to apply indefinite confinement on all individuals “endangering the general public by asocial behavior.” Thereupon the concentration camp became a common measure against outsiders, while the Kripo turned into the dominant actor of social exclusion (Ayaß 1995; Gellately and Stoltzfus 2001). In 1938, the police leadership prompted two nationwide sweeps against so-called work shy, in the course of which the Criminal Police arrested more than 9,000 people (the Gestapo about 1,500). Since then the local Kripo posts consistently put more and more “asocials” into 3631 P “preventive detention” – next to prostitutes, homeless and vagrants welfare recipients, alcoholics, men neglecting their family duties, women labeled as promiscuous and women with venereal diseases, dealers, peddlers, etc. Even biographically, “crime prevention” radicalized: Since the early 1940s, 1,000 “criminal and antisocial youths” were interned, terrorized, and biologically examined in special camps. Especially involved was the female unit of the Kripo (Weibliche Kriminalpolizei), which not only served as kind of welfare police for (female) adolescents but was responsible for the elimination of “criminal offspring.” Until the end of the Nazi era, the Kripo under the label of “crime prevention” delivered about 80,000 offenders to the terror of the concentration camps (Wagner 1996). In addition, there was the fight against “alien races.” The Criminal Police assisted the Gestapo in its anti-Jewish policy, for example, by sending Jews with criminal records to camps or persecuting relationships between “Aryans” and “nonAryans” as “race defilement” (“Rassenschande”). To core projects of the Kripo belonged the exclusion of the Roma and Sinti, who, as “gypsies,” had been particularly discriminated against and placed under special surveillance long before 1933 (Zimmermann 1996). Since the mid-1930s, they were deprived of civil rights, prohibited further mobility, separately registrated, examined by racial experts, and marked as “racial aliens.” After May 1940 the Kripo started several deportations, taking thousands of German and Austrian Roma and Sinti to the annexed and occupied Poland, where most of them lost their lives. From March 1943, about 23,000 “gypsies” from the “Reich” and occupied Europe were transported to the extermination camp at Auschwitz. As the practice of Gestapo, the work of the Kripo since the 1940s was closely associated with national socialist mass murder. Gestapo and Kripo During World War II The beginning of World War II provided additional rationalizations for the radicalization P P 3632 of policing and increased the willingness of policemen to act harshly and murderously against political, social, and racial “enemies.” With the expansion of the Nazi regime into large parts of Europe, new spaces of social control and eliminatory rule were created, while millions of people who were defined as dangerous by the Nazi regime fell in the hands of the Gestapo and the Criminal Police (Mallmann and Paul 2000; Topographie des Terrors 2010). The further radicalization of the Sipo occurred in the occupied territories, where the Sipo exercised unprecedented and unbound physical violence. Since September 1939, more and more Gestapo and Kripo detectives had to leave their offices within Germany and put themselves at the service of Nazi occupation and warfare. Some of them participated in the “Einsatzgruppen,” who entered the occupied territories behind the Wehrmacht to “cleanse” the conquered areas of indigenous elites, oppositional groups, Jews, and minorities like gypsies and the disabled. The “Einsatzgruppen,” already established as mobile killing units in the Polish campaign 1939 and considerably extended since the invasion of the Soviet Union in 1941, have been responsible for the direct killing of hundreds of thousands of people especially in Eastern Europe (Klein 1997). In these units, and the offices established in the occupied territory, the institutional merging of police and SS was further promoted. Members of the Security Police were involved at all levels in Nazi crimes: in the invention of killing techniques for the gas vans and death camps and the “administrative execution” of genocide; in the surveillance of ghettos and economic plundering of the occupied countries; in reprisals against political opponents, mass executions of Jews, political officials, prisoners of war, or “partisans”; and in the killing of “criminals,” “asocials,” or “gypsies.” In the violent environment of the East, it could be practiced without restraint and directly, what the police in the “Reich” before the war could achieve only indirectly through deportation and imprisonment into concentration camps: the annihilation of those categories of people defined as enemies of the “Volksgemeinschaft.” When doing this, the Police in Nazi Germany Security Police was not only supported by the Germany army or the civil administrations of the occupied countries. An important element of German police power in Europe was the collaboration of local police forces, radical nationalist organizations, and auxiliaries, which contributed significantly to the execution of mass murder. The Security Police on the “Home Front” In the course of World War II also inside Germany, the Sipo radicalized its scenarios of crucial enemies and possible dangers (Mallmann and Paul 2000). Political opposition and social deviance were now seen as a threat to the Nazi war effort and the stability of the “home front.” But while this resulted in a further tightening of sanctions, gaps in the system of police control were widening, as many officers were withdrawn from the “internal front,” the police functions were continually extended, and the prolonged war and ongoing air raids, especially in big cities, lead to a decline of law-abidance and loyalty to the regime. The impending loss of control in the war did not lead the Security Police to a strategy of deescalation but was answered with a further intensification of terror. To this added, that police officers who had returned from the occupied territories brought their experiences of violence and concepts of “enemy combat” with them to the “internal front.” Due to the expansion of control requirements and the social distractions of war society, the Kripo focused more and more on the disciplining of those refusing to work for the war community, on surveilling the conduct of young people and single women, on halting the spread of sexually transmitted diseases among prostitutes and soldiers, or on the persecution of the black market, “looting” and other war-related crimes (Roth 2010; Wagner 1996). These control efforts also met conservative and bourgeois opponents of the regime – as the mass arrests after the attempt to assassinate Hitler in 1944 illustrate. However, on the “home front” within Germany, racial politics stood at the center of the State Police’s activity. In addition to the exclusion of the Jewish population, the control Police in Nazi Germany of “foreign workers” became a main task of the Gestapo – especially since the intensification of the use of foreign workers in the German Economy (Ausl€andereinsatz) and the massive recruitment of forced laborers from the occupied Soviet Union since 1942. The Gestapo not only had to monitor the work discipline of foreign workers and to ensure the functioning of the war economy, it also was to suppress resistance and sabotage and punish forbidden relations between Germans and foreigners. That was mainly applied to workers from Poland and Soviet Russia: They were classified as “racial aliens” and placed at the bottom of the racial hierarchy of the Nazi system, were regarded as a special threat to the order of the “internal front,” and were almost entirely subject to the power and violence of the State Police. Since the middle of the war, the measures of the Gestapo even included the killing of East European laborers. Numerous Polish, Ukrainian, or Russian civilian workers, who have had intimate relations with locals, were publicly executed due to transgression of “racial barriers” (Gellately 2001). This indicates what State Police practice characterized in the last months of the war: A policy of open terror, which brought mass murder to the “home front.” In the final phase of the war, the Gestapo inside the “Reich” increasingly followed the models and methods of occupation. Hierarchies, bureaucratic procedures, and the formal allocation of responsibilities became less important, as much of the work of the State Police was taken by Sonderkommandos (special task forces) operating with high mobility and flexibility. They worked increasingly independent to the central offices in Berlin, with almost unlimited instruments of terror. In the last months of the war, executions, initially dependent upon authorization from Berlin, could be imposed by regional commanders of the Security Police and eventually the local offices themselves. Before the collapse of the Nazi system, the work of the Gestapo in the “Reich” was marked by mass arrests, targeted killings, and “combat missions.” They were directed primarily against “foreign workers,” young people, deserters, and criminals who were in hiding in the ruins of the big cities. 3633 P Since the Gestapo with its flexible organizational structures and unlimited powers assumed nearly all of the Security Police’s competencies, the officers of the Criminal Police lost importance and influence in the last months of the Nazi regime. However, at least some of the Kripo officers participated in arbitrary killings and supported the “final battle” of the Gestapo. The Uniformed Police: Everyday Practices and Participation in the Holocaust During the Weimar Republic Period, the uniformed police tried to change the image it had in the public. While an image, deriving from the police before World War I, lingered on, which portrayed the police very much as authoritarian, militaristic, and emphasizing the social distance between the uniformed police and the general public, senior police officers tried to change this image for a portrait, which displayed a police much closer to the public, a police, which was no longer primarily a protector of the state but a protector of the “people” as well. After the Nazi seizure of power, the leadership of the police attempted to give this portrait even more contours by popularizing a label, which showed “The police, your friend and helper.” The uniformed police organized during the 1930s and even during the first years of the war a number of “Tage der Polizei” (days of the police), which, as a public relations action, were to propagandize the label. Other activities, inaugurated by the police during the 1930s, focused on improving the traffic circulation in the cities and on preventing the growing risk of traffic accidents, by training the general public, in particular children, how to behave adequately on the roads of the city. All this was intended to make the slogan “The police, your friend and helper” popular, but this label covered only partially the reality of the uniformed police during the Nazi regime. The uniformed police was “friend and helper” only to those, who were members of the “Volksgemeinschaft.” Jews, for example, were P P 3634 not members of this community, which comprised only Germans along very narrowly defined social, racial, and biological criteria. Some of those, who were opponents of the new regime, or were not members of the “Volksgemeinschaft,” experienced immediately, others very soon a new repressive side of the uniformed police and a new specific, selective approach to law and order, influenced by the political strategies of the Nazi regime. The uniformed police did not intervene, when political opponents of the Nazi regime were arrested, maltreated, or even killed but conceded instead to a partition of labor with the police doing the work, which looked professional and members of the paramilitary groups of the Nazi movement, often in the position of auxiliary police personnel, doing the “dirty” work, such as torture and killings of political opponents. And in 1933, soon after the Nazi movement had come into power, the police did not intervene, when the Nazi movement staged a boycott against German-Jewish shopowners and merchants, thus indicating law and order might not pertain to German Jews any longer. These attitudes became increasingly enhanced, when a growing loading of police training with patterns of Nazi ideology and anti-Semitic contents occurred (Matth€aus 2003; Westermann 2005). Institutionally and organizationally, the uniformed police experienced a drawback, when in 1936, after a organizational reconstruction, which had started very early after the Nazi seizure of power already, the units of the uniformed police were transferred to the German army to increase the army’s numerical strength. This weakened the organizational resources of the uniformed police and reduced the number of its personnel to about fifty percent of its original strength. Until the end of the 1930s, the uniformed police gradually managed to increase again the number of its officers and to reestablish police units. The personnel of these newly established units, later named as police battalions (Polizeibataillone), was comprised to large extents of police reserve recruits without any professional police background instead of professional police officers. These police units were used alongside the military, when the Nazi regime annexed Austria (1938) and Czechoslovakia (1938/1939). These Police in Nazi Germany participations of units of the uniformed police still ran under the heading of securing the occupied territories, but with the start of the war against Poland in 1939, the uniformed police turned into an instrument executing the racial and genocidal ideologies of the Nazi regime. The uniformed police finally became a murderous key institution in the Holocaust. Already during the starting phase of the war against Poland, the units of the uniformed police, following the advancing German army, committed atrocities among the Polish population, Jewish and non-Jewish, thus becoming part of the racial strategies the Nazi regime started pursuing already during the first phase of the war. Especially the violent transfer of populations, the settlement of “ethnic Germans” in the occupied parts of Western Poland and the brutal eviction of Polish and Polish-Jewish inhabitants of these parts of the country into the occupied central Poland (the “Generalgouvernement”) became one of the first elements of the participation of the uniformed police in the geostrategical and racial policies of the Nazi regime. With the beginning of the war against the Soviet Union in June 1941, the involvement of the units of the uniformed police gained unprecedented genocidal dimensions. The socalled Einsatzgruppen, operating in the hinterland of the advancing German army within the Soviet Union, killed more than 500,000 victims until the end of 1941, most of them Jews. These mobile killings units not only were composed of members of the Security Police and the Security Service of the SS (SD) but could rely to large parts on military SS-formations (Waffen-SS) and members of the uniformed police. These mobile killing units advanced within the Soviet Union as far as the German army, that is, into the territory of the former Baltic states, and from there close to Leningrad, they covered Belorussia and moved forward into the vicinity of Moscow, covered the whole of Ukraine and proceeded as far as the northern fringe of the Caucasus. Most of the direct killing actions and massacres on the Eastern Front, as the killing of about 33,000 Jews from Kiew in Babi Jar, were carried out by the “Einsatzgruppen” and supporting units. Police in Nazi Germany While the overall number of members of the “Einsatzgruppen” remained relatively small (there were up to 3,000 men in the “Einsatzgruppen” following the advancing German army in the war against the Soviet Union), the overall figures for the members of the units of the uniformed police participating in war, occupation and genocide were much higher: In occupied Poland and in the occupied parts of the Soviet Union, approximately 50,000 men served in different units of the uniformed police, the number of these units amounting to 90. This high figure of men serving in mobile units of the uniformed police was due to the fact that the Order Police was not limited to its participation in the murderous actions of the “Einsatzgruppen.” The units of the uniformed police carried out a great number of executions of their own, quite often when the Ghettos in the cities of Eastern Europe, where the Jewish population was forced to live in, were dissolved and its inhabitants being sent into the death camps. But the radius of action of the uniformed police was not limited to Eastern Europe. In most of the countries occupied by Nazi Germany, units of the uniformed police held a significant position in the occupation apparatus, often charged with a more general maintenance of the security in the occupied countries. In the later phases of the war, units of the uniformed police became heavily involved in fighting guerrilla activities against the German occupation (“Partisanen-” or “Bandenbek€ampfung,” terms often used for masking executions of Jewish men, women, and children; the elimination of resistance groups; and the brutal suppression of the local population). During the final phases of the war, units of the uniformed police took part in the indiscriminate mass killings of hostages all over Europe, leading to the extinction of whole village populations (Oradour-sur-Glane). The overall death toll, for which the uniformed police of the Nazi regime could be held responsible, is difficult to calculate precisely. But calculations in different publications, older ones (Gutman 1990) and more recent ones (Curilla 2011), count approximately 1,200,000 victims, who were either murdered by 3635 P the units of the uniformed police or by members of this police as participating in mass executions as members of other units (“Einsatzgruppen”). After 1945: Research and Institutional Reflections Elaborated research about the role and the functions of the police as part of the Nazi regime did set in late in Germany. The few studies available until the 1980s either gave limited descriptions of the police’s institutional settings and the development of this settings during the years from the Nazi seizure of power until the end of the war, or they focused on the Gestapo, emphasizing a picture of the Gestapo as omnipresent and omnipotent, terrorizing political opponents and the so-called racial enemies of the German people and, since the beginning of the war, covering the whole of Nazi-occupied Europe with its murderous activities. This early research concentrated very much on a top-down perspective, by looking primarily at the main goals, leadership, and institutional context of the Gestapo’s activities without analyzing the whole personnel involved and without detailing the Gestapo’s impact and societal background. This changed for a bottom-up perspective, when the social history turn within historiography touched upon the writing about the Gestapo as well. This meant primarily to find out in detail what the Gestapo had meant for its victims. But next to the attempts of giving answers to this question, another feature turned up during the 1970s and 1980s: A new social history of the Gestapo revealed how important input from other institutions and the population had been for the work of the police during the Nazi regime, in particular input in the form of denunciations and input deriving from all sorts of informers. This led some historians to postulate, that Germany under the Nazis had been a selfpolicing society (Gellately 1990; Paul and Mallmann 1996). More recent research after the year 2000 however has refocused the attention on the terror exercised by the Gestapo and emphasized the initiative and specific politicalideological radicalization of the Gestapo corps. P P 3636 At the same time earlier, descriptions of the Gestapo focusing mainly on Himmler and Heydrich or paradigmatic figures like Eichmann were replaced by more complex and differentiated analyses of the personnel, emphasizing factors like generational background, collective values, organizational culture, and institutional dynamics (Mallmann and Paul 2004; Paul 2002; Wildt 2009). If the research about the Gestapo did set in relatively late already, critical studies of the other polices, that is, about the criminal and the uniformed police, did set in even later. The longlasting silence surrounding the Kripo’s crimes during the Nazi period had much to do with the fact that those victims affected by national socialist “crime fighting” were continuously marginalized after 1945, mostly remained objects of repressive policing and were not seen as “legitimate” victims of the “Third Reich.” This changed during the 1970s as critical social scientists and “grassroots historians” developed a more comprehensive approach toward the exclusionary politics of the Nazi regime and claimed recognition for the formerly “forgotten victims” (Ayaß 1995; Wagner 2002). The research on the Kripo, which was clearly expanding since the 1990s, has given its attention on the politics of the “fight against criminality” and the Kripo’s growing inclusion into the biological and racial strategies of the Nazi regime. While it elaborated the characteristics of crime fighting in the “racial state” of the “Third Reich,” this research yet also made clear in what extent police work during the Nazi regime adapted values, images, policies, and techniques from pre-Nazi times – and what continuities of policing can be identified between the German Empire and the Weimar Republic – the Nazi regime, and the postwar years. The interest, research has taken into the history of the uniformed police, has grown significantly in recent years. In particular its involvement in the mass executions of the Jewish population in Nazi-occupied Eastern Europe has been analyzed in great detail. Due to this focus, research on ordinary policing of the uniformed police in German cities is only gradually emerging. A core issue of the research Police in Nazi Germany about the uniformed police is asking for the factors, which turned policemen from members of the police force, loyal to the Nazi regime, into murderous perpetrators. There is currently a consensus among researchers that a whole spectrum of factors has to be taken into account for explaining this shift, ranging from the effects of political indoctrination to the habituation to murderous violence, from psychological factors such as group pressure to situational time- and location-based factors (Browning 1992; Welzer 2005). In 1945, when Nazi Germany was defeated, the victorious allied forces declared the Gestapo, together with a number of Nazi organizations, a criminal organization, while the Kripo and the uniformed police were left out from being accused of a specific affinity to the Nazi regime. In those parts of Germany, occupied by the Americans, the British, and the French, purges of the police took place, but the overall continuity remained relatively high. Very many of the detectives and the officers of the uniformed police continued to work in the police service (F€urmetz et al. 2001). As the public – at least during the first decades of (Western) postwar Germany – was reluctant to a detailed and critical examination of the Nazi regime, its leading actors, and supporters and as strong political, institutional, and legal barriers were impeding systematic investigations against Nazi perpetrators, only few of the former members of the Gestapo, Kripo, and Orpo were accused and sentenced for their participation in racial politics and genocide (Mallmann and Andrej 2009; Ullrich 2011). It has taken the German police considerable time to deal with the legacies of its Nazi past. First projects did set in during the early 1980s already. These projects, which quite often had the form of joint teams of police officers and academic historians, were much driven by so-called “critical” members of the police force, who saw police history as being part of a police reform strategy. This strategy aimed at a more civil, service-orientated, and self-reflecting police. But as this reform turned into a contested field, which did not find undivided acceptance among members of the police force, some of these early Police in Nazi Germany police history enterprises came under the critic from the police, especially as not everyone among senior ranks of the police was already “open” for critical views on the history of the police during the Nazi period. More or less a decade later, during the 1990s, a second wave of police history activities, involving big city police forces, did set in. The – in many aspects – most prominent among these big city police force histories was carried out under the auspices of the Cologne police (Buhlan and Jung 2000). A major result of this project on the Cologne police had been to show how deeply and intensively everyday policing had been involved in pursuing the exclusionary, racial policies of the Nazi regime. Further projects on the police of major German cities during the Nazi period confirmed these findings. In 2007, the Bundeskriminalamt (BKA) initiated a history project, which was to deal with the history of the BKA during the 1950s and 1960s, thereby focussing on the question to what extent continuities existed within the BKA: “Continuities” either meant asking for the members of the Bundeskriminalamt, who had served already in the security forces of the Nazi regime, or it meant trying to find out what impact (if at all) these characteristics of the BKA-personnel had on the practical work, the practices of the Bundeskriminalamt (Baumann et al. 2011). Since very recently (2011), projects dealing with the Nazi legacies within the Bundesnachrichtendienst (Federal External Secret Service) and the Bundesamt f€ ur Verfassungsschutz (Federal Internal Secret Service) are on the way as well. The initiatives for these projects are very much driven by the following logics: Firstly, dealing with the Nazi legacies of an institution such as the police, even if highly problematic aspects might emerge, is increasingly seen as important for a reflective police culture. Secondly, the German public generally recognizes positively efforts to deal with the Nazi past. And thirdly, and last but not least, within many institutions in the Federal Republic, a self-understanding has evolved, which sees the development of the institutional infrastructure of the Federal Republic as part of a democratic success story – which is the more successful, as this 3637 P success had evolved on the background of a terrible past. That is why many of the research questions put forward in this context are not only directed on scandalizing continuities (personnel, practices) beyond the 1945 line within these institutions but to show how successful the respective institutions had moved toward democracy and “Rechtsstaat,” the rule of law, despite the burdens of the Nazi past. Related Entries ▶ Comparing Police Systems Across the World ▶ Conceptualizing of Police ▶ German Police Until 1918 ▶ History of Criminal Investigation ▶ History of Criminological Theories: Causes of Crime ▶ Police in the Police State ▶ Political Crime Recommended Reading and References Ayaß W (1995) ‘Asoziale’ im Nationalsozialismus. Cotta, Stuttgart Banach J (1998) Heydrichs Elite. Das F€ uhrerkorps der Sicherheitspolizei und des SD 1936–1945. Scho¨ningh, Paderborn Baumann I, Reinke H, Stephan A, Wagner P (2011) Schatten der Vergangenheit. Das BKA und seine Gr€ undungsgeneration in der fr€ uhen Bundesrepublik. Luchterhand, Ko¨ln Browder GC (1996) Hitler’s enforcers. The Gestapo and the SS Security Service in the Nazi revolution. Oxford University Press, New York/Oxford Browning CR (1993) Ordinary men: reserve police battalion 101 and the final solution in Poland. Harper Collins, New York Buhlan H, Jung W (eds) (2000) Wessen Freund und wessen Helfer? Die Ko¨lner Polizei im Nationalsozialismus. Emons, Ko¨ln Curilla W (2011) Der Judenmord in Polen und die Ordnungspolizei. Paderborn, Scho¨ningh Dams C, Stolle M (2012) Die Gestapo. Herrschaft und Terror im Dritten Reich, 3rd edn. Beck, M€ unchen F€ urmetz G, Reinke H, Weinhauer K (eds) (2001) Nachkriegspolizei. Sicherheit und Ordnung in Ost- und Westdeutschland. Ergebnisse, Hamburg Gellately R (1990) The Gestapo and German society. Enforcing racial policy 1933–1945. Oxford University Press, New York, Oxford P P 3638 Gellately R (2001) Backing Hitler. Consent and coercion in Nazi Germany. Oxford University Press, New York/ Oxford Gellately R, Stoltzfus N (eds) (2001) Social outsiders in Nazi Germany. Princeton University Press, Princeton/ Oxford Gutman I (ed) (1990) Encyclopedia of the Holocaust. Macmillan, New York Herbert U (2011) Best. Biographische Studien € uber Radikalismus, Weltanschauung und Vernunft. 1903–1989, 5th edn. Dietz Nachfolger, Bonn Klein P (ed) (1997) Die Einsatzgruppen in der besetzten Sowjetunion, 1941/42. Die T€atigkeits- und Lageberichte des Chefs der Sicherheitspolizei und des SD. Edition Hentrich, Berlin Mallmann K-M, Andrej A (eds) (2009) Die Gestapo nach 1945. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt Mallmann K-M, Paul G (eds) (2000) Die Gestapo im Zweiten Weltkrieg. ‘Heimatfront’ und besetztes Europa. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt Mallmann K-M, Paul G (eds) (2004) Karrieren der Gewalt. Nationalsozialistische T€aterbiographien. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt Matth€aus J (2003) Ausbildungsziel Judenmord? ‘Weltanschauliche Erziehung’ von SS, Polizei und Waffen-SS im Rahmen der ‘Endlo¨sung’. Fischer, Frankfurt/M Paul G (ed) (2002) Die T€ater der Shoah. Fanatische Nationalsozialisten oder ganz normale Deutsche? Wallstein, Go¨ttingen Paul G, Mallmann KM (eds) (1996) Die Gestapo. Mythos und Realit€at. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt Roth T (2010) ‘Verbrechensbek€ampfung’ und soziale Ausgrenzung im nationalsozialistischen Ko¨ln. Kriminalpolizei, Strafjustiz und abweichendes Verhalten zwischen Macht€ ubernahme und Kriegsende. Emons, Ko¨ln Topographie des Terrors (2010) Gestapo, SS und Reichssicherheitshauptamt in der Wilhelm- und Prinz-Albrecht-Straße. Eine Dokumentation. Stiftung Topographie des Terrors, Berlin Ullrich C (2011) ‘Ich f€ uhl’ mich nicht als Mo¨rder’. Die Integration von NS-T€atern in die Nachkriegsgesellschaft. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt Wagner P (1996) Volksgemeinschaft ohne Verbrecher. Konzeptionen und Praxis der Kriminalpolizei in der Zeit der Weimarer Republik und des Nationalsozialismus. Hamburg, Christians Wagner P (2002) Hitlers Kriminalisten. Die deutsche Kriminalpolizei und der Nationalsozialismus zwischen 1920 und 1960. Beck, M€ unchen Welzer H (2005) T€ater. Wie aus ganz normalen Menschen Massenmo¨rder werden. Fischer, Frankfurt/M Westermann EB (2005) Hitler’s police battalions enforcing. Racial war in the East. UP of Kansas, Lawrence Police in the Police State Wildt M (2009) An uncompromising generation. The Nazi leadership of the Reich Security main office. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison Zimmermann M (1996) Rassenutopie und Genozid. Die nationalsozialistische ‘Lo¨sung der Zigeunerfrage’. Christians, Hamburg Police in the Police State Justice Tankebe Institute of Criminology, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, UK Overview “Police state” is a translation of the German word polizeistaat. The first citation of the term by the Oxford English Dictionary comes from the Times (London) of 1851: “Austria has become more of a police state than before.” The War Illustrated followed suit in 1939: “spies are everywhere; indeed, Germany is the modern exemplification of ‘the police state’ in action.” One way to understand the category of the police state is to frame it in terms of the question of the relationship between the “police” and the “state” (Neocleous 2000). Two, albeit, crude distinctions can be drawn; on the one hand, there are regimes in which the relationship is intimate to the point where the police institution is merely a handmaiden of the state and concerned almost exclusively with the task of executing regime orders; the aim is to protect the regime rather than serve citizens. On the other hand are regimes that claim to operate in such a way as to maintain a distance between the state and the police institution. These two types of regimes correspond, respectively, with non-liberal and liberal political cultures. In liberal political cultures, the police institution is seen as identical with civil society. For example, it has been argued that the source of legitimacy for the British police is a strong moral and emotional identification between the police and the British people: Thus, Reith (1956, p. 287) stressed Police in the Police State what he considered to be “the historic tradition that the police are the public and that the public are the police.” This alleged independence of the police from the state is the converse of what happens in police states or totalitarian states. This entry summarizes three main issues: First, it examines what is known about the nature of police states. Second, how do police states emerge? Third, it discusses what the police do and how well they do it in the police state. For example, what is the nature of crime in the police state, and what are the technologies of crime control? How reliable is it to assess the effectiveness of the technologies used? Fourth, how do citizens respond to the police state? Were the actions of the police considered “legitimate,” or police states lie outside the consideration of legitimacy? Did citizens live in fear of the police or they expressed popular support for the police? Problems of Definition1 The emergence of the modern state in Europe was associated with the birth of what has been termed the “well-ordered police state” in the sixteenth century. It is not that police states were unknown prior to this period. Indeed, some scholars make a distinction between the traditional police state and the modern police state, the latter referring to the well-ordered police state and the former describing the state prior to the era of the modern state. Why are certain regimes classified as “police states”? Stated differently, what is the “police state”? Prima facie, the answer to both questions is straightforward, and many will easily cite examples of such regimes. However, a careful consideration of the literature leads to a more cautious appraisal of the concept, that one cannot simply make a binary categorization of regimes into police states and nonpolice states. Rather it is more useful to speak of a continuum of police statehood, with different regimes 1 The essay draws heavily on the work of Arendt (1968) and Evans (2005). 3639 P (both democratic and nondemocratic) positioned on different points of the continuum: totalitarian regimes at one extreme end of the continuum and (liberal) democratic regimes at the other end. One of the few attempts to engage conceptually with the idea of the police state is Brain Chapman (1970). He set out a number of criteria for measuring the applicability of the police state model. The first is politicization. This is not to be equated with the idea that the police are political. All police forces, whether in totalitarian or liberal democracies, are political in the sense that they are created by the state and used by the state to maintain law and order. By politicization, Chapman is referring to police involvement in partisan politics and to a situation where police actions are dictated by partisan political considerations rather than the rule of law. Under such circumstances, the vicissitudes of police legitimacy are closely tied up with politics. Second is militarization of the police; rather than relying on the army for armed response where necessary, the police organization chooses to augment the capacity of its riot unit by providing it with armored vehicles and other equipments to enable it to operate independently of the army. This is a deeply problematic criterion, especially when Chapman argues that a state is on the road to becoming a police state if its police force weans itself from the control of the army and operates as an independent state institution (p. 119). There is no liberal democracy in which police operations are under the control or supervision of the army. Chapman’s third criterion is the Centralization of police services. It is hard to see how can be seen as a distinctive feature of the police state. For example, the structural configuration of a police force does not necessarily correspond to the character of the political culture in that country. Countries such as Belgium and Sweden have centralized police forces, yet they are scarcely the kind of countries we might describe as being totalitarian. A decentralized police institution does not guarantee against the emergence of localized despots, whether such despots are police officers acting on their own or P P 3640 under the dictates of local politicians. The Royal Commission on Police in Britain considered and rejected this approach to defining the police state. The Commission argued that the proper criterion for the police state should be “whether the police are answerable to the law,” and that in the police state, “the government acknowledges no accountability to a democratically elected parliament, and the citizen cannot rely on the courts to protect him” (1962, p. 45). But even this test of police statehood is not without difficulty. For example, it fails to differentiate between formal or procedural accountability and substantive accountability. Police states such as Nazi Germany had a parliament (the Reichstag) which, it was claimed, represented the will of the German public and passed laws to legitimate Nazi actions often in retrospect (The question of legality and its legitimacy will be considered in final part of this entry). Finally, Chapman discusses what he labels penetration. This, he asserts, entails an encroachment into the judicial domain, with the police obtaining powers of arrest, supervision, and detention, and a right to inflict penal sanctions outside the control of the normal judicial machinery. It is very hard to claim that this characterization is typical of totalitarian regimes and that such encroachment is alien in liberal democracies, even in the twenty-first century; police forces in all societies are vested with powers of arrest and detention, although the duration of detention before trial varies widely. Nor is it unknown in democratic societies for police to have powers to administer penal sanctions without recourse to the courts. Take the example of Britain: Criminal Justice Act 2003 effectively granted police officers the power of punishment. Specifically, the Act allows officers to issue cautions to certain categories of offenders, a legal provision that has been criticized for its procedural and substantive unfairness (Brownlee 2007). While dictionary definitions should not drive criminological analysis, a look at the dictionary can often illuminate our grasp of certain concepts. According to the Oxford English Dictionary the meaning of a police state is Police in the Police State “a totalitarian state run by means of a national police force, using repressive methods such as covert surveillance and arbitrary arrest and imprisonment to control the population.” Here again, the idea of a national or centralized police force is set out as a feature of totalitarianism, yet it is never entirely clear why centralization should be anathema to democratic governance. Even the notion of “repressive methods” is not without difficulties. Although a liberal democracy, the United Kingdom is considered to be one of the most closely surveilled countries in the world. For example, the City of London has 69 closed circuit television (CCTV) cameras per 1,000 population; Wandsworth, an area of 4.6 miles, has a total of 1,113 CCTV cameras which is far more than the CCTV cameras of police departments of Boston (USA), Johannesburg (South Africa), and Dublin City (Ireland) combined (BBC 2009). This level of surveillance was unparalleled by the experience of Nazi Germany or any other police state. In the end, all regimes target certain sections of their populations (for example, migrants and suspected terrorists), and embark on elaborate surveillance against them. It may be a bold claim but it may not be delusional to suggest that it is not the fact of particular actions or modes of operation of particular regimes that ipso facto make those regimes totalitarian or police states; many liberal democracies share with totalitarian regimes the use of intensive covert surveillance, imprisonment as a means of control of some sections of their population, and encroach upon the powers of the judiciary. Far more important might be how these technologies are employed and what mechanisms exist for substantive democratic accountability. In other words, deploying the category of police state to label non-liberal states may not help to illuminate the difference between them and liberal states (Neocleous 2000). It is far more useful to pay attention to how the police in both liberal and non-liberal societies treat citizens during everyday encounters. As a dictum, claims to democratic governance “would hardly be allowed to go unchallenged if the police severely restricted Police in the Police State public meetings and political demonstrations or resorted readily to physical force and intimation in order to prevent crime” (Bayley 1969, p. 11). Nor is it unreasonable to observe that even within democratic societies, the experiences and perceptions that some sections of society have of the police is akin to what citizens of police states experience. Put colloquially, one person’s democratic state might be another person’s police state. Emergence of Police States The preceding comments about the conceptual challenges in making sense of the category of police state do not mean that such a category is without merit. It has been argued that concepts are the gateway to the empirical world of study for empirical science, and therefore, the effective functioning of concepts is a matter of decisive importance (Blumer 1954). However, one cannot hope to deploy concepts effectively withoutclarity in their meaning. That is not a task necessarily attempted here; the objective so far has been more modest, and it is to draw attention to the need for further work in order to understand more fully its analytical utility. Nonetheless, there are examples of states in recent history widely described as police states: Nazi Germany and Stalin’s Russia. Under what conditions do police states emerge? It is difficult to answer this question without the risk of contextless generalizations. The coming to power of Stalin and Hitler occurred under completely different conditions. Russian was a relatively backward country, with a weak economy and history of despotic rule. Germany, on the other hand, was a welldeveloped economy; it had a highly educated population with reasonably strong institutions and a burgeoning democracy. Indeed, as discussed below, Hitler came to power through elections. It is important to expatiate on the Germany situation further, because it demonstrates that economic development and education do not necessarily suppress the emergence of totalitarian rule (Fukuyama 1992). 3641 P Toward the end of the nineteenth century, Germany had embarked upon its first experiment with democratic governance, and the experiment had gone spectacularly wrong. Parliament was toothless, unable to check executive power. The rights of workers were not fully recognized and industrialists had mounted strong opposition against moves toward unionized labor, arguing that unionized labor was an impediment to economic growth. Nor could it restrain encroachment upon the civil liberties of some sections of the population, in particular Catholics and Jews, both of which were considered “enemies of the Reich” (Evans 2005). At the same time, extremist political parties were increasingly gaining prominence. These parties tapped into the anxieties and resentment of ethnic Germans who felt increasingly disillusioned by the major economic and social transformation in German society at the time. In many Western societies today, migrants and asylum seekers are easy targets for such anxieties (Bauman 2004). In Germany, Jews were the target; they were seen as the source of all societal problems. Extremist politicians argued for their civil liberties and economic activities to be restricted. Mainstream political parties capitulated. Finally, defeat in the First World War brought economic burdens, and there was also increased violence. The judiciary was a tainted institution, widely perceived as partisan in favor of reactionary elements. It was within this context that Nazis came to power under the leadership of Adolf Hitler “who possessed one great gift: the ability to move crowds with his rhetoric” (Evans 2005, p. 7). The first electoral success for the Nazis was in September 1930 and July 1932, largely with support from the middle classes which had felt threatened by the election promises of the Communists to restrain capitalism. After various political maneuvers in parliament, Hitler was appointed the head of a new government in 1933. In the initial stages of the development of the police state, there is often a struggle for power and the focus of the regime is to liquidate all forms of organized resistance, both open and secret. Nazi Germany was not an exception. It established an extensive P P 3642 surveillance system that tracked down, arrested, and punished people opposed to it. So effective was this pursuit that the regime succeeded in crushing completely all forms of organized opposition. The Nazis banned all political parties, transforming Germany from a fledging multi-democratic state into a one-party state under the leadership of Hitler. In 1934, a nationwide plebiscite approved a law that made Hitler the Leader and Reich Chancellor; his authority was “total and all-embracing. . .and subject to no checks or controls” (Evans 2005, p. 44). One of the features of the police state is the dominance of the police in domestic politics. The military tends to occupy peripheral positions. There are at least two interrelated reasons for this state of affairs. First, regimes in police states tend not to have confidence in the military to make the necessary cognitive shift from its raison d’eˆtre of dealing with external threats to that of considering its own people as if they were foreign combatants. Second, police states aspire eventually to establish a world government (Arendt 1968). Consequently, they tend to approach the victims of their foreign aggressive adventures as though they were rebels, and therefore prefer to govern them with the police rather than the military. The Police State and Crime Control To understand the effectiveness of the mechanisms of crime control, it is prudent to first consider what law and crime mean under the police state. A key feature of law in democratic societies is that it brings a certain degree of certainty and predictability into aspects of relationships among citizens. The law is also applied prospectively, thereby allowing those subject to power to know in advance when they will be subject to coercion and thus avoiding needless interference in their lives. The opposite is true of police states; unpredictability and uncertainty were the main features of the law both in Germany under Hitler and Russia under Stalin. The law and procedures for its application are always in “continuous flux.” Police in the Police State In Nazi Germany, two states existed contemporaneously: the normative state and the prerogative state (Fraenkel 1941). The former was the formal institutions that existed prior to Hitler coming to power, and were bounded by long-standing rules, laws, and procedures. The Prerogative state was an extralegal institutional arrangement that derived its legitimacy from Hitler. Although initially characterized by conflict and sometimes accommodation, the relationship between the two eventually became one of subjugation; the spirit of the prerogative state permeated the normative state as it abandoned its legal procedures and gave approval to hitherto illegal state actions. Hitler’s word was law, and the legally correct procedure was as he deemed it. At any rate, the courts of the normative state were dominated by Nazi sympathizers; the Nazis disregarded the law, including laws enacted by themselves if this suited their convenience. Within this context is to be expected shifting definitions of crime and their punishments. Criminologists have long recognized that crimes are social constructions and that there is a great deal of variation between societies in perceptions of crime seriousness. Thus, the kind of behavior, utterance, or dissent that would be tolerated in liberal democratic societies is viewed as criminal in police states. For example, under the Malicious Gossip Law of 1934 in Nazi Germany, it was an offense to make “spiteful or provocative statements” in public against the governing party, to criticize its policies, or complain about suppression of freedoms and civil liberties. Whether the offense was for malicious gossip or not, the social identity of the offender was always an important consideration in determining the swiftness of police response and the severity of sentences by the courts. Thus, Jews, for instance, were punished more severely for criminal offenses that were otherwise overlooked or attracted very lenient sentences if committed by non-Jews. Once the police state has been established, there is a shift from dealing with the “suspect” to dealing with the “objective enemy” (Arendt 1968). The objective enemy is unlike the suspect in many ways. Suspects are people whose Police in the Police State previous and present deeds and “dangerous thoughts” give reason for the state to be suspicious about what they might do. They are people who oppose and desire to overthrow the government, or are believed to have committed crimes. The objective enemy, on the other hand, is the product of government policy irrespective of the orientations of those so defined. The objective enemy is seen as a “carrier of tendencies” considered a threat to the state. The government never runs out of objective enemies because new ones are easily found depending on the circumstances (Arendt 1968). For example, the Nazi regime had well-developed plans for the extermination of the Polish people when the extermination of Jews was near completion (Arendt 1968). This was to involve, among other things, attempts to impose regulations strikingly similar to what had been done before implementing “the final solution”: for example, change of names and the death penalty for racially undesirable marriages, such as those between Germans and Poles (Evans 2005). The secret police constitute the main channel through which orders of the government are transmitted. In addition to the change from dealing with suspects to attending to objective enemies is a corresponding change from suspected offense to possible crime: . . .every thought that deviates from the officially prescribed and permanently changing line is already suspect, no matter in which field of human activity it occurs. Simply because of their capacity to think, human beings are suspects by definition, and this suspicion cannot be diverted by exemplary behavior, for the human capacity to think is also a capacity to change one’s mind. Since, moreover, it is impossible ever to know beyond doubt another man’s heart . . .suspicion can no longer be allayed if neither a community of values nor the predictabilities of self-interest exist as social realities. (Arendt 1968, p. 430) The result of this is to create a system of ubiquitous spying, infusing hitherto healthy social relationships with mutual suspicion. Each person feels under constant surveillance; what was once methods employed exclusively for dealing with the population is now the methods that ordinary citizens employ to deal with their 3643 P neighbors in everyday encounters. As discussed later, however, scholars differ on whether fear, terror, and intimidation were as pervasive as it is often portrayed in popular accounts, or it was the case that citizens freely consented to the decisions and directives of the police. In the initial years of the establishment of the police state, the focus is primarily upon eliminating all sources of organized opposition. Concern with suspects of possible crimes assumes prominence when the regime is fully established. As the police state enters its last and fully totalitarian stage, it abandons the category of objective enemy and possible crime. The new category of “undesirables” replaces them. Here victims are chosen at random and officially declared unfit to live. In the well-documented case of the Nazis, undesirables included the mentally ill and persons with certain kinds of diseases. This introduction of arbitrariness means that the police state becomes far more efficient in suppressing freedoms; both the innocent and the guilty share the fate of being undesirable. But more importantly, this change in the concept of crime and criminals comes with new methods for law enforcement. Consistent with their task of executing executive orders, it is the responsibility of the police to ensure criminals are punished and undesirables disappear, often without a trace. The only trace victims leave behind are the memories of those who knew them; a challenging task for the secret police is to ensure that even this trace will disappear with the victims. The Russian secret police, for instance, employed elaborate network analysis of families, friends, and acquaintances of suspects with the aim to eliminating those believed to possess “dangerous memories” of the disappeared. Hannah Arendt has captured this well: In totalitarian countries all places of detention ruled by the police are made to be veritable holes of oblivion into which people stumble by accident and without leaving behind them such ordinary traces of former existence as a body and a grave. Compared with this newest invention for doing away with people, the old-fashioned method of murder, political or criminal, is inefficient indeed. The murderer leaves behind him a corpse, and although he tries to efface the traces of his own P P 3644 identity, he has no power to erase the identity of his victim from the memory of the surviving world. The operation of the secret police, on the contrary, miraculously sees to it that the victim never existed at all. (Arendt 1968, pp. 434–435) In common with their counterparts in democratic societies, the lifeblood of police work in the police state is information from the public. Two decades of empirical analyses of police legitimacy have shown that cooperation with police forces rests mainly on the perceived legitimacy of the police (Tyler 1990). Police states and their secret police forces were fully aware of this role of legitimacy in securing the flow of intelligence, and they devoted much energy and resources cultivating legitimacy among their publics. In Nazi Germany, the Gestapo relied upon the assistance of the German public, and there is strong evidence to show that many Germans responded positively, denouncing their neighbors, colleagues, and relatives to the secret police. The police in the police state also rely heavily on extensive networks of informers, both impressed and voluntary informers (Chapman 1970). The use of informers is not exclusive to police states; it is a technique that is also widely used by law enforcement agencies in democratic societies (Natapoff 2009). But informers are not always reliable sources of intelligence. The police therefore seek to operate their own sources of intelligence gathering by infiltrating areas of social and political life. Again, the strategy of infiltration is as much a practice of police states as it is of democratic states. The police in Nazi Germany were effective in destroying initial opposition to the regime and subsequently perceived enemies and undesirables such as Jews and social outsiders. Levels of petty criminality were however comparable to those that pertain in democratic societies. Johnson (2011) has shown that a large proportion of Germans committed crimes on a frequent basis, without much fear of being detected and punished. The reason for that situation was not ineffectiveness by the police; on the contrary, it was because the police prioritize other crimes over petty street-level offenses. Police in the Police State Citizens and the Police State How do citizens react to police states? This question divides historians of Germany under Hitler and Russia under Stalin, the two quintessential cases of police state in the twentieth century. There are two broad schools of thought. One school of thought holds that citizens consented voluntarily to the police state. Some studies have produced evidence to show that the Gestapo, for example, was a much smaller organization than it was often thought. Hitler was “so immensely popular among most Germans that intimidation and terror were rarely needed to enforce loyalty” (Johnson and Reuband 2005, p. 329). Gellately (1990) cites election results in support of a view that the Nazi regime was popular among the German people. The coercion the regime applied was aimed at only a small proportion of minorities but that was even done with the approval of the majority of the population. Apart from election results, the other reason for the claim that citizens did not experience the police state as an “all knowing, all powerful, and omniscient” is the size of the secret police. The ratio of secret police to citizens is estimated at 1 per 10,000 residents in the cities of the Third Reich, and usually with extremely limited presence in rural areas (Johnson 2011). The secret police, it is said, were after all not always well resourced, and therefore could not be said to have relied systematically on terror and coercion to induce citizen compliance. As further evidence, scholars argue that the reaction of the ordinary population was that of voluntary supply of information through denunciation of neighbors (Johnson 2011). A second school of thought contends that police organizations of police states were omnipresent and omnipotent, and that they employed arbitrary powers, repressive tactics, and unimaginable brutality against citizens. Consequently, citizens lived in fear and terror, mindful of the potentially ruthless repercussions from the police. Elections, it is argued, lacked integrity and therefore a poor measure of popular attitudes toward the police state. Far from being a society of “self-policing,” terror was widespread. Police in the Police State The Nazis regularly publicized executions, court proceedings, and sentences. The aim of the publicity was to deter potential offenders from underestimating the risk of being caught and punished (Evans 2005). It is fair to say that police states thrived upon a mixture of coercion and terror, and popular support both from within the security forces and the general population. There is no evidence throughout history to show that any regime relied exclusively on its ability to physically intimidate its subjects or citizens into obedience, not even the most “unjust and blood-minded dictatorship” (Fukuyama 1992, p. 16). The Nazis, for instance, “did not just seek to batter the population into passive, sullen acquiescence. They also wanted to rouse it into positive, enthusiastic endorsement of their ideals and their policies, to change people’s minds and spirits and to create a new German culture that would reflect their values alone” (Evans 2005, p. 118). The question that rises is whether one can speak of legitimacy under totalitarian regimes. It is a question that recalls a long-standing debate among scholars. Social scientists approach legitimacy (that is, recognition of the moral rightness of power) within the particular historical societies rather than universally. They are fully aware that what makes power legitimate in one society may differ from others, and that the conditions for legitimacy in one may be repudiated by another. This approach does not require the social scientist to make any judgment about the appropriateness or otherwise of the social order she investigates. A clear implication of this line of thought is that it is possible for a researcher to conclude that a police organization is legitimate in the empirical sense (that is, it finds wide moral acceptance among citizens) and yet for that researcher to believe that that organization is deeply unjust or even “evil.” It is on this conclusion that moral philosophers and some political scientists depart from Max Weber. For them, legitimacy relates to whether by some objective standards of ethical evaluation, a claim to legitimacy can be recognized as valid. The contention is that one cannot simply reduce legitimacy to a matter of fact, the 3645 P fact that citizens hold a certain belief about a regime. On the contrary, the concept should signify a normative evaluation of the correctness of the procedures, the justification for decisions, and the fairness with which regimes treat their subjects (Grafstein 1981). The full implication of this approach is that there is a need to connect analysis of legitimacy to theories about justice (Bottoms and Tankebe 2012). That is a discussion beyond the scope this entry. The point to note here, however, is that a focus on the public actions or behavior of citizens as the measure of their reactions to a regime, especially one that exercises unrestrained power, is unlikely to tell the whole story about power relations; indeed, it is likely to lead to the erroneous conclusion that “subordinate groups endorse the terms of their subordination and are willing, even enthusiastic, partners in that subordination” (Scott 1990, p. 4). What is known so far about the reactions of citizens to police states offers no assurance against this error. Conclusion It is commonplace to read from newspapers, and even from scholarly work, that some democratic societies are on a pathway to becoming police states. Such claims often arise from evidence that those states have undertaken certain measures to facilitate a greater surveillance of the population or a section of that population (e.g., the US Patriot Act and the UK CONTEST strategy for counterterrorism) and other forms of intrusion into private liberties of citizens. By any account, these are poor indicators of the police state; no state, democratic and totalitarian, can hope to respond effectively to threats in the modern world without some level of surveillance of (some) its population. The absence of conceptual clarity regarding the category of police state suggests that the greatest immediate need in assessing the utility of that category has to start with attempts to clarify its meaning. It appears that criminology can contribute toward that endeavor from two interrelated standpoints. First is to return to P P 3646 Edwin Sutherland’s well-known definition of criminology as the study of “the processes of law-making, of law-breaking, and of reacting to the breaking of laws” (Sutherland 1939, p. 1). At the heart of this triumvirate is the question of power, and how it is exercised. A second and related issue is for criminology to engage with the political science literature with the aim of procuring a proper understanding of democracy. That literature suggests that democratic societies are characterized by a universalistic ideological claim about human equality, that all human beings are of equal worth and therefore entitled to equal respect and treatment. Consequently, any exercise of power must do so with respect for the principles of individual liberty and equality. Democratic societies attempt to achieve this through mechanisms of democratic accountability of the police, including external oversight of police institutions that is independent of government. How effectively such oversight works is open to debate. What is true is that democracies differ from police states on this check on police power, and it is here that the search for conceptual clarity should begin. Related Entries ▶ Conceptualizing of Police ▶ Counterterrorism ▶ Democratic Policing ▶ Electronic Monitoring ▶ False Confessions and Police Interrogation ▶ Policing of Peacekeeping ▶ Surveillance Technology and Policing Recommended Reading and References Arendt H (1968) The origins of totalitarianism. Harcourt, London Bauman Z (2004) Wasted lives: modernity and its outcasts. Polity Press, Cambridge Bayley DH (1969) The police and political development in India. Princeton University Press, Princeton Blumer H (1954) What is wrong with social theory? Am Sociol Rev 19:3–10 Police in the Police State Bottoms AE, Tankebe J (2012) Beyond procedural justice: a dialogic approach to legitimacy in criminal justice. J Crim Law Criminol 102:119–170 Browder GC (1990) Foundations of the Nazi police state: the formation of Sipo and SD. University Press of Kentucky, Kentucky Brownlee ID (2007) Conditional cautions and fair trial rights in England and Wales: form versus substance in the diversionary agenda? Crim Law Rev 129–140 Chapman B (1970) Police state. Pall Mall Press, London Coicaud J-M (2002) Legitimacy and politics: a contribution to the study of political right and political responsibility. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK Evans RJ (2005) The third Reich in power: how the Nazis won over the hearts and minds of a nation. Penguin, London Fraenkel E (1941) The dual state: a contribution to the theory of dictatorship. Oxford University Press, New York Fukuyama F (1992) The end of history and the last man. Penguin Books, London Gellately R (1990) The Gestapo and German society: enforcing racial policy, 1933–1945. Oxford University Press, Oxford Giddens A (1985) The nation-state and violence. Polity Press, Cambridge Grafstein R (1981) The failure of Weber’s conception of legitimacy: its causes and implications. J Polit 43:456–472 Johnson EA (2011) Criminal justice, coercion and consent in ‘totalitarian’ society: the case of national socialist Germany. Brit J Criminol 51:599–614 Johnson EW, Reuband K-H (2005) What we knew: terror, mass murder, and everyday life in Nazi Germany: an oral history. Basic Books, Cambridge, MA Lukes I (1996) The birth of a police state: the Czechoslovak ministry of the interior, 1945–48. Intell Natl Sec 11:78–88 MacCormick N (2007) Institutions of law: an essay in legal theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford Natapoff A (2009) Snitching: criminal informants and the erosion of American justice. NYU Press, New York Neocleous M (2000) The fabrication of social order: a critical theory of police power. Pluto Press, London Raeff M (1983) The well-ordered police state: social and institutional change through law in the Germanies and Russia, 1600–1800. Yale University Press, New Haven/London Reith C (1956) A new study of police history. Oliver & Boyd, London Scott JC (1990) Domination and the arts of resistance: hidden transcripts. Yale University Press, New Haven/London Sutherland EH (1939) Principles of criminology. Lippincott, Philadelphia Tamanaha BZ (2004) On the rule of law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Police Integrity 3647 P Tyler T (1990) Why people obey the law. Yale University Press, Yale Weber M (1978) Economy and society: an outline of interpretive sociology (Roth G, Wittich C, eds), 2 vols. University of California Press, Berkeley Zureik E, Salter MB (2007) Global surveillance and policing: borders, security, and identity. Willan Publishing, Cullompton history on police integrity. The accompanying methodological approach has been utilized to survey police officers and to detect the contours of police integrity in nearly 20 countries across the world. Other research on police integrity explores the mechanisms used to enhance integrity and accountability, such as the early warning systems and citizen reviews. Police Integrity Police Integrity Sanja Kutnjak Ivkovic´ School of Criminal Justice, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI, USA Introduction In the 1990s, a wave of police misconduct scandals shook the country, from the police corruption scandal in New York, which prompted the establishment of the Mollen Commission, the Rodney King beating, which resulted in the establishment of the Christopher Commission, the Abner Luima sexual violence case in New York, which resulted in $8.75 million dollar settlement, and the Rampart Division scandal in Los Angeles. In 1997, the Office of Community Oriented Policing Services (COPS) and the National Institute of Justice (NIJ) held a national symposium bringing together policy makers and social scientists to address this emerging problem. A natural tendency would be to anchor the conference on the events that signal the lack of integrity. That is, the discussion would center on various forms of misconduct and the ways of controlling them. As Hickman and colleagues (2004, p. 1.1) put it, “[a]ll too often we infer integrity from its demonstrated absence. That is to say, research that focuses on corruption infers ideas about integrity absent its measurement.” Instead, the COPS/NIJ team decided to use the term police integrity as the guiding theme for the conference (Greenberg 1997, p. v): Overview Police integrity and police misconduct are closely related; traditionally, the discussion of police integrity typically would focus on the events that signal the lack of integrity (e.g., forms of police misconduct and the ways of controlling them). Since the mid-1990s, the focus has shifted on police integrity, which, in turn, allows for the exploration of a broader concept – the development of a high-integrity police agency. Police integrity is defined as “the normative inclination among police to resist temptations to abuse the rights and privileges of their occupation” (Klockars et al. 2006). Although police integrity could be associated with the moral virtues of individual police officers, starting with the writings by Herman Goldstein in the 1970s, the idea has started to develop that this “bad apple” theory of police corruption is inadequate and that a more organizational approach should be used instead. Klockars and colleagues (Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2004; Klockars et al. 1997) built upon this view and proposed their theory of police integrity. The theory features four dimensions: organizational rulemaking, detection, investigation, and discipline of rule violations, curtailing the code of silence, and the influence of public expectations and agency The focus on “police integrity” opened a whole new domain. Although previous research, study, and experimentation had focused on critical issues such as corruption and excessive use of force, these approaches, had, in fact, revolved around single dimension. As a result, the solutions were constricted in that they were derived out of a need to control unwanted behaviors of individuals. In comparison, police integrity guided the focus on P P 3648 the broader domain of developing a healthy organization that would serve to reinforce and maintain the good character and constructive motivations of many of the individuals joining the ranks of law enforcement. In July of 1996, about 200 police leaders, politicians, lawyers, and researchers attended a three-day National Symposium on Police Integrity in Washington, D.C. (Gaffigan and McDonald 1997). Among the participants who tried to define police integrity, the preferred approach was to envision a police officer with high integrity and list the characteristics (e.g., virtues, values, and character traits) that separate this police officer apart from other police officers of lower integrity. The characteristics explicitly listed at the Symposium were allegiance, courage, honor, honesty, prudence, trust, effacement of self-interest, intellectual honesty, justice, morality, principled behavior, responsibility, and dedication to mission (Vicchio 1997). Mark Moore was in charge of summarizing the findings of the symposium; he wrote that “[w]hat we mean by integrity and professionalism is law-abiding character, technical confidence, neutrality, distance – in Steve Vicchio’s wonderful phrase, ‘the effacement of personal interest’ – and probably some notion of courtesy and client responsiveness” (Moore 1997, p. 63). Similarly, Hickman and colleagues wrote in their introductory remarks to a co-edited book on police integrity that “police integrity refers to the underlying values and ethical attachment of the police and how those values and ethics affect police behavior” (Hickman et al. 2004, p. 1.1). These lists of characteristics contain expected individual police officers’ character traits. As Klockars and colleagues argue (2006, p. xiv), “[t]he fact is that any virtue – charity, compassion, decency, faith, loyalty, passion, patience, and perspective, to add but a few to the list mentioned at the Symposium – is at least arguably as crucial to the integrity of a professional police officer as any other and this approach gives us no guidance whatsoever in prioritizing this litany.” Yet, some of the officers who exhibit these characteristics may Police Integrity decide not to act in accordance with high integrity, just like the police officers who do not possess many of these characteristics may decide to act in accordance with high integrity. Finally, these character traits are features of individuals and they close the possibility that police integrity could be an organizational feature as well. Since 1996, the issue of police integrity has been discussed at several conferences (“the 1999 NIJ/NYU Seminar on Police Integrity and Democracies; the 1999 Strengthening Police-Community Relationships conference; the 2000 biannual conference Policing in Central and Eastern Europe: Ethics, Integrity, and Human Right (Pagon 2000); the 1998 Sixth International Conference on Ethics: Integrity at the Public-Private Interface (Huberts and van den Heuvel 1999”)), and continues to be explored bi-annually at corruption conferences such as the Global Forum against Corruption and Safeguarding Integrity and the Transparency International’s International Anti-Corruption Conference. The US Department of Justice provided a publication addressing the Principles for Promoting Police Integrity (2001). The co-edited book Police Integrity and Ethics (Hickman et al. 2004) contains chapters addressing various aspects of police integrity. However, the understanding of what police integrity is, and what should be covered under this topic, varies substantially across conference organizers, presenters, and authors. A substantial portion of the literature seeks to develop integrity-enhancing mechanisms or mechanisms that would control police misconduct (Pope 2000; Transparency International 2001; U.S. Department of Justice 2001; See ▶ Control of Police Misconduct). Yet, it seems that even the basic debate regarding what constitutes police integrity has not been resolved. Sam Walker, a leading expert on police accountability, points out that “[t]he issue of police integrity is extremely important and has received an increasing amount of public attention among policy makers and the general public. Unfortunately, the academic literature has not adequately addressed this very important subject” (2004, p. vii). Police Integrity Definition Klockars and colleagues (Klockars et al. 2006) have provided a definition of police integrity that goes beyond the traditional focus on individual police officers’ character traits and allows for the organizational approach toward it. They have also accompanied the definition with a theory of police integrity and the methodological approach toward its measurement. Klockars and colleagues (2006) define police integrity as “the normative inclination among police to resist temptations to abuse the rights and privileges of their occupation.” According to the authors (Klockars et al. 2006), this definition has six critical components. Normative – The normative aspect of the definition emphasizes that integrity is based on the moral norms of right and wrong (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 1) that tell people what they should or should not do. Thus, integrity combines a belief in moral values with an inclination to behave in accordance with that belief; “[j]ust as a belief in honesty inclines one to avoid lying and a belief in fidelity obliges one to be faithful, integrity requires not only a belief that certain behaviors are right or wrong, but also actions that are in accord with those beliefs” (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 2). Inclination to Resist – This part of the definition emphasizes the difference between attitudes and behavior. The authors do not expect that the person of high integrity will always behave in accordance with these values. Rather, they discuss a general problem that people who believe in honesty sometimes lie; people who believe in fidelity sometimes are unfaithful; and people of integrity sometimes do things they know are wrong. Three dimensions of the relation between police attitudes of integrity and police misconduct are addressed. The first point the authors emphasize is that, while integrity describes the normative inclination to resist temptations, integrity is not the only source (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 3). Other possible candidates include the lack of imagination, lack of opportunity, fear of discovery and public humiliation, shame, punishment, or a simple unfavorable risk/reward 3649 P calculus as potentially critical in ensuring that police officers behave honestly. The second point the authors emphasize is that that attitudes of integrity put at least some pressure on police officers who share them to actually avoid wrongful behavior. Because these attitudes of integrity may lead police officers to comply with the rules and, at the same time, may not necessarily be the driving force behind compliant behavior, the authors have decided to refer to integrity as the inclination to resist rather than the actual resistance to temptations. The third point the authors emphasize is that the direction of the causal relation between attitudes of integrity and behavior of integrity is not always absolutely clear. In particular, while attitudes may cause behavior, behavior may also cause attitudes. Requiring of police officers to behave in accordance with integrity may lead them to adopt the attitudes of integrity as well. Police – Klockars et al. (2006) emphasize that integrity is a characteristic of the “police,” without specifying that this is a characteristic of individual police officers or police agencies. This reflects the view that integrity may be a feature of an individual police officer, a group of police officers, a subunit of a police agency, a whole police agency, or police agencies. The authors caution that the discussion about police integrity easily lapses into the discussion of integrity at the police officers’ individual level. Yet, police integrity is also an organizational feature – a feature of police agencies, organizations, and institutions – and we can discuss organizational cultures of police integrity. However, the discussion of the dynamics and the relevant correlates of police integrity will differ depending on the level of integrity under discussion (e.g., individual, organizational); “[h]ow one understands and explains the psychology of integrity of an individual police officer will most certainly differ from the understanding and explanation of the evolution of a culture of integrity in a police agency” (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 3). Temptations – The motivation or the reasons why police officers engage in misconduct could vary dramatically across forms of police P P 3650 misconduct, individual police officers, and police agencies. The most obvious of these temptations is gain, the monetary or non-monetary reward for type of police misbehavior, a typical feature of traditional police corruption. However, other forms of police misconduct are not necessarily motivated by gain; different forms of police misconduct are by no means the product of a similar, singular, or even ignoble temptation. The example of use of excessive force is particularly illustrative (Klockars 1995, p. 17): . . .[the excessive force] need not (and usually will not) be the product of malicious or sadistic behavior. It can spring from good intentions as well as bad, mistakes and misreading, lack of experience, overconfidence, momentary inattention, physical or mental fatigue, experimentation, inadequate or improper training, prejudice, passion, an urge to do justice or demonstrate bravery, misplaced trust, boredom, illness, a specific incompetence, or a hundred other factors that might influence an officer to behave in a particular situation in a less than expert way. Klockars et al. (2006) conclude that the methods used to control misconduct should differ depending on the type of temptation and argue that the methods used to control corruption could be quite different for the methods used to control the use of excessive force. They also infer not only that the contours of integrity may be very different in different police agencies, but also that the contours of police integrity within the same police agency could be different depending on the form of police misconduct. They argue that police integrity need not be a uniform phenomenon. Consequently, “it is not difficult to imagine a police organization or subculture that was highly intolerant of officer theft, soliciting bribes, taking kickbacks and other acts of corruption and at the same time was much more accepting of discourtesy, excessive force, perjury, forging records, fabricating evidence, or unwarranted or illegal searches” (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 4). The authors proceed to note that one could also expect that police officers who succumbed to the temptations of one variety (e.g., gain) may also be more likely to succumb to the temptations of another variety (e.g., prejudice). Police Integrity Abuse – A crucial element of the definition is the concept of abuse. In many situations, the abuse of office is obvious (e.g., a police officer accepts a bribe in exchange for letting the citizen caught violating the speeding limit). However, the discussion of whether particular behavior is abusive is confounded by two possible arguments. The first argument flatly denies that the behavior in question is abusive. For example, the police officers’ acceptance of discounts, holiday gifts, free food, and liquor could be viewed as gestures of goodwill, hospitality, and/or gratitude. The second argument recognizes that the behavior could be abusive, but justifies and excuses it as an expression of “street justice.” As Klockars and colleagues (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 5) elaborate, “[a] common theme is that police are ‘human’ and cannot be expected to behave without normal human emotions in situations in which they are insulted, defied, assaulted, deceived, shocked, repulsed, disgusted, or horrified by the conduct of those they police.” The Rights and Privileges of Their Occupation – Policing is a highly discretionary, coercive activity that routinely takes place in private settings, out of the sight of supervisors, and before witnesses who are often regarded as unreliable. Policing as an occupation is rife with opportunities for misconduct, as independent commission reports and scholarly studies clearly demonstrate (see, e.g., Christopher Commission 1991; Knapp Commission 1972; Manning and Redlinger 1993; Mollen Commission 1994; Pennsylvania Crime Commission 1974). Causes of Police Integrity Until relatively recently, the prevailing administrative view of integrity (at least in the United States) was to associate integrity with the moral virtues of individual police officers; consequently, the tendency was to fight corruption, for example, by carefully screening applicants for police positions, pursuing defective officers aggressively, and removing them from their police positions before their behavior spreads throughout the agency (see, e.g., Knapp Commission 1972). In the 1970s, Police Integrity Herman Goldstein (1975) embarked on the pioneering work and argued that this “bad apple” theory of police corruption is inadequate and that a more organizational approach should be used instead. Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ and their colleagues (Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2004; Klockars et al. 1997) built upon this view and proposed their theory of police integrity. This approach stresses the importance of four distinct dimensions, each of which is profoundly organizational in nature. Organizational Rulemaking – The first dimension of the organizational theory of police integrity addresses organizational rule making (see, e.g., Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003; Klockars et al. 1997) and relates police misconduct to the ways police agencies create, teach, and enforce rules explicitly prohibiting misbehavior (Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003, p. 1.4). In countries with highly decentralized police organization, as is the case with the United States, police agencies could differ dramatically in the nature of the behavior they prohibit. First, agencies could differ in terms of whether they have official rules at all. Some agencies may have no written rules, particularly if they are very small (fewer than 10 police officers), while others, particularly if they are very large (with 500 sworn officers or more), may have extremely lengthy official rules (e.g., standard operating procedures, official rules). Second, when they do have the official rules established, the behaviors those rules allow and prohibit may differ substantially from agency to agency. This is particularly the case for less serious forms of misconduct such as mala prohibita corrupt behavior (e.g., receipt of favors, gratuities, small gifts, free meals, and discounts, off-duty employment). The problem of organizational rulemaking is further complicated by the fact that in many agencies, while an agency’s official policy formally prohibits certain activities, the agency’s unofficial policy tolerates them (see, e.g., Knapp Commission 1972; Mollen Commission 1994). The obligations of rulemaking require police agencies not only to 3651 P develop both formal and informal rules that specify agency expectations of integrity, but also to teach these rules and enforce them. As Klockars and colleagues conclude (2006, p. 9), “[i]n a police agency of integrity police officers ought to know the agency’s integrity relevant rules, understand the agency’s rationale for them, and believe in the rightness of both.” Detecting, Investigating, and Disciplining Rule Violations – The second dimension of the organizational theory of police integrity focuses on both the creation and maintenance of activities that permit detection, investigation, and discipline of misconduct (see, e.g., Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003; Klockars et al. 1997). The activities are heterogeneous by nature. They include not only reactive and proactive investigations by police agencies, but also inspections, audits, early-warning systems, external reviews, reception of citizen complaints, and integrity testing. The extent to which these activities have been implemented and actually used by a police agency varies substantially across the agencies. According to Klockars and colleagues (2006, p. 9), in a police agency of integrity the occupational culture of the agency will support the introduction and management of the activities employed to detect, investigate, and discipline rule-violating behavior. Circumscribing “The Code” – The third dimension of the organizational theory of police integrity emphasizes the police agency’s obligation to circumscribe the code of silence (i.e., “the blue curtain,” “the code”). The code of silence refers to the norm of the police culture which prohibits reporting of misconduct by fellow police officers (see, e.g., Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003; Klockars et al. 1997). However, although potentially viewed as a single norm that could apply to all police officers, the reality is that the code of silence could vary substantially. First, exactly what behavior – in terms of its nature and seriousness – is covered by the code varies enormously across police agencies. The code of silence in some agencies may cover only the least serious forms of corruption (e.g., the acceptance of gratuities and small gifts), while in others it can cover even the most serious forms of P P 3652 corruption (e.g., thefts from crime scenes, the acceptance of bribes from motorists caught speeding). Second, to whom the benefit of the code’s protection is extended could also vary extensively. In some agencies, the code could be limited to protect only misconduct by partners, viewed a testimonial immunity that would be a mirror image of traditionally privileged relationships (husband and wife, physician and patient, lawyer and client). In other agencies, the code could protect misconduct not only by police partners, but also by all police officers working on the same shift, section, or unit. Klockars and colleagues (2006, p. 9) write about the close relation between the code of silence and integrity: Many police administrators probably understand that circumscribing both whom and what The Code covers should be an administrative priority . . . However virtually all police administrators were line officers at some point in their careers, and thus they have at least an appreciation, if not an affection, for the bonds of collegial loyalty and fraternal support that are part of the subculture of policing. To the extent that circumscribing The Code requires the weakening of those bonds of loyalty and support, it is a task that not a few police administrators approach with ambivalence. A police agency of integrity is one in which the occupational culture is intolerant of those who abuse the rights and privileges of their office. The Influence of Public Expectations and Agency History on Police Integrity – The fourth dimension of the organizational theory of police integrity relates to the influence of the social and political environment in which police institutions, systems, and agencies operate (see, e.g., Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003; Klockars et al. 1997). This theory argues that the integrity of a police agency is affected by the larger social and political environment in which it operates (Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2003). Although this understanding – the idea that the police agency is affected by its environment – is the underlying assumption of virtually all historical studies of police, Reiss and Bordua (1967; Reiss 1971) were the pioneers who provided the first systematic exploration of the topic. When the society at large expects ethical behavior of its officials, police agencies are also Police Integrity more likely to set high expectations and expect ethical behavior from its employees. Not only do the expectations of integrity differ enormously across the world (see, e.g., Transparency International Corruption Perceptions Index), but they could also differ within the same country. Using the United States as an example, Klockars and colleagues (2006, p. 10) argue that some parts of the country have long and virtually uninterrupted traditions of persistent police corruption (e.g., Chicago, New Orleans, Key West), some areas have equally long traditions of integrity (e.g., Milwaukee, Kansas City), and other areas have undergone repeated cycles of scandal and reform (e.g., New York, Philadelphia, Oakland). In the end, Klockars and colleagues conclude that “not only public expectations about police integrity exert vastly different pressures on police agencies in different areas, but also police agencies of integrity may effectively resist such pressures” (2006, p. 10). Measuring the Extent of Police Integrity Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ (2003) designed a questionnaire that seeks to measure the extent of police integrity in systematic, standardized, and quantitative manner. The respondents were provided with a letter asking them to assume that the officer described in the scenarios had been a police officer for 5 years, had a satisfactory working record, and had not been disciplined in the past. The first version of the questionnaire contains 11 hypothetical scenarios focusing mostly on corruption and ranging from those merely giving an appearance of a conflict of interest to those describing incidents of bribery and theft (Klockars and Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2004; Klockars et al. 1997). The second version of the questionnaire went beyond seeing police integrity as the opposite of police corruption and includes a range of police misconduct such as the use of excessive force, failure to execute an arrest warrant, and falsification of official record, as well as police corruption. Each scenario is followed by the same set of seven questions that ask about police officers’ knowledge of official rules, their opinion about the seriousness of particular rule-violating behaviors, the discipline Police Integrity these behaviors should receive and would actually receive, and their estimates of how willing they would be to report such behavior. The first version of the questionnaire has been distributed across 30 police agencies in the United States (Klockars et al. 1997, 2000), characterized with a decentralized police. The authors reported substantial differences across the agencies. Although the sample of police agencies is not nationally representative, but a convenience sample, it nevertheless illustrates the point that the level of police integrity could vary substantially across the police agencies. Klockars and colleagues (2000) created a ranking of police agencies based on their levels of integrity. The authors (Klockars et al. 2006, p. 37) note: In some police agencies in our sample police officers found nearly half of the behaviors described in our sample to be of sufficient seriousness to merit dismissal. In those agencies officers also claimed that they and their police colleagues were highly likely to report all but the least serious forms of misconduct. In other agencies only theft from a crime scene was, in the opinion of a plurality of respondents, sufficient grounds to fire a police officer and not even that offence would motivate the majority of officers in such agencies to break the Code of Silence and report the misconduct of a colleague. A comparison of the results from the two large municipal police agencies, one ranked at the top and one at the bottom of the police integrity scale, shows large differences in how serious police officers perceive misconduct, what discipline they expect and approve, and how wiling they seem to be to report the fellow officers’ misconduct. With one exception, police officers from the agency at the bottom of the police integrity scale would not expect the police officer to be dismissed for any of the behaviors described in the questionnaire, while the police officers from the agency at the top of the police integrity scale expected dismissal in four most serious cases. In addition, Klockars and colleagues (Klockars et al. 2006) found stark contrasts in the extent of the code of silence between the two agencies: in the agency ranked at the top of the integrity scale, the majority of police officers 3653 P reported that their colleagues would report their fellow officer who engaged in the behavior described in all cases. On the other hand, the majority of police officers from the agency ranked at the bottom of police integrity scale did not expect their fellow officers to report misconduct in any of the described cases. However, as the subsequent study of three large municipal police agencies (identified to be in the top third of the police integrity scale) demonstrates, police agencies can be quite diverse in the ways they create and maintain their integrity (Klockars et al. 2006). The authors studied each of these three agencies – Charleston, South Carolina; Charlotte-Mecklenburg, North Carolina; and St. Petersburg, Florida – for two years and have developed their integrity profiles. Since 1996, nearly two dozen studies have used this first police integrity survey. Three studies (Micucci and Gomme 2009; Burbach Raines 2009; Marche 2009) analyzed the 30-agency data collected by Klockars and colleagues, and another four studies (Chappell and Piquero 2004; Hickman, et al. 2004; Schafer and Martinelli 2008, Gottschalk 2009) used the police integrity questionnaire as the basis for their surveys of other US police agencies. In addition to the US agencies, the same questionnaire has been used in nearly 20 countries across the world, including Austria, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Canada, Croatia, the Czech Republic, Finland, Hungary, Japan, the Netherlands, Pakistan, Poland, Slovenia, South Africa, Sweden, and the UK (see Klockars et al. 2004). Although the list of the countries participating in the survey is far from exhaustive, the findings clearly show that the levels of police integrity differ substantially and significantly, analogously to the tremendous variation in the levels of police integrity across the 30 US police agencies. The nature and extent of police integrity measured in the countries such as Finland and Sweden is quite different from the nature and extent of the police integrity measured in countries such as South Africa and Pakistan (see Klockars et al. 2004). The differences are visible not only in the police officers’ perceptions P P 3654 of seriousness and willingness to report, but also in their views of appropriate and expected discipline (Klockars et al. 2004, p. 13): It appears that in each country the seriousness of officers’ misconduct is, in large part, determined by the absolute level of discipline the organization is expected to visit on the offending officer. In almost every case, when the police organization is expected to punish a offense very severely, officers regard that offense as serious. Conversely, when organizations do not punish misbehavior severely, as is the case in Hungary, Pakistan, and South Africa, officers seem to have little ability to distinguish among the levels of seriousness with regard to misconduct. Perhaps the most dramatic finding that emerges from examining the contours of integrity concerns the worldwide prevalence of the code of silence. The authors continue to note that, in five out of 14 countries included in the book “Contours of Police Integrity,” the code of silence would cover misconduct described in every scenario (Klockars et al. 2004, p. 17). In addition, the code of silence would protect behaviors such as the acceptance of a bribe from a person caught speeding – a violation of the penal code – in nine out of 14 countries. The heterogeneity of police integrity is influenced by a host of reasons; a police agency’s local social, political, economic, and legal environments influence its level of police integrity. Research indicates that countries that belong to the same category along one dimension (e.g., economic development, geographic location) still have different levels of police integrity. This is the case for both developed democracies (e.g., the USA and the UK) and countries in transition (e.g., Croatia and Hungary), as is the case for countries from Northern America (e.g., the USA and Canada) and Europe (e.g., Croatia and the Netherlands). The second version of the questionnaire, exploring the resistance to various sources of temptations (not only police corruption), has been developed as well. The initial work by Klockars and colleagues explored the extent of police integrity in three US police agencies using both versions of the questionnaire (see Klockars et al. 2006). The comparative efforts are underway, with the first results coming from Croatia Police Integrity (Kutnjak Ivkovic´ 2009), South Korea (Kutnjak Ivkovic´ and Kang 2011), and South Africa (Kutnjak Ivkovic´ and Sauerman 2012). Other Research on Police Integrity The issues of police integrity and police misconduct are closely interconnected. Please see separate entries addressing different forms of police misconduct (e.g., “police corruption,” “use of excessive force,” “police lying”). A few writings explicitly connect police misconduct (or any of its specific forms) with police integrity. For example, Garner and colleagues (2004) studied the patterns in the police use of force as a way of measuring police integrity. The authors (Garner et al. 2004, p. 6.119) conclude that, although the average extent of force used by the police during a typical arrest is about equal across racial categories (and thus should be taken as an indication of police integrity), the extent of force used by the police during a typical arrest of male suspects is larger than the quantity of force used during a typical arrest of female suspects (and thus should be taken as an indication of the lack of police integrity). In 2001, the US Department of Justice published Principles of Promoting Police Integrity. The publication, available in print and on the Internet, lists the “best practices” for promoting integrity. The first part of the publication explores the use of force, complaint and misconduct investigations, training, recruitment, hiring, and retention, as well as general principles of promoting accountability and effective police management. The second part of the publication contains examples of promising police practices and policies, as well as the research projects on police integrity funded by the US Department of Justice. Many of the practices that should be used to enhance integrity (e.g., complaint misconduct investigations, the early warning systems, citizen reviews), at the same time, are mechanisms of accountability. Publications like that, focusing on the specific mechanisms or practices that should be used to enhance integrity, have significantly grown in numbers since the late 1990s. A separate body of research focuses on these mechanisms. Please see the entry “Control of Police Misconduct.” Police Integrity Related Entries ▶ Control of Police Misconduct ▶ History of Police Unions ▶ Police and the Excessive Use of Force ▶ Police Corruption ▶ Police Culture ▶ Police Discretion and Its Control ▶ Police Lying and Deception Recommended Reading and References Burbach Raines J (2009) Ethics in policing: misconduct and integrity. Jones and Barlett, Sudbury Chappell AT, Piquero AR (2004) Applying social learning theory to police misconduct. Deviant Behav 25:89–108 Gaffigan SJ, McDonald PP (eds) (1997) Police integrity: public service with honor. U.S. Department of Justice, Washington, DC. http://www.ncjrs.org/pdffiles/ 163811.pdf. Accessed 8 Apr 2006 Garner JH, Maxwell CD, Heraux C (2004) Patterns of police use of force as a measure of police integrity. In: Hickman M, Piquero AR, Greene JR (eds) Police integrity and ethics. Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, Belmont, p vii Goldstein H (1975) Police corruption: a perspective on its nature and control. The Police Foundation, Washington, DC Gottschalk P (2009) Crime-based survey instrument for police integrity measurement. Policing Int J Police Strateg Manag 33(1):52–68 Greenberg SF (1997) Executive summary. In: Gaffigan SJ, McDonald PP (eds) Police integrity: public service with honor. U.S. Department of Justice, Washington, DC. http://www.ncjrs.org/pdffiles/163811.pdf, p. v. Accessed 8 Apr 2006 Hickman M, Piquero AR, Greene JR (eds) (2004) Police integrity and ethics. Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, Belmont Huberts LWJC, van den Heuvel JHJ (eds) (1999) Integrity at the public-private interface. Shaker Publishing B.V, Maastricht Klockars, C. (1995). A Theory of Excessive Force and Its Control. In William A. Geller & Hans Toch (Eds.), And Justice for All. Washington, D.C.: Police Executive Research Forum, pp. 11-29. Klockars CB, Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S (2003) Measuring police integrity. In: Hickman MJ, Piquero AR, Greene JR (eds) Police integrity and ethics. Wadsworth, Belmont Klockars CB, Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S, Harver WE, Haberfeld MR (1997) The measurement of police integrity. Final Report Submitted to the U.S. Department of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, National Institute of Justice 3655 P Klockars CB, Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S, Harver WE, Haberfeld MR (2000) The Measurement of Police Integrity. Research in Brief. U.S. Department of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, National Institute of Justice. Government Printing Office, Washington, DC Klockars CB, Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S, Haberfeld MR (eds) (2004) The contours of police integrity. Sage, Newbury Park Klockars CB, Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S, Haberfeld MR (2006) Enhancing police integrity. Springer, New York Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S (2009) The Croatian police, police integrity, and transition toward Democratic policing. Policing Int J Police Strateg Manag 32(3):459–488 Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S, Kang W (2011) Police integrity in South Korea. Policing Int J Police Strateg Manag 35(1):76–103 Kutnjak Ivkovic´ S, Sauerman A (2012) Curtailing the code of silence among the South African Police. Policing: Int J Police Strateg Manag (forthcoming) Manning PK, Redlinger L (1993) The invitational edges of police construction. In: Klockars C, Mastrofski S (eds) Thinking about police. McGraw Hill, New York, pp 398–412 Marche GE (2009) Integrity, culture, and scale: an empirical test of the big bad police agency. Crime Law Soc Change 51:463–486 Micucci AJ, Gomme IM (2009) American police and subcultural support for the use of excessive force. J Crim Justice 33:487–500 Moore M (1997) Epilogue, police integrity. In: Public service with honor. U.S. Department of Justice. https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles/163811.pdf. Retrieved on Oct 10 2012 Pagon M (ed) (2000) Policing in central and Eastern Europe: ethics, integrity, and human rights. College of Police and Security Studies, Ljubljana Pope J (2000) Confronting corruption. The elements of a national integrity system (TI Source book 2000). Transparency International, Berlin. http://www.transparency.org. Accessed 8 Apr 2006 Reiss AJ Jr (1971) The police and the public. Yale University Press, New Haven Reiss AJ Jr, Bordua DJ (1967) Environment and organization: a perspective on the police. In: Bordua D (ed) The police: six sociological essays. Wiley, New York Schafer JA, Martinelli TJ (2008) First-line supervisor’s perceptions of police integrity. Policing Int J Police Strateg Manag 31(2):306–323 Transparency International (2001) The national integrity system. Concept and practice. A report by Transparency International (TI) for the global forum II on fighting corruption and safeguarding integrity. Transparency International, Berlin U.S. Department of Justice (2001) Principles for promoting police integrity; examples of promising police practices and policies. U.S. Department of Justice, Washington, DC. http://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/ojp/ 186189.pdf. Retrieved on 8 Apr 2006 P P 3656 Vicchio SJ (1997) Ethics and police integrity: some definitions and questions for study. In: Gaffigan SJ, McDonald PP (eds) Police integrity: public service with honor. U.S. Department of Justice, Washington, DC Walker S (2004) Forward. In: Hickman M, Piquero AR, Greene JR (eds) Police integrity and ethics. Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, Belmont, p vii Police Interrogation ▶ Law of Police Interrogation Police Interrogation general theories of leadership and organizational behavior might be used to explain aspects of police organizations (Adlam and Villiers 2003). This is often the approach taken in textbooks and professional literature. The second approach examines the styles and methods supervisors use in seeking to influence subordinate personnel (Engel 2001). The entry begins by briefly reviewing the dominant implications arising from these two traditions. It continues with an examination of what research evidence suggests about the ability of police leaders to influence unit productivity and output. The entry concludes by considering how different generations of police personnel and leaders might respond to different styles of leadership. Police Leadership Styles Joseph A. Schafer Department of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, IL, USA Overview Leadership is of central importance to the operation of effective, efficient, and equitable police organizations, yet it remains an elusive concept. It is clear that good leadership is vital to ensure that an agency operates in a manner that preserves public legitimacy and trust. Among the compelling evidence in support of this assertion is the fact that a crisis of leadership is often associated with major scandals in police agencies. Despite recognizing that strong leadership is of vital importance, scholars and police organizations have struggled to measure and understand a number of key questions, including what leadership styles are commonly used by police supervisors, when and how supervisors can influence subordinate performance and output, and what distinguishes between effective and less effective leaders. This entry considers the topic of police leadership styles. Literature considering leadership in police organizations can be separated into two major approaches. First, some write about how Introduction At the onset it is important to distinguish between police management and police leadership. Police supervisors are often interchangeably referred to as managers and leaders. Management is the control of routine processes and the maintenance of the status quo. Leadership emphasizes changes that will improve processes, personnel, and organizations. Effective supervisors tend to excel at both management and leadership, because both skill sets are important. However, they are not of the same quality, and policing has tended to emphasize management far more than leadership to its own detriment. It should also be noted that leadership is a behavior that can be independent of formal rank or authority. Some very prominent and influential leaders in police organizations are front-line personnel. Much of what has been written about police “leadership” is actually describing aspects of managing, administering, and supervising police organizations and personnel. The emphasis of this entry is on true leadership, not what is often described in policing literature (including academic scholarship, which has tended to confuse management and leadership). Leaders innovate, take calculated (and often necessarily) risks, encourage and develop personnel, and are willing to challenge tradition and status quo. This does not imply that leaders blindly Police Leadership Styles challenge anything, everything, and everyone in the organization. Rather, they have the courage to confront the pointless, mindless, counterproductive aspects of their organizations and its practices. This tendency is sorely lacking in many aspects of the modern public sector, particularly policing. Though much has been written about leadership in broader settings, especially in corporate, military, political, and athletic contexts, policing scholars have given limited empirical consideration to matters of leaders and leadership. The traditional perspective found in police literature tends to cast leaders as using a narrow range of directive and controlling styles; as a consequence, supervisor-subordinate relationships are characterized by tension and animosity (Rowe 2006; Van Maanen 1984). More recently, research evidence has suggested an alternative perspective. Leaders have increasingly been framed as using a range of styles and approaches when interacting with those they seek to influence. These clusters of leadership approaches go beyond the traditional, authoritarian, and autocratic supervisory approaches that once dominated policing (Kuykendall and Unsinger 1982). It is quite likely this change reflects a very real transformation in leadership styles observed in policing. Major Theories Relevant to Police Leadership A wide array of theories has been offered to describe and explain the behavior of individuals and organizations. Some of the earliest studies of leaders and leadership tended to focus on the “great man/great woman” tradition. Wellregarded leaders were studied in a biographical format in the hope of deriving an understanding of the behaviors and actions that contributed to their perceived success. Over time, studies expanded this tradition by examining samples of recognized leaders. Modern research continues to seek an understanding of the casual links between leader traits and subsequent efficacy; what characteristics, habits, and behaviors differentiate leaders who are most effective from their peers? 3657 P Because early studies were concerned with the traits and habits of leaders, they tended to pay less attention to followers. The latter were often seen as liabilities and risks that organizations and supervisors needed to manage through control, policy, procedure, reporting requirements, and similar of mechanisms. This was based on what Douglas McGregor (1960) referred to as Theory X assumptions, and it led to a very distinctive, controlling, directive form of management. In contrast, McGregor described Theory Y approaches that were predicated on the belief that people can achieve good work outcomes when they are given the proper motivation and environment. As a result, Theory Y management approaches emphasize creating the optimal environment in which employees can be engaged and empowered, rather than seeking to regulate and constrain their choices and behavior. James Burns observed a similar duality in the nature of leader-follower interactions, writing about “transactional” and “transformational” approaches to leadership (1978). Transactional leaders were seen as emphasizing exchanges and quid pro quo arrangements with the personnel they supervised. Followers were provided with an understanding of what they were to accomplish and how it was to be achieved; they also understood what they would receive for adhering to those expectations and the consequences of violating accepted practices. The role of leaders in such arrangements was not to provide leadership; in actuality, they were there to monitor and manage followers, grant rewards when earned, and issue discipline when needed. Followers were given “carrots” (rewards) for good behavior and faced the risks of “sticks” (punishments) if they did not produce the expected outcomes in the expected way. In contrast, transformational leadership was characterized as a process of seeking to improve organizations, operations, and personnel. Leaders truly lead rather than just managing and maintaining the status quo. To accomplish this outcome, transformational leaders sought to inspire employees to embrace a shared vision and empowered them to use discretion and creativity in the pursuit of that outcome. Followers P P 3658 were given the freedom to make choices, the authority to develop new ideas, and the independence to identify and implement ways to pursue the leader’s vision. In other words, followers were viewed as being smart enough and creative enough to be entrusted to solve problems, pursue new ideas, and act in a way that was consistent with the vision of the leader. This was done without requiring followers to engage in burdensome reporting requirements, bureaucratic permission seeking, and mindless compliance checks. Though not universally embraced, there is also a sense in more contemporary perspectives that the models, styles, and traits that generate leadership efficacy are situational. This idea was first expressed by Tannenbaum and Schmidt (1958) in writing about management in the corporate world. They arrayed leadership approaches on a continuum from “boss centered” to “subordinate centered,” noting that a major challenge for (then) modern managers was deciding where to fall on the continuum in a given situation. In policing contexts, this suggests that “what works” for a leader is rarely universal, instead varying based on context, culture, position, objectives, the environment, the strengths and predispositions of a leader, and the preferences and characteristics of those the leader seeks to influence. An officer or leader who is ineffective in one agency or assignment might perform quite well in a different set of circumstances or vice versa. It has also been argued that leadership is not the same at all levels of an organization. The behaviors that make a leader an effective patrol sergeant might not yield the same outcomes for the leader when promoted to serve as a lieutenant overseeing the records division. Leaders need to be conscious of the fact that the approaches used in a given situation and/or to achieve a given end might not yield universal success. Leadership is a challenging process, but it can be the element that distinguishes organizations that are “great” from those that are merely “good.” In addition, leadership is a behavior, not a position within an organization. Leaders are people who demonstrate certain skills and habits, regardless of their formal rank or office. Police Leadership Styles Too often it is presumed that all supervisors are leaders and that only supervisors can lead. Increasingly there is awareness and celebration of the idea that every officer must be a leader, at least in some contexts. Informal leadership is very difficult to measure in any type of organization, but it can have a profound influence on personnel and operations (Schafer 2001). Though the influence of informal police leaders is generally evident in policing scholarship, research has not been able to empirically define when and how it matters. Theoretical perspectives and explanations regarding leadership extend far beyond the brief ideas reviewed in this passage. What is of relevance for this discussion are the ideas that leadership is situation but that modern perspectives tend to emphasize involving employees in the decision-making process. It is sometimes observed that leadership is something done with, not to, others. Further, it should be recognized that good leadership is actually quite difficult to achieve. Effective leaders continually seek ways to improve their performance as they confront new and different challenges (Schafer 2012). Leadership Styles Displayed in Policing Despite the presumed importance and influence of informal leaders in policing context, studies of police leadership have focused on studying formal supervisors. As a consequence, what is known about leadership styles and their influence (or lack thereof) is based on studies of those who have been awarded a rank. Such supervisors may or may not demonstrate actual leadership behaviors as they carry out their duties. Far less is known about leaders in police organizations, who may or may not hold an official rank in their agency (Van Maanen 1983). This section reviews literature seeking to describe the management and leaders styles police supervisors have displayed in prior studies. There is a distinction between what scholars found when they first began to study police supervisors and what is more often seen in contemporary agencies. Police Leadership Styles Early efforts to study the management styles of police supervisors did not paint a favorable picture of the level of actual leadership taking place in organizations. Kuykendall and Unsinger (1982) administered a leadership inventory to police managers. Their results suggested that most respondents used a variety of styles in the course of performing their supervisory duties. The most commonly reported management styles were selling, telling, and participation. There was little evidence that supervisors used actual leadership or other forms delegation as a component of their managerial style, though their data was collected in the late 1970s before these types of approaches had entered the discourse of police management. In other words, managers reported a preference to use styles that were oriented more toward “safe” methods emphasizing control and direction of personnel, rather than responses that might be considered more “risky” styles, such as delegating important tasks to subordinate personnel. Mayo (1985) contended supervisors tended not to trust the skills, loyalty, and judgment of personnel in their agencies. This resulted in the observed practice of police supervisors engaging in micromanagement. Girodo (1998) surveyed police executives from around the world and found most reported leaning toward what might be considered “Machiavellian” approaches. End objectives were achieved not through democratic and participative approaches but through the manipulation of subordinate personnel. This is reflective of the tendency for police agencies to seek to operate as paramilitary organizations that exert top-down control over personnel, communication, and decision making. These traditional styles of police supervision have been subject to extensive criticism because they do not encourage employees to be committed, productive, and creative members of the workforce. Allen (1982) found the type of supervision (i.e., the use of incentives) was likely more influential than the volume of supervision. Quality was more important than quantity (more contact), though his measures were quite limited. It should also be noted his research was conducted on 3659 P a 1970s group of front-line police personnel. The education, traits, experiences, and expectations of modern patrol officers are likely quite different than what was seen in earlier eras. Johnson (2006) studied supervisor influence on traffic and drunk driving enforcement in a collection of agencies in the Cincinnati metropolitan region. His results support that leadership matters, both in terms of the priorities of agency executives and also the priorities of patrol supervisors. Though leadership was deemed important, it was not the only factor influencing enforcement productivity. Organizational factors such as policies, supervision, and bureaucratic requirements do influence when and how officers enforce the law but so do situational factors, officer preferences, and environmental considerations. In other words, even when leadership matters, it is not the only force or factor influencing officers and the decisions they make. Engel (2001) developed four broad categorizations of supervisory styles that help frame an understanding of different leadership approaches in policing. “Traditional” leaders were highly task oriented and expected aggressive enforcement of the law from subordinates; they were focused on traditional policing outcomes and presumably would have leaned toward transactional relationships with followers (e.g., officers making a lot of arrests and issue a lot of citations would presumably be ranked higher by traditional leaders). “Innovative” leaders were situated further onto the transactional end of the leadership continuum; they shared power with subordinates, sought to have friendly and productive relationships with subordinates, and emphasized community relations. “Supportive” supervisors sought to be a buffer between frontline personnel and top agency leaders; they place less emphasis on accomplishing traditional policing tasks. Finally, “active” supervisors were themselves highly active in front-line policing matters; they had positive views of their subordinates, tended to exemplify the idea of “leading by example,” and did not see themselves as radically different than those they supervised. Active supervisors demonstrated the most influenced in the two agencies included in Engel’s study. P P 3660 Beginning in the 1980s, there has been a greater emphasis on democratic and participative approaches to police supervision and leadership (Wycoff and Skogan 1994), though limited advancements have been realized. The promise of such approaches is multifaceted. A leader who engages subordinates in making decisions can tap into the creativity, experience, and intelligence of employees. It is expected that participative approaches can make organizations more adaptable and responsive in the face of shifting and dynamic social environments. Leaders who use these types of approaches do not make all choices unilaterally. They engage subordinates to identify problems, determine priorities, and derive solutions. This does not suggest that all choices and actions are subject to full participation by all employees. Certainly there are aspects of police operations that require command-and-control authority and decision making, but such circumstances are the exception, not the rule. Though there is limited evidence assessing these types of practices, experiences to date suggest promising implications (Steinheider and Wuestewald 2008). Survey data from police officers finds personnel often express a preference for supportive and participatory leadership styles (Witte et al. 1990). Officers do not like directive and controlling management styles. Instead, they prefer to be led in a process that grants them a voice and input into organizational decisions. This does not suggest that officers do not understand and support the needs of leaders to have ultimate authority. Rather, it implies that, when possible, officers prefer to be able to participate in organizational decision making in an open and democratic manner. Tentative evidence suggests that many police executives and leaders are similarly open-minded in employing nontraditional systems (Steinheider and Wuestewald 2008; Tannenbaum and Schmidt 1958). It is less clear, however, whether those expressions of support translate into actual changes in supervisory style as perceived by employees. Consideration of supervisory styles in policing should not overlook the role of poor or ineffective leadership. Barbara Kellerman (2004) offered one of the best considerations of this topic in Police Leadership Styles leadership literature. She argued that too often, professional and scholarly discussions of leadership frame leader behavior as benevolent and positive behavior. She and others have argued consideration of leadership needs to acknowledge leaders sometimes use less-than-ideal methods. Some supervisors achieve their objectives while using poor leadership techniques. Some leaders are quite successful but pursue ignoble or evil objectives (Adolf Hitler is the common example of this outcome). People who are generally very good and effective leaders occasionally make mistakes. Leaders who have been successful sometimes “derail” (McCall and Lombardo 1983). Consideration of police leadership styles should not overlook how poor and ineffective approaches can hamper the ability of leaders to achieve their objectives. The Influence of Leadership It is generally accepted that police supervisors (who are formally in positions of leadership) can shape various organizational and individual outcomes produced by employees (Engel 2001). Supervisors are thought to have the ability to influence the tone of police operations, helping shape the style, tactics, and outcomes. In reality, it is far easier to believe that supervisors have such a strong and direct influence on officers and the organizations than it is to prove that belief is reality. This is partially a function of the limited amount of quality research studying supervisory and leadership influences in policing. It is also a reflection of the nature of the police organization itself. In many organizational contexts, supervisors have routine and direct contact with their subordinates. The task environment is also such that employees often have limited discretion, established accountability mechanisms, and routine reporting demands that serve to structure, regulate, and formalize the decisions they make. Police departments are often characterized as a quasi-military bureaucracies characterized by command-and-control relationships between supervisors and subordinates. This tends to Police Leadership Styles support the use of directive supervisory styles, which are predicated on the ability of a manager to closely monitor employee performance. In reality, officers are frequently separated from their supervisors by both time and space. The nature of police work also means that officers enjoy a wide degree of discretion in performing their duties, particularly the low seriousness events that typify much of police work (Brown 1988; Van Maanen 1983). Additionally, police operations and personnel are influenced by cultural and external forces that serve to condition where, when, how, and to what end police decisions are made. The result is that it has been suggested police agencies are “loosely coupled organizations” (Maguire and Katz 2002). Police managers do not have the time or capacity to effectively monitor the actions of officers on the street. The unpredictable, dynamic, and complex nature of police work also makes it quite difficult for agencies to craft effective policies to govern and guide how officers make decisions in the field. As a result, police personnel are not nearly as restricted by administrative impositions. On paper and in textbooks, agencies are orderly and control is clear; reality is quite different. This makes leadership (particularly transformational and democratic approaches) all the more important. Directive, controlling, manipulative, and micromanaging approaches actually function to push officers away from organizational objectives and discourage them from supporting the mission and vision of executives. Real leadership (as opposed to management) can help engage, empower, and motivate personnel to support and pursue organizational objectives. Because officers are often performing their duties with no direct supervision and little reliable evidence verifying when, where, and how they perform their duties, having engaged personnel is all the more important. Creating work environments that treat officers in accordance with McGregor’s (1960) Theory Y assumptions would, in the aggregate, be expected to produce better outcomes and results for the organization. As a result of these factors, it is reasonable to expect limitations on the ability of police leadership to influence police personnel. Many of these 3661 P challenges are far more acute in policing than in other occupational and organizational settings. Police personnel operate in environments with limited direct supervision, handle a diverse range of tasks, and make myriad high-discretion decisions (Allen 1982; Engel 2001; Van Maanen 1983, 1984). Though supervisors and organizations seek to impose policies, protocols, structures, and mandates to condition and direct discretionary behavior, officers enjoy a considerable degree of latitude in performing their duties. This totality of circumstances suggests that leaders will have a limited, but not nonexistent, ability to influence officers. Police supervisors and leaders are able to exert at least a limited degree of influence on personnel. Much of the research studying supervisory influence has focused on examining traditional policing outcomes, such as enforcement behavior, use of force, and officer misbehavior (Brown 1988; Huberts et al. 2007). Though such considerations are important, they reflect but a narrow range of the tasks to which officers attend and the expectations the public has of their police. Equally important, they tend to focus on the ends, rather than the means, of policing. A small number of studies have attempted to examine issues such as the nature of police encounters with the public and self-initiated efforts officer undertakes to address specific problems. Taken as a whole, researchers have achieved mixed assessments of whether supervisors can influence the behavior of subordinate personnel (cf, Allen 1982; Brown 1988; National Research Council 2004). It should be noted that many of these studies were limited in the types of influence they were studying and the methods that were used to measure specified outcomes. It has conventionally been assumed that bringing about change in police organizations is akin to “bending granite” (Rowe 2006). In recent years, increasing experience and empirical evidence have begun to suggest this may not always be the case. Jermier and Berkes (1979) studied officers in a Midwestern agency, finding that officers were supportive of leadership approaches that emphasized participation. Officers reported they were less inclined to respond to directive and P P 3662 controlling management approaches. Case studies of community policing have highlighted the role of leadership as a mechanism to facilitate rapid (and at times, radical) organizational transformation (Wycoff and Skogan 1994). Though critics have dismissed the roles of William Bratton and COMPSTAT as causal forces influencing New York City’s crime decline, there can be little doubt that his leadership style in NYPD (and elsewhere) has brought about rapid change in climate and culture. Thus, leadership can change police culture, though it is still difficult to determine how and why that outcome is achieved in some instances and not in others. Several studies based on data collected for the Project on Policing Neighborhoods (POPN) tend to offer some provisional evidence that supervisors can influence front-line personnel (Engel 2001). Importantly, these studies attempted to assess not just the general idea of supervisory influence. Instead, supervisors were categorized based on their general management style. Findings based on the POPN data offer a possible explanation for the mixed results achieved in prior studies by suggesting that variation in supervisory influence is partially a product of dissimilarity in supervisory styles. Not all supervisors use the same approaches in seeking to control, influence, and lead. The methods and styles used by supervisors vary based on the circumstances, timing, and audience, as well as the supervisor’s perceptions of various situational exigencies. Far less is known about the measurement of leadership efficacy beyond considerations of officer performance, output, and conduct. What other metrics might be used and who should provide input on the performance of a given leader? These efforts can be challenging, as they require the development of broader definitions and measures of leader efficacy, which tends to invoke a number of methodological difficulties. Huberts et al. (2007) studied Dutch police officers. They found leadership approaches did influence integrity violations by officers. In particular their results suggested that officers were influenced by strong role modeling by their leaders. When leaders took a strong stance against integrity Police Leadership Styles violations and were perceived to perform their duties with a high moral standard, officers were more inclined to emulate that approach. This is certainly a favorable representation of what might be achieved through leadership, at least based on some important outcomes of relevance to policing. As a result of this body of literature, several important observations and conclusions can be made about leadership and influence in police organizations. Supervisors can influence frontline personnel, at least in the production of some outcomes using some management styles. Poor leadership practices can also generate real and negative consequences in the workplace, including poor productivity, dissatisfaction, stress, attrition, and absenteeism, among other concerns (Kelloway et al. 2005). Though traditional police leadership approaches were primarily transactional (stick and carrot) approaches, transformational strategies seem more promising in their ability to favorably influence personnel and behavior. There is evidence that followers might prefer such participatory approaches and that leaders are open to their use. To date, however, research has not been able to conclusively contrast the outcomes of transactional and transformational leadership approaches in policing. Generational Effects There may be generational and experiential influences that shape the approaches used by supervisors. In the 1960s and 1970s, there was a renewed emphasis on college education for police personnel. Pursley (1974) compared police chiefs based on education, experience, and involvement in professional activities (belonging to national professional associations, publishing in professional periodicals); he analyzed their responses to a variety of leadership inventories. He found that educated chiefs had less experience (both as officers and chiefs, suggesting they were also likely to be younger), were more connected with professional groups and activities, and were more receptive to more transformational leadership approaches (though he did not use this term). Police Leadership Styles Younger leaders were more willing to support delegating authority within the workforce, allowing subordinates to participate in decision making, embracing more democratic approaches, and supporting less authoritarian and controlling leadership approaches. Thus, when considering how generations influence policing and police leadership, it is not just a matter of different mentalities across groups of different officers. Supervisors from different generations might also have different ideas about how to lead personnel. Cohen (1980) studied command personnel (captains and above) in the New York City Police Department based on data collected in 1972. He found two primary management styles. Tradition-oriented leaders generally had no education beyond high school. Reform-oriented leaders generally had attended or were attending college. Tradition-oriented leaders were focused on power and authority, while reform-oriented leaders were more participative and emphasized community relations and service. Cohen found that reform-oriented leaders had received lower ratings on internal performance assessments, but he attributed this to the probability that traditionoriented leaders were evaluating most reformoriented leaders. Thus, it is would not be surprising to see that the disjuncture in their orientations toward leadership and the broader role of the police might result in less positive performance evaluations. This holds important implications for understanding leadership. First, it reinforces that leadership is situational; at the very least “good” leadership is a time-bound concept. Cohen’s work was being done during a time of transition and reform in NYPD. Second, leadership practices and police personnel might both experience different generations. Several factors contribute to this situation. In general, different generations are distinct from one another based on variation in life experiences, culture, and broader society during their formative years. During eras of transition in policing (the movement out of the traditional model in the 1970s, the proliferation of community policing in the 1980s and 1900s, the emergence of various data-driven and evidence- 3663 P based policing practices in the 2000s), there is likely to be tension throughout all ranks of police agencies. Personnel who started their career one (or two) ideological generations earlier might be less inclined to adapt their beliefs, values, and practices. Making matters more complicated, the role of leadership in periods of reform and transition might be a function both of a leader’s generation and position within the organization. Top executives likely are driving forces behind implementing these reforms and innovations, so their support might be expected. In contrast, the drag or tension may be among mid-level supervisors. Sergeants, lieutenants, captains, and others who feel no ownership over the new idea have little reason to embrace new perspectives. They may resist the change or evenly actively obstruct its emergence because they view the change as a threat to both their perspective on leadership and their continued advancement in the organization. Andreescu and Vito (2010) found contemporary managers expressed strong support for ideals consistent with transformational leadership approaches. These included inclusive and human-oriented styles of leadership, the articulation of an organizational vision, caring for the well-being of employees, and setting an example for employees. Transformational approaches remain a challenge for police organizations. Though support for this style of leadership is apparent among police personnel and leaders (Witte et al. 1990), there is also a belief that such circumstances as participatory management are not actually found in most organizations. Stamper (1992) found a disjuncture between how executives perceived themselves and how members of their executive staff perceived them. Executives believed they lead their organization in one fashion. This self-perception tended to differ from how those around the executives perceived their leadership style and influence. Intuitively it makes sense that younger officers might be more likely to support transformational, participatory, and democratic approaches to leadership. These youth are more oriented toward social interaction, social involvement, and being allowed a voice in aspects of P P 3664 organizational operations. Scholars and professionals continue to speculate that there might be a generational preference for transformational leadership approaches, but there is still an absence of research evidence assessing this matter in policing contexts. As the labor force becomes increasingly filled with those from generations desiring more transformational leadership, it will be increasingly important that police leadership adapt to reflect that situation. If organizations are to maintain long-term viability, it will be essential to create work environments that attract and retain newer generations of officers. Conclusions Leadership remains a vital issue in modern police organizations. Its importance cannot be refuted, and the need for leadership (not simply strong management) is quite apparent within the profession. What remains more elusive is a clear understanding of when and how leadership matters as a force influencing the values, beliefs, attitudes, and behaviors of police personnel. Though there is a natural appeal toward transformational leadership styles, the potential benefits of these approaches remain presumed rather than proven in police organizations. Issues of leadership will most likely continue to become increasingly important in the future as police organizations need to be more adaptive in responding to everchanging criminal threats and community expectations. This will be compounded by work forces increasingly composed of officers from more recent generations, who may well require a very different style of leadership and a very different organizational environment. If police organizations are going to remain viable in confronting crime and disorder, real leadership will be of increasing importance. Both the research community and the profession itself must support the development of greater knowledge of the role leadership will play in these dynamic future environments. Police Leadership Styles Related Entries ▶ Managing Innovation of Policing ▶ Measuring Police Performance ▶ Methodological Issues in Evaluating Police Performance Recommended Reading and References Adlam R, Villiers P (eds) (2003) Police leadership in the twenty-first century: philosophy, doctrine and developments. Waterside Press, Winchester Allen DN (1982) Police supervision on the street: an analysis of supervisor/officer interaction during the shift. J Crim Justice 10:91–109 Andreescu V, Vito GF (2010) An exploratory study of ideal leadership behaviour: the opinions of American police managers. Int J Police Sci Manag 12:567–583 Brown MK (1988) Working the street: police discretion and the dilemmas of reform. Russell Sage, New York Burns JM (1978) Leadership. Harper & Row, New York Cohen B (1980) Leadership styles of commanders in the New York City police department. J Police Sci Adm 8:125–138 Engel RS (2001) Supervisory styles of patrol sergeants and lieutenants. J Crim Justice 29:341–355 Girodo M (1998) Machiavellian, bureaucratic, and transformational leadership styles in police managers: preliminary findings of interpersonal ethics. Percept Mot Skills 86:419–427 Huberts LWJC, Kaptein M, Lasthuizen K (2007) A study of the impact of three leadership styles on integrity violations committed by police officers. Policing Int J Police Strateg Manag 30:587–607 Jermier JM, Berkes LJ (1979) Leader behavior in a police command bureaucracy: a closer look at the quasimilitary model. Adm Sci Quart 24:1–23 Johnson RR (2006) Management influences on officer traffic enforcement productivity. Intl J Police Sci Mgt 8:205–217 Kellerman B (2004) Bad leadership: what it is, how it happens, why it matters. Harvard Business School Press, Boston Kelloway EK, Sivanathan N, Francis L, Barling J (2005) Poor leadership. In: Barling J, Kelloway EK, Frone MR (eds) Handbook of work stress. Sage, Thousand Oaks, pp 89–112 Kuykendall JL, Unsinger PC (1982) The leadership styles of police managers. J Crim Justice 10:311–321 Maguire ER, Katz DM (2002) Community policing, loose coupling, and sensemaking in American police agencies. Justice Quart 19:503–536 Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters Mayo L (1985) Leading blindly: an assessment of chief’s information about police operations. In: Geller W (ed) Police leadership in America. American Bar Foundation, Washington, DC McCall MW Jr, Lombardo MM (1983) Off the track: why and how successful executives get derailed. Center for Creative Leadership, Greensboro McGregor D (1960) The human side of enterprise. McGraw-Hill, New York National Research Council (2004) Fairness and effectiveness in policing: the evidence. Committee to review research on police policy and practices. In: Skogan W, Frydl K (eds) Committee on law and justice, division on behavioral and social sciences and education. The National Academies Press, Washington, DC Pursley RD (1974) Leadership and community identification attitudes among two categories of police chiefs: an exploratory inquiry. J Police Sci Adm 2:414–422 Rowe M (2006) Following the leader: front-line narratives on police leadership. Policing Int J Police Strateg Manag 29:757–767 Schafer JA (2001) Community policing: the challenges of successful organizational change. LFB Scholarly Publishing, New York Schafer JA (2012) Effective leadership in policing: successful traits and habits. Carolina Academic Press, Durham Stamper NH (1992) Removing managerial barriers to effective police leadership: a study of executive leadership and executive management in big-city police departments. Police Executive Research Forum, Washington, DC Steinheider B, Wuestewald T (2008) From the bottom-up: sharing leadership in a police agency. Police Pract Res 9:145–163 Tannenbaum R, Schmidt WH (1958) How to choose a leadership pattern. Harv Bus Rev 36:95–101 Van Maanen J (1983) The boss: the American police sergeant. In: Punch M (ed) Control in the police organization. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 275–317 Van Maanen J (1984) Making rank: becoming an American police sergeant. Urban Life 13:155–176 Witte JH, Travis LF, Langworthy RH (1990) Participatory management in law enforcement: police officer, supervisor and administrator perceptions. Am J Police 9(4):1–23 Wycoff MA, Skogan WG (1994) The effect of a community policing management style on officers’ attitudes. Crime Delinq 40:371–383 Police Legitimacy ▶ Organizational Change and Police Legitimacy 3665 P Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters John D. McCluskey1, Robert E. Worden2,3 and Sarah J. McLean3 1 Department of Criminal Justice, Rochester Institute of Technology, Rochester, NY, USA 2 School of Criminal Justice, University at Albany, State University of New York, Albany, NY, USA 3 John F. Finn Institute for Public Safety, Inc., Albany, NY, USA Overview Research on police legitimacy is an area of growing interest among researchers and practitioners. The concept of legitimacy ties together issues of compliance, obedience, satisfaction, trust, and order. The fundamental recognition of its importance rests on the idea that police will more easily maintain order when civilians view the police as legitimate. Regimes, organizations, and individual officers lacking legitimacy, conversely, face crises based on undermined public support for their authority. The discussion that follows considers how legitimacy is influenced by individual encounters with authorities and in a reciprocal sense, provides a context for understanding how citizens relate to police in terms of future cooperation and compliance. Fundamentals Definition of Legitimacy Legitimacy is an outlook, with cognitive and affective components as well as behavioral predispositions. People who believe that the police are legitimate trust the police to exercise their authority appropriately, identify with the police (Tyler and Huo 2002), have confidence in the police to do the right thing, and feel an obligation to obey the police. The sense of P P 3666 obligation to obey has been central to discussions of legitimacy, because insofar as legitimacy has behavioral implications, it points the way toward broader and more economical ways for the police to cultivate public support, cooperation, and compliance. More generally, we might say that when police are perceived as legitimate, they are thought to be entitled to have their authority reciprocated with obedience. From the observation that legitimacy encompasses a sense of obligation to obey, it does not follow that obedience ensues reliably from legitimacy; the association between legitimacy – an outlook – and obedience (a behavior) is imperfect. Many studies of attitude-behavior consistency have reported only rather modest associations, and against that empirical backdrop, the reported relationships between legitimacy and obedience appear quite robust, as we summarize below, but they are far from perfect, and we might surmise that the strength of the relationship depends in part on the nature of the behavior. Legitimacy, to the extent it is an attitude toward police, likely shares a high correlation with other attitudes, such as satisfaction with the police, which have been studied more extensively. Furthermore, a variety of research points to the likelihood that legitimacy is conceptually multidimensional, comprised of trust in motives, obligation to obey, and identification with the authority. This suggests that legitimacy is a composite of both affect toward authorities and their motives (e.g., trust and identification) and perhaps what might be considered an “action”-oriented component based on whether the authority’s directives should be followed (obligation to obey) or can form the basis for citizen authorization (empowerment). We would add that legitimacy is a property of different types of authority – of political systems; discrete political institutions, such as Congress or the Supreme Court; legal systems; specific legal institutions or agencies; and even private employers. We focus here on the legitimacy of the police, but we caution that inasmuch as the police exercise a mandate based, arguably, in law enforcement, police legitimacy is difficult to Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters separate from the legitimacy of the legal order in which police are embedded. The police are, thus, tied directly to the concept of legitimacy as they represent the legal order and simultaneously are reliant on deference to that order as a reservoir of public cooperation, obedience to their authority, and trust. The relationship between these concepts and legitimacy is explored below. Sources of Legitimacy Wilbur Miller’s (1977) comparative history of the New York City police and the London “bobbies” illustrates the tie between legal order and legitimacy. In England, for example, the police were viewed as impersonal representations of the established legal order, which was primarily divided along the lines of social class in the relatively homogeneous English society. As such the police had impersonal authority that stemmed from a general civilian deference to the larger political structure in 1800s England. Conversely, in New York, during the 1800s, there was no such easily agreed upon legal order, given the diversity of religious, ethnic, and social classes occupying the city. Thus, in this environment, police authority was believed to emanate from personal authority that was essentially earned respect and deference from the community which accumulated over the course of face-to-face encounters. Legitimacy of one’s role and action that ties directly to the law would appear to be advantageous to police as the bobbies enjoyed a reluctant respect even among the lower classes with whom they had a more adversarial relationship. However, this simplification glosses over several differences between the US police system and those of much of the remainder of the world. First, centralized authority in England allowed for uniform lawmaking and centralized police forces. The USA, conversely, has a proliferation of thousands of agencies, each which has to build its own reservoir of authority from a local (or State) body of law. Thus, fragmentation and decentralization push legal legitimacy to local levels in the US political system. While one might argue this is a weakness and causes police to diverge from a strictly legal mandate, there is Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters some evidence that police function in such an environment, in the long term, may offer some advantages. First, no local police agency in the USA represents the legitimacy of law in the United States. Hence, we should distinguish the legitimacy of the legal system, in the more abstract sense, from the legitimacy of police or of individual police agencies in a more concrete sense; the latter is much more proximate to the day-to-day work of police officers. The fragmented and decentralized nature of US policing, instead, gives police a local legitimacy and authority. By contrast, in the Fall 2005, French police chased several Muslim youths, and two were accidentally electrocuted. This situation boiled into many days of widespread riots against French police, since, in the more centralized governmental system, the police represent all of French government in some respects. As one can observe, the source of legitimacy in a political system has trade-offs and costs, some of which are not readily apparent in the day-to-day function of police. Clearly, in the USA, with a proliferation of local police departments, legitimacy is homegrown by departments and the men and women who serve within those organizations. To paraphrase Tip O’Neill’s keen observation, “Much policing is local.” Thus, important questions to ask are as follows: Where does legitimacy come from, and what are the consequences of legitimacy? As such one might consider legitimacy to be both a dependent variable (something caused by other forces, such as respect for political institutions and the behavior of those institutions) and an independent variable (one that predicts changes in some outcomes, such as citizens’ cooperation with authorities). Where Does Legitimacy Come from? The encounter between police and the public has been studied as a petri dish for the creation of legitimacy among the public. Observations of police-citizen contacts as well as post-contact surveys of citizens have formed the basis for a substantial body of literature pointing to the antecedents of legitimacy. These antecedents 3667 P emanate from the treatment that citizens receive or perceive receiving in those encounters they have with authorities, such as police. The term procedural justice is used to describe treatment that is fair, respectful, and generally thought to lead to a sense that the processing one receives is appropriate and that the authority behind it is legitimate. Satisfaction or the extent to which citizens are content with the encounter is also correlated with legitimacy. These linkages are explored below. Tom Tyler (2003, 2004) and other researchers have done extensive research to outline the relationship between processing, procedural justice, and legitimacy. Procedural justice has been conceived as encompassing two broad elements: quality of treatment and quality of decisionmaking. Quality of treatment encompasses the tenor of interaction between citizens and authorities and includes elements such as voice, or the notion that people believe that they should be given an opportunity to tell their side of a story, explain their situation, and communicate their views, and quality of interpersonal treatment, the notion that people believe that they should be treated with dignity and respect. Quality of decision-making comprises a set of signals that pass from authorities to citizens about how decisions are being made in any particular instance and whether they appear to be fair. Indicia of quality decision-making include how authorities demonstrate trustworthy motives. For example, people believe that authorities should care about their well-being and consider their needs and concerns, and they draw inferences about that when authorities explain their decisions and justify and account for their actions. Similarly, neutrality is a marker for quality of decision-making, since people believe that decisions should be made evenhandedly and with proper consideration of objective facts. While it may be helpful for heuristic purposes to describe these elements of procedural justice as distinct constructs, they are conceptually and empirically intertwined with one another. Empirically, these features of police-citizen encounters tend to be strongly or at least P P 3668 moderately correlated, yielding only one (Reisig et al. 2007; Gau 2011) or two (Tyler 1990) factors in factor analysis. These patterns of association are open to (at least) two interpretations: It might be that authorities’ behaviors are correlated (e.g., officers who are polite also tend to listen to citizens and explain themselves) and that citizens’ perceptions are correlated (citizens who judge officers’ actions as respectful also tend to perceive them as attentive), or some combination of both sets of forces. Survey research has repeatedly shown that the procedural justice that people subjectively experience in their encounters with the police is directly related to their satisfaction with the encounters and, moreover, to the legitimacy that they attribute to the police. People are more satisfied with their encounters with the police when they perceive that police acted in a procedurally just fashion. Furthermore, people have greater trust in the police, and feel a greater obligation to obey police instructions, when they have experienced procedurally just encounters with the police. This is the sense in which legitimacy can be “created” by police in their day-to-day interactions with the public and also illustrates its close tie to citizen satisfaction. Satisfaction and legitimacy can also be eroded by police, if they act with procedural injustice, if they are impolite or disrespectful, and if they interrupt citizens, ignore what citizens have to say, or do not permit citizens to explain themselves. The core linkage posited is that elements of processing which leave citizens unsatisfied (e.g., disrespect, bias) undermine legitimacy, while those which amplify satisfaction (e.g., respectful treatment, explaining decisions) similarly enhance legitimacy. For example, in one of the earliest studies, Tyler and Folger (1980) surveyed a random sample of Evanston (Illinois) residents in 1979, identifying among the respondents those who reportedly had a personal experience with Evanston police in the previous 5 years, by either calling for assistance or being stopped by police. About each type of contact, they asked respondents to indicate the outcome (police had or had not taken care of the problem, and police issued or did not issue a citation, respectively), whether Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters police treated them fairly, and how satisfied they were with the contact. They found that both outcome and perceived fairness affects citizens’ satisfaction in both types of contacts, and also that perceived fairness affects citizens’ more general evaluations of the police. Similarly, Tyler (1988) surveyed a sample of Chicago residents, nearly half of whom reportedly had a direct experience with Chicago police and/or courts in the preceding year. He found that procedural fairness affects citizens’ satisfaction with both their outcomes and their treatment in the particular case, and also that procedural fairness affects citizens’ more general evaluations of and support for the authorities. Moreover, this research makes it clear that citizens’ subjective experience is not determined entirely or even primarily by the outcomes that they receive. Put differently, neither substantive justice (whether one deserves what one objectively receives) nor distributive justice (whether one receives what others who are similarly situated receive) is as important to attitude formation as procedural justice (the manner in which justice is delivered). Even citizens whose outcomes are unambiguously unfavorable – who, for example, are cited for a traffic violation – may be satisfied with their experience if police are procedurally fair. It is people’s normative expectations about how authority should be exercised, more than their instrumental considerations about the favorability of outcomes, that drive their assessments of their own experiences. Since much of the research on this topic is based on cross-sectional survey data, the analysis of which forms the basis for only rather tentative inferences about cause and effect relationships; caution in drawing conclusions is advised. Several studies suggest that citizens’ prior attitudes toward police shape both their subjective experiences, including perceptions of procedural justice, and their more general attitudes toward the police, including legitimacy, thereby contributing to a partially or wholly spurious relationship between procedural justice and legitimacy. But when these relationships have been examined in panel surveys (e.g., Tyler 1990; Tyler and Fagan 2008), so that the temporal Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters ordering of the variables can be properly specified, the results have shown that even while prior attitudes do influence judgments about procedural justice and legitimacy, procedural justice has independent effects on subsequent legitimacy. The structure and context of police-citizen encounters vary considerably, with respect to visibility, the nature of the issue that prompted police involvement, the “situational status” of the citizen (as complainant, suspected offender, witness), and the neighborhood setting of the encounter. The structure and context of interaction between police and citizens likely contribute both to objective features of the encounter (the routines of interaction or typical procedure) and how the interaction is experienced by the citizen. One structural feature that has an important bearing on citizens’ subjective experience is how the encounter is initiated – at the request of a citizen or on the authority of the officer. Citizen requests may serve, at least to a degree, to legitimate the involvement of the police, as the officer(s) is responding to a request for police assistance. For at least one of the citizens who participate in such an encounter, the encounter is voluntary. When police intervene on their own initiative, however, as they do when they stop traffic violators or other people who arouse police suspicion, citizens’ participation is not voluntary but obligatory, and citizens may be more apt to question the propriety of police involvement (Reiss 1971). Such “obligation encounters” (Moore 2002) pose greater challenges for police in meeting citizens’ expectations for procedural justice. Skogan (2006) found among Chicago residents a significant disparity in satisfaction between those whose contacts with the police were self-initiated (78 % satisfied) and those whose contacts were initiated by police (58 % satisfied). Furthermore, procedural justice criteria appear to have an even greater bearing on citizens’ satisfaction in police-initiated contacts than they do in citizen-initiated contacts. Tyler and Folger (1980) found that procedural fairness has a larger effect when citizens are stopped than when citizens call for assistance. Wells (2007) surveyed citizens involved in any of three types 3669 P of contacts with the Lincoln (NE) police: victims of crimes, drivers involved in vehicle crashes, and drivers who received citations. He found that in each type of situation, citizens’ judgments about procedural justice affect their ratings of overall police performance in the encounter, though procedural justice mattered less for crime victims, who typically call for assistance, than for motorists who are stopped for traffic violations. We would also note that the effects of satisfactory experiences many not be as powerful as the effects of unsatisfactory experiences. Skogan (2006) stresses the asymmetry in the effects of positive and negative experiences with the police, finding in survey data on Chicagoans that their confidence in the police is very weakly or not at all related to positively evaluated contacts, but negatively evaluated contacts have a substantial detrimental effect on confidence. Skogan (2005) also found that citizens’ satisfaction with their contacts is shaped by procedural justice. More specifically, whether police were polite and whether they were helpful were the most important predictors of satisfaction with citizeninitiated encounters, and whether police were polite and whether they were perceived as fair were the most important predictors of satisfaction in police-initiated encounters. Satisfaction was also enhanced if police explained what action they would take. These beneficial effects of procedural justice did not, however, translate “up” to confidence in the police. Other studies have also found asymmetrical effects, though not to the degree that satisfactory contact had no effect on more general attitudes (e.g., Reisig and Parks 2000). No treatment of police legitimacy would be complete without acknowledging the attitudinal disparities across race and ethnicity: AfricanAmericans hold less favorable views of the police than whites do, with Latinos typically in between. For example, Weitzer and Tuch (2006) conducted a national survey and found variations in satisfaction with police across race and ethnicity, as 86 % of White, 80 % of Hispanic, and 73 % of Black respondents reported being satisfied or very satisfied with the police P P 3670 department in their city. More interestingly, perhaps, they also found that the effect of race on satisfaction was mediated by what citizens perceived as police actions. For instance, those believing police were involved in misconduct, such as improper stops, verbal abuse, excessive force, or corruption, were less satisfied with police. Further, they found that beliefs about misconduct were shaped not only direct, personal experiences but also by vicarious experiences (those communicated to individuals by others). Thus, the police-citizen encounter can have farreaching effects that ripple through a community. The overriding racial issue in policing for the past 15 years has been racial profiling, with countless police departments across the US collecting and analyzing data on the race of the people stopped by their officers in order to address concerns about racial bias. The analyses are seldom conclusive with respect to bias, but some research suggests that procedural justice plays an important role in shaping citizens’ perceptions of bias. For example, Tyler and Wakslak (2004) surveyed residents of Oakland and Los Angeles who had been stopped by police. Those who thought that police were polite, treated them with dignity and respect, and showed concern for their rights were much less likely to believe that they had been profiled. Other elements of procedural justice had similar, albeit more modest effects on profiling attributions. More recently, Gau and Brunson (2010) interviewed 45 youths from low-income areas of St. Louis, MO, and reported findings consistent with the theme that perceptions of unfair treatment undermined youths’ support for the police. Thus, legitimacy appears to be causally linked back to the basic concept outlined above: those situations where there is an obligation to obey the authority, which can be boiled down to several simple aspects of police encounters. Were the police invited to intervene (as compared to proactively inserting themselves into a situation)? Did the police clearly explain the rationale behind their decisions? Did police allow the individual to tell his or her side of the story? Did the police listen to the individual? Did the Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters police act courteously and show respect to the individual? These types of questions, when answered affirmatively, illustrate the procedural justice of police encounters; they also represent important antecedents of legitimacy, and, not surprisingly, they are closely correlated with citizen satisfaction. Legitimacy is intrinsically important, but it is important also because it is consequential. Legitimacy affects citizens’ acceptance of police decisions, their cooperation with the police, and even their compliance with the law more generally. We turn now to a consideration of these outcomes. Legitimacy and Outcomes: Support and Citizen Self-Regulation Police rely heavily upon citizens for support and self-regulation. Supporting citizen behavior and attitudes is important to the police for the maintenance of order and the control of crime. Police effectiveness depends upon citizen involvement in community activities, reporting crimes and giving information to the police, which would be considered as cooperation. Empowerment of the police is also a form of (active or passive) support, in the sense that citizens who grant police the capacity to exercise authority with fewer rather than more restrictions, and are supportive of (or do not oppose) police tactics and strategies, offer important if implicit consent from the governed to the authorities. Self-regulation, that is, obeying laws and complying with police requests, represents another area in which police rely on citizens. Thus, if police request citizens to leave a scene or to discontinue making noise at a party, they are relying on citizen self-regulation (Mastrofski et al. 1996). In the larger sense, police rely on everyday self-regulation or self-control in refraining from committing minor (e.g., littering) and major (e.g., robbery) crimes. One might think that citizens comply and cooperate due to the overall legitimacy of the legal system in which police-citizen contacts are embedded. This, for example, might help us Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters understand why an English citizen would obey a bobby but someone in New York would be reluctant to obey a police officer in the 1880s. Thus, in that larger sense, legal legitimacy can predict cooperation in face-to-face encounters. Analogously, one might look across US agencies and examine the relationship between the police and the community as an indicator of overall police legitimacy. Thus, in locales where policecommunity ties are strong, one might expect greater cooperation and compliance from citizens in encounters with police. Legitimacy and Support It is a well-understood fact that police rely on the public for information and mobilization to identify and solve problems. Police rely on citizens to report crimes and to act as witnesses and information providers on scene. One question that arises is whether there is a link between legitimacy and the willingness to cooperate with the police. If so, then police that engage in promoting legitimacy will build public support and cooperation. Evidence linking legitimacy and cooperation has slowly accumulated from the body of research on procedural justice. Tyler and Fagan (2008) used a panel data survey design with 830 respondents to test the relationship between legitimacy and cooperation. This allowed them to measure legitimacy at two points in time and determine how contact with police influenced subsequent legitimacy and self-reports of intention to cooperate with the police. Consistent with other research, procedurally just treatment yielded increases in perceived legitimacy of the police. More specifically, those respondents reporting they had been treated fairly and with respect had measureable increases in legitimacy, controlling for whether they received a positive or negative outcome from the police. To measure cooperation, the researchers asked citizens how likely they were to call the police and report a crime, help find a criminal, and report suspicious activity. A parallel scale regarding helping the community fight crime was constructed from similar measures asking whether the respondent was likely to volunteer 3671 P time to help the police, to patrol streets with others, and to attend community meetings about crime. In multivariate analyses, taking advantage of the panel design capacity for causal analysis, Tyler and Fagan (2008) found that those who reported police as being more legitimate were more likely to report intending to cooperate directly with the police and also cooperate with others in efforts to deal with community crime. Sunshine and Tyler (2003) have examined the relationship between empowerment and legitimacy among a panel of New York City respondents. Empowerment represents the extent to which citizens recognize a greater scope for police action and discretion. The findings from that research indicated that citizen perceptions of legitimacy and to a lesser extent distributive fairness predicted respondents’ extent of empowerment. Legitimacy and Self-regulation Research on self-regulation has focused on whether citizens obey the commands of police immediately as well as in the longer term with respect to both minor offending (e.g., traffic or other violations) and serious crime (e.g., violence). The research on immediate compliance has been derived from observations of what police do in interactions with citizens and whether citizens comply with police requests for self-control. For example, McCluskey (2003) studied face-to-face interactions between police and 939 suspects in St. Petersburg, FL, and Indianapolis, IN. The results of that research indicated that, with regard to immediate compliance, it appears that citizens who are given opportunities to tell their side of the story and are treated respectfully are significantly more compliant than citizens not afforded such courtesies during the police-citizen encounter. This type of treatment and behavioral outcome lends support to the linkage between treatment by authorities, legitimacy, and compliance. Sunshine and Tyler (2003) collected survey data regarding the link between citizens’ reports of compliance and the legitimacy of police. That research indicated a similar effect of perceptions of legitimacy, which provided a robust P P 3672 explanation of citizens’ self-reported compliance with the law. Thus, observed and self-reported behaviors, among the general public, are influenced by legitimacy. More simply, as legitimacy increases either as measured by perception of citizens, or by the fair procedures consistent with legitimacy, compliance increases. It is important to note that the observed police-citizen contacts and self-reports involve typically more trivial disputes or lawbreaking. Thus, one is obliged to ask: Does the perceived legitimacy of the police and law influence serious misbehaviors in a similar fashion? With regard to legitimacy’s relationship to longer-term patterns of compliance among serious offenders, several studies involving arrestees for spousal assault, intoxicated drivers, and serious delinquents indicate substantial links. Paternoster and his colleagues (1997) were the first to study the influence of procedural justice on serious criminal activity. Using data collected for the Milwaukee Domestic Violence Experiment, they found among a sample of males arrested for spouse assault that perceptions of procedural justice influenced recidivism. All of these offenders experienced an unfavorable outcome (arrest), but some of them perceived their treatment as procedurally fair, and those who did were significantly less likely to recidivate. Moreover, the recidivism rate for those who were arrested and who felt that the process was fair was similar to the recidivism rate for those who had been warned only. These findings suggest that legitimacy impacts longterm legal compliance to the extent that perceived fair treatment reported by these offenders is related to their sense of fair and legitimate treatment. Based on a sample of offenders arrested for drunk driving in Australia, Tyler and his colleagues (2007b) evaluated the impact of reintegrative shaming and procedural justice on recidivism. Recidivism was based on self-reports in a 2-year follow-up period and on police records for a 4-year follow-up period. The study tested the hypotheses that procedural justice and restorative justice conferences (as opposed to traditional court proceedings) would foster more positive assessments of the law and lead to higher Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters levels of law abidingness. First, they found that the treatment (restorative justice conference) was not associated with lower recidivism (measured in terms of self-reported drunk driving or police records), though they did detect a direct effect on self-reported efforts to curb driving while drunk. With respect to the influence of legitimacy on behavior, they found that those who viewed the police as more legitimate were less likely to recidivate. This held true when behavior was measured in terms of self-reported levels of drunk driving and when it was measured using police records. The extent to which the initial experience was viewed as procedurally just shaped subsequent views of legitimacy, which in turn led to lower levels of recidivism. Bouffard and Piquero (2010) analyzed the Philadelphia Birth Cohort data follow-up for 212 juveniles with police contacts. Those characterizing their initial contact as unfair had substantially higher frequency and longer periods of offending compared to those who did not. Fagan and Piquero (2007) examined a sample of 1,355 juveniles referred to courts in Philadelphia and Phoenix and found that assessments of procedural justice had a strong direct impact on perceptions of legitimacy among these serious offenders. In turn, legitimacy exercised a substantial direct impact on self-reported aggressive and income offending. In sum, across multiple methodologies, lawabiding and lawbreaking samples, and less serious and serious behavioral outcomes, it appears that where police legitimacy and behaviors consistent with procedurally fair policing are greatest, citizen self-regulation, both immediately and in the longer term, is greater. More specifically, citizen self-regulation is positively associated with police legitimacy. The Policy Consequences of Legitimacy and Future Research As the notion of procedural justice (Tyler 1990) and legitimacy came to the forefront of academic consideration, it was recognized that at least some of what police might accomplish required thinking about the issue of legitimacy and how citizens come to see authorities as legitimate. Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters This sparked research on procedural justice and has led to the recognition that legitimacy is to a significant degree in the hands of police as they relate to the public in everyday encounters. Clearly police misbehavior, corruption, and rudeness can do much damage to legitimacy. But the more optimistic side of the research indicates that police can repair and create legitimacy via politeness, taking time to explain their decisions and treating individuals in a fair manner. This is a very economical solution to the policecommunity relation issue which has at times seemed intractable and dominated by us vs. them rhetoric. Field stops by police have attracted considerable attention and generated considerable controversy, especially in New York City, where police have in recent years documented hundreds of thousands of “stop, question, and frisk” contacts annually. Proponents tout the value of such stops in confiscating illegal firearms and, more generally, reducing crime. Critics hold that the stops exhibit a racially biased pattern and, moreover, detract from the legitimacy of the police, as stops for low-level offenses may be viewed by the citizens who are stopped – and by their family, neighbors, and friends – as harassment (Gau and Brunson 2010; Warren 2011). Extant research does not suffice to resolve this controversy, even if it could be resolved with reference to empirical evidence, but we would note that several questions are important to consider in this connection: (1) How often are stops made? (2) For what reasons are stops made? (3) Are stops concentrated in places and at times at which crime occurs? (4) Are the stops conducted by officers in conformance with principles of procedural justice? Some have called for a “procedural justice model” of policing (Schulhofer et al. 2011; Meares 2009). A procedural justice model of policing does not hold that police platoons become grin-andwave squads. The coercive authority of police is, as Bittner (1970) observed long ago, their unique occupational prerogative, and it enables them to fulfill their role in society: negotiating or imposing solutions upon emergent problems. Procedural justice is not about whether but how authority is 3673 P exercised. Police who operate according to a procedural justice model will of course need to exercise their authority, but they do so sparingly, judiciously, and in accordance with principles of procedural justice: They honor legal limits on their authority; they treat the people with whom they interact – even the people whom they arrest – with dignity and respect; they allow – even invite – people to explain themselves and their situations; and they explain their actions. Police departments that adopt such a model would, we suppose, establish and enforce expectations that their officers will exercise their authority in these ways. Their chief executives make procedural justice an explicit priority. They embody their expectations in department policies and procedures. For example, the Redlands (CA) police revised their traffic stop procedures, as their chief explains, “instead of starting out the interaction between the motorist and the police officer, where we typically walk up and say, ‘Let me see your license and registration, please,’ then we walk back to our car, and the next time you see us is when we’re handing you a ticket or whatever. Turning that around and saying, ‘Good afternoon, my name is Officer Bueermann, and I’ve stopped you because you were speeding. Is there some reason you might have been speeding?’ And then we give you the opportunity to explain to us what was going on in your head, or why you were doing . . .” (quoted in Tyler 2011). They train their officers in proper policecitizen interaction (see, e.g., Rosenbaum and Lawrence 2012). They monitor the available indicators of police performance, such as complaints and uses of force, and recognizing the limits of these indicators, they make supervisors responsible for spot-checking the quality of police-citizen encounters. They might even develop more systematic measures of such performance. And they treat officers with the same procedural justice that they demand of officers in their encounters with citizens, thereby nurturing the legitimacy of the organization and its rules in the eyes of its human resources (Tyler et al. 2007; Wolfe and Piquero 2011). Beyond these basic suppositions, however, extant research does not provide much guidance P P 3674 for police administrators who are persuaded that their agencies would benefit from systematic efforts to engage in procedurally just policing. Hardly any empirical evidence is available for these purposes. One study showed that police disrespect toward citizens – a form of procedural injustice – is most likely a response to citizen disrespect toward the police, but it is also affected by a citizen’s lack of self-control (e.g., in the form of intoxication) and social status (Mastrofski et al. 2002). The same study also detected some differences across jurisdictions that might be attributable to differences in department administration. But at this time the translation of research on procedural justice and police legitimacy into the practice of procedurally just policing is largely a matter of trial and error. As research on legitimacy and procedural justice yields more insights regarding the specific content of just and fair processing and its consequences, it becomes imperative to begin developing key elements into the content of everyday police-citizen contacts. Answering questions such as what dosage level and content of procedurally just processing are related to the formation of a “sense of legitimacy” will help to tune police action to desired outcomes. If the current research trajectory on legitimacy matures into an action research agenda, then perhaps the police will find they have always had the tools for building legitimacy, cooperation, and compliance at their disposal. This would have an interesting symmetry with the idea of personal authority and the difference between cops and bobbies outlined at the beginning of this entry. More simply, the creation of legitimate police authority, in a decentralized republic, does in fact lie in the day-to-day contact between police officers and citizens. Thus, legitimacy is indeed local and continuously recreated or undermined in those everyday encounters. Related Entries ▶ Causes of Police Legitimacy ▶ Organizational Change and Police Legitimacy ▶ Police Self-legitimacy Police Legitimacy and Police Encounters ▶ Police-Led Interventions to Enhance Police Legitimacy ▶ Procedural Justice and Cooperation ▶ Procedural Justice, Legitimacy, and Policing Recommended Reading and References Bittner E (1970) The functions of the police in modern society. Oelgeschlager, Cambridge, MA Bouffard LA, Piquero NL (2010) Defiance theory and life course explanations of persistent offending. Crime Delinq 56(2):227–252 Fagan J, Piquero A (2007) Rational choice and developmental influences on recidivism among adolescent felony offenders. J Emp Legal Stud 4(4):715–748 Gau JM (2011) The convergent and discriminant validity of procedural justice and police legitimacy: an empirical test of core theoretical propositions. J Crim Justice 39(6):489–498 Gau JM, Brunson RK (2010) Procedural justice and order maintenance policing: a study of inner city young men’s perceptions of police legitimacy. Justice Q 27(2):255–279 Mastrofski S, Snipes J, Supina A (1996) Compliance on demand: the public’s response to specific police requests. J Res Crime Delinq 33:269–305 Mastrofski SD, Reisig M, McCluskey JD (2002) Police disrespect toward the public: an encounter-based analysis. Criminology 40:519–552 McCluskey J (2003) Police requests for compliance. LFB Scholarly Press, New York Meares T (2009) Barrock lecture on criminal law; the legitimacy of the police among young African American men. Marquette Law Rev 92:651–666 Miller W (1977) Cops and Bobbies. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Moore MH (2002) Recognizing value in policing: the challenge of measuring police performance. Police Executive Research Forum, Washington, DC Paternoster R, Brame R, Bachman R, Sherman L (1997) Do fair procedures matter? Law Soc Rev 31:163–204 Reisig MD, Parks RB (2000) Experience, quality of life, and neighborhood context: a hierarchical analysis of satisfaction with police. Justice Q 17(3): 607–630 Reisig MD, Bratton J, Gertz MG (2007) The construct validity and refinement of process-based policing measures. Crim Justice Behav 34:1005–1028 Reiss AJ Jr (1971) The police and the public. Yale University Press, Connecticut Rosenbaum DP, Lawrence DS (2012) Teaching respectful police-citizen encounters and good decision making: results of a randomized control trial with police recruits. Center for Research in Law and Justice, University of Illinois at Chicago, Chicago. www.nationalpoliceresearch.org Police Line-Level and Agency Accountability Schulhofer SJ, Tyler TR, Huq A (2011) American policing at a crossroads: unsustainable policies and the procedural justice alternative. J Crim Law Criminol 101:335–374 Skogan WG (2005) Citizen satisfaction with police encounters. Police Q 8(3):298–321 Skogan WG (2006) Asymmetry in the impact of encounters with police. Police Soc 6:99–126 Skogan W, Frydl K (eds) (2004) Fairness and effectiveness in policing: the evidence. The National Academies Press, Washington, DC Sunshine J, Tyler T (2003) The role of procedural justice and legitimacy in shaping public support for policing. Law Soc Rev 37:513–548 Tyler TR (1988) What is procedural justice? Criteria used by citizens to assess the fairness of legal procedures. Law Soc Rev 22:103–135 Tyler TR (1990) Why people obey the law. Yale University Press, New Haven Tyler TR (2003) Procedural justice, legitimacy, and the effective rule of law. In: Tonry M (ed) Crime Justice 30:431–505 Tyler TR (2004) Enhancing police legitimacy. In: Skogan WG (ed) Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 593:84–99 Tyler T (2011) Race, police legitimacy and cooperation with the police. National Institute of Justice, research for the real world
© Copyright 2024