Discrete Structures: Sample Questions, Exam 1 SOLUTIONS (This is longer than the actual test.) 1. Prove by mathematical induction that n3 −n is a multiple of 3 for every positive integer n. Solution: The basis step is n = 1. That is, that 13 − 1 = 0 should be a multiple of 3, which it is. For the inductive step let P (n) be the statement that n3 −n is a multiple of 3. In other words, there is an integer k so that n3 − n = 3k. To show the inductive step P (n) → P (n + 1), consider the inductive conclusion P (n + 1), which is that (n + 1)3 − (n + 1) is a multiple of 3. So compute (n + 1)3 − (n + 1) = = = = = = = (n + 1)[(n + 1)2 − 1] (n + 1)(n2 + 2n + 1 − 1) (n + 1)(n2 + 2n) n3 + 3n2 + 2n (n3 − n) + (3n2 + 3n) 3k + 3(n2 + n) by the inductive hypothesis 3(k + n2 + n), which is a multiple of 3. Thus we have shown the inductive step P (n) → P (n + 1). So by induction, n3 − n is always a multiple of 3 for each n ≥ 1. 2. Show that any postage of 8 cents or more can be achieved by using only 3-cent and 5-cent stamps. Solution: We proceed by induction. There are 3 basis steps. This corresponds to the fact that the smaller stamp is for 3 cents. Basis case n = 8: 8 = 5 + 3 one 5-cent stamp plus one 3-cent stamp. Basis case n = 9: 9 = 3 + 3 + 3 three 3-cent stamps. Basis case n = 10: 10 = 5 + 5 two 5-cent stamps. Inductive case. We will add 3-cent stamps to prove the result. If we can make n cents out of 3- and 5-cent stamps, then we can add another 3-cent stamp to the total to make n + 3 cents. This shows P (n) → P (n + 3). It remains to note that we can reach any integer n ≥ 8 by starting at one of the 3 base cases and adding nonnegative multiple of 3. Starting at 8, we get 8, 11, 14, 17, 20, . . .; starting at 9, we get 9, 12, 15, 18, 21, . . .; starting at 10, we get 10, 13, 16, 19, 22, . . .. This covers all the integers ≥ 8. (It’s possible to make a more rigorous argument by considering n mod 3 for n ≥ 8.) 3. (a) For x a real number, write down the definition of the absolute value |x| by cases. Solution: x for x > 0 0 for x = 0 |x| = −x for x < 0 (b) Prove by cases: If x, y ∈ R and y 6= 0, then x |x| = y |y| . Solution: We have 6 cases: Case 1: x > 0 and y > 0. Then x y x x = , y y |x| x = . |y| y Case 2: x > 0 and y < 0. Then x = −x, y y x y < 0 and |x| x x = =− . |y| (−y) y Case 3: x = 0 and y > 0. Then x = 0, y > 0 and x y = 0 and |x| 0 = = 0. |y| y Case 4: x = 0 and y < 0. Then x = 0, y x y < 0 and |x| (−x) x = =− . |y| y y Case 6: x < 0 and y < 0. Then x x = , y y = 0 and 0 |x| = = 0. |y| (−y) Case 5: x < 0 and y > 0. Then x = −x, y y x y x y > 0 and |x| (−x) x = = . |y| (−y) y 4. Write out the truth table for (p ∨ q) → (p ∧ q). Solution: p T T F F q p ∨ q p ∧ g (p ∨ q) → (p ∧ q) T T T T F T F F T T F F F F F T 5. Consider the function f (x) = 5x3 + 4, where f : R → R. Find the inverse function. Solution: If y = 5x3 + 4, solve for x y = 5x3 + 4, y − 4 = 5x3 , 1 (y − 4) = x3 , 5 q 3 1 (y 5 − 4) = x. 6. Let an be the sequence recursively defined by a1 = 2, a2 = 3, an = an−1 an−2 for n ≥ 3. Compute the first five terms a1 , . . . , a5 . Solution: a1 = 2, a2 = 3, a3 = a1 a2 = 6, a4 = a3 a2 = 18, a5 = a4 a3 = 144. 7. Let P (x) be the statement x is a student, and Q(x) be the statement x buys the meal plan. Consider the statement “Every student buys the meal plan.” (a) Write the statement symbolically. Solution: ∀x(P (x) → Q(x)). (b) Write the negation of the previous proposition symbolically, and also in words. Solution: The negation is ¬∀x(P (x) → Q(x)) ≡ ∃x¬(P (x) → Q(x)) ≡ ∃x(P (x) ∧ ¬Q(x)). In words, this say that there is a student who does not buy the meal plan. 8. True/False. Circle T or F. No explanation needed. (a) T F (b) T F (c) T F (d) T F (e) T F (f) T F (g) T F (h) T F (i) T F (j) T F (k) T F If p is true and q is false then determine p → q. Solution: F. If p is false, and the truth values of q, r are unknown, then determine (p ∧ q) → r. Solution: T, since if p is false, then p ∧ q is false no matter what q is. Similarly, if p ∧ q is false, the implication (p ∧ q) → r is true no matter what the value of r is. (p → q) ∧ (q → p) ≡ (p ↔ q). Solution: T. (p → q) ∨ (q → p) ≡ (p ↔ q). Solution: F. For example if p = T and q = F , then p ↔ q is false, but (p → q) ∨ (q → p) = (T → F ) ∨ (F → T ) = F ∨ T = T. (The domain of discourse for (e)-(g) is Z.) ∀n∃m(n = m2 ). Solution: F. For √ n = 2, there is no integer m so that 2 = m2 (since ± 2 is not an integer). ∃n∀m(nm = n). Solution: T. n = 0 works, since for all m, nm = 0·m = 0 = n. ∀n(n2 + 1 > 0). Solution: T. Since n2 ≥ 0, we have n2 + 1 ≥ 1 > 0. Let f : R → R be given by f (x) = 3x − 5. Then f is one-to-one. Solution: T. If y = 3x − 5, then x = 13 (y + 5). So for each y, there is only one x so that y = 3x − 5. f from (h) is onto. Solution: T. See (h) above. For f from (h), f −1 (x) = 3x + 5. Solution: F. f −1 (x) = 13 (x + 5), as we compute in (h) above. Consider A = {0, 1, 2, 3}. The function g : A → A defined by g(x) = 2x mod 4 is a bijection. Solution: F. Compute g(0) = 0, g(1) = 2, g(2) = 0, and g(3) = 2. This shows g is not onto (since 1 and 3 are not in the range), and also g is not one-to-one, since g(0) = g(2). (l) T F (m) T F (n) T F (o) T F (p) T F (q) T F (r) T F (s) T F (t) T F (u) T F (v) T F (w) T F (x) T F (y) T F (z) T F For A as in (k), the function h : A → A defined by h(x) = 3x mod 4 is a bijection. Solution: T. Compute h(0) = 0, h(1) = 3, h(2) = 2, h(3) = 1. This is clearly one-to-one and onto, and thus is a bijection. If X, Y are subsets of a universal set U , then X ∩ Y = X ∪Y. Solution: T. This is DeMorgan’s Law. For X, Y as in (m), it is always true that |X ∪ Y | = |X| + |Y |. Solution: F. This is false (for finite sets) if X and Y are not disjoint. So if X = {1, 2}, and Y = {2, 3}, then X ∪ Y = {1, 2, 3}, and |X ∪ Y | = 3 6= 2 + 2 = |X| + |Y |. If V = {1, 2, 3} and W = {a, b, c, d}, then there exists a one-to-one function f : V → W . Solution: T. For example, define f by f (1) = a, f (2) = b, f (3) = c. For V, W as in (o), there exists an onto function g : V → W. Solution: F. If f : V → W , then the range {f (1), f (2), f (3)} can have at most 3 elements. This cannot cover all of W , whose cardinality is 4. If A, B are sets, then A ∩ B = B ∩ A. Solution: T. Again A, B are sets. Then (A ⊆ B) ∨ (B ⊆ A). Solution: F. For example, A = {1} and B = {2} give a counterexample. If A, B are sets, then (A − B) ∪ B = A ∪ B. Solution: T. Draw the Venn diagram. If A, B are finite sets, then |A ∩ B| + |A ∪ B| = |A| + |B|. Solution: T. Draw the Venn diagram. For (u)-(w), the domain of discourse is R. ∀x∃y(x = 2y). Solution: T. Take y = 21 x. ∃x∀y(xy = y). Solution: T. x = 1 works. ∀x(x2 > 0). Solution: x = 0 is a counterexample. For all integers n ≥ 1, n! < 10n2 . Solution: F. The first counterexample is n = 6: 6! = 720 but 10n2 = 360. Any conditional proposition is logically equivalent to its converse. Solution: F. Any conditional proposition is logically equivalent to its contrapositive. Solution: T.
© Copyright 2024