PHIL10131: Metaphysics of Mind 2014-15 Course Organizer: Prof Jesper Kallestrup - [email protected] Course Lecturers: Prof Jesper Kallestrup Dr Chris Ranalli - [email protected] Course Secretary: Sue Richards - [email protected] Contents 1. (Course) Aims and Objectives 2. Intended Learning Outcomes 3. Lecture Times and Locations 4. Lecture Content 5. PPLS Undergraduate Student Handbook 6. MSc Programme Handbook 7. Readings 8. MSc Tutorials 9. Assessment Information 10. Learn 11. Autonomous Learning Groups 12. Useful Information 13. Common Marking Scheme Department of Philosophy School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences University of Edinburgh 1. Course Aims and Objectives This course examines some central questions at the intersection of Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: questions that concern the fundamental kind of thing that minds are; how to find a place for them in a physical world; and how they can have behavioural effects if they are not themselves fully physical. The first part of the course will survey various historical views of what minds are such as dualism, the mind-body identity theory and functionalism. Secondly, we will then expound physicalism, and examine a causal argument to the effect that mental states must be identical with physical states. In the last part of the course we deal with various conceivability arguments against physicalism such as Chalmers’s zombie argument and Jackson’s knowledge argument. 2. Intended Learning Outcomes By the end of this course students should: Have an in-depth understanding of core arguments in the metaphysics of mind. Understand central issues in contemporary philosophy of mind, e.g. non-reductive and a priori physicalism; functionalism and the multiple realizability of the mental, problems about mental causation and various conceivability arguments. Be able to analyse these arguments and offer their own evaluations of their strengths and weaknesses Be able to clearly explain these arguments in a written format. Gain transferable skills in research, analysis, argumentation and presentation. 3. Lecture Times and Locations The class meets weekly on Mondays 2.10 - 4.00 p.m. in the Dugald Stewart Building, room 1.20. 4. Lecture Content Week 1 15 September Introduction Kallestrup/Ranalli Week 2 22 September Substance Dualism Ranalli Week 3 29 September The Causal Pairing Problem Ranalli Week 4 6 October The Mind-Body Identity Theory Ranalli Week 5 13 October Varieties of Functionalism Ranalli Week 6 20 October Physicalism I: Defining the View Kallestrup Week 7 27 October Physicalism II: Reduction and the A Priori Kallestrup Week 8 3 November The Causal Exclusion Argument Kallestrup Week 9 10 November Kripke's Argument against the Identity Theory Kallestrup Week 10 17 November Chalmers' Zombie Argument Kallestrup Week 11 24 November Jackson's Knowledge Argument Kallestrup 5. PPLS Undergraduate Student Handbook The PPLS Undergraduate Student Handbook has more information on Student Support and academic guidance; late coursework and plagiarism; illness and disability adjustments, and useful sources of advice. The Handbook can be found here: http://www.ppls.ed.ac.uk/students/undergraduate/documents/PPLS_Student_Handbook-Master_Copy.pdf 6. MSc Programme Handbook MSc students can find information about our postgraduate policies regarding late submission, essay extensions, assessment deadlines and so on in our MSc Programme Handbook. The handbook can be found here: http://www.ppls.ed.ac.uk/students/postgraduate/taught_research_masters.php#Handbooks Lists of MSc specializations and postgraduate courses in Philosophy can be found here: http://www.philosophy.ed.ac.uk/phil_students/postgraduate/current_postgraduates/mSc_dip_stud ents.php 7. Readings Recommended textbooks include Danial Stoljar’s Physicalism, Routledge 2010 [P], Tom Crane’s Elements of Mind, Oxford University Press, 2001 [EOM], and Jaegwon Kim’s Philosophy of Mind, Westview Press, 2006 [POM]. Several of the class readings will be taken from Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, edited by Brian McLaughlin and Jonathan Cohen, Blackwells, 2007 [CDPM]. We will also make extensive use of the Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin and Sven Walter, Oxford University Press 2009 [OHPM]. All of these books are on reserve in the main library. Copies are also are available in the Blackwells Bookshop on South Bridge. Week 1: Introduction We will begin with a quick overview of the central topics to be covered in the course, and discuss class structure and assessment. We will also review some of the main positions that have been defended in the philosophical literature on the metaphysics of mind. Required Readings: 1. Jesper Kallestrup (2009) ‘The Mind-Body World-Knot’, Think 8, 37-51. 2. Tim Crane, EoM, Chapter 2 ‘Body’. Optional Readings: 1. David Chalmers Ted talk: http://www.ted.com/talks/david_chalmers_how_do_you_explain_consciousness#t-666059 2. Jaegwon Kim, POM, Chap. 1. Week 2: Substance Dualism We will look at substance dualism, the view that we are composed of an extended, non-thinking, material substance and a non-extended, thinking mental substance. We will also examine Descartes’ conceivability arguments for this view. Required Readings: 1. Rene Descartes, Meditations II and VI. The prescribed translation of Descartes’ Meditations is John Cottingham’s. This is available in at least three formats, the following from Cambridge University Press: Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes Vol. II, and Meditations on First Philosophy, with Selections from the Objections and Replies, translated by J. Cottingham with an introduction by B. Williams. 2. Jaegwon Kim, POM, Chapter 2 “Substance Dualism”. 3. Tim Crane, EoM, Chapter 9 and 10. 4. E. J. Lowe, ‘Dualism’ in OHPM. Optional Readings: 1. John A. Foster (1989). “A Defense of Dualism.” In J. Smythies & John Beloff (eds.), The Case for Dualism. University of Virginia Press. 2. William Lycan (2009). “Giving Dualism its Due.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (4):551-563. Week 3: The Causal Pairing Problem If substance dualism is true then it becomes problematic how the mental, being located outside space-time, can causally interact with physical objects at particular times and places. We will scrutinize this so-called causal pairing problem. Required Readings: 1. Jaegwon Kim, PoM, Chapter 6 “Mind as a Causal System” and Chapter 7 “Mental Causation”. 2. Jaegwon Kim (2005), ‘The Rejection of Immaterial Minds: A Causal Argument’ in Physicalism, or Something Near Enough, Princeton University Press. 3. Tim Crane, EoM, Chap 11. Optional Readings: 1. Jaegwon Kim, ‘Mental Causation’ in OHPM. 2. Tim Crane, ‘The Mental Causation Debate’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. suppl. Vol. 69, 1995, 211-36. 3. Frank Jackson, ‘Mental Causation: The State of the Art’, Mind, 105, 1996, 377-413. Week 4: The Mind-Body Identity Theory This week we will look at the mind-body identity theory, as advocated by Place, Smart, Davidson and others, both as a claim about psychophysical types and as a claim about psychophysical tokens. We will also assess some of the objections that were made against this theory. Required Readings: 1. Tim Crane, EoM, Chap 14. 2. Jaegwon Kim, PoM, Chap 4. 3. Place, U. T. (1956) “Is Consciousness a Brain Process?”, in W. G. Lycan (Ed.) (1999) Mind and Cognition: A Reader. (2nd. Ed.) Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, pp. 14-19 Optional Readings: 1. Smart, J.J.C., (1959) ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review 68: 141-156. Available online at: http://philosophyfaculty.ucsd.edu/faculty/rarneson/Courses/SMARTJACKphil1.pdf 2. Davidson, D. (1980) “Mental Events”, in W. G. Lycan (Ed.) (1999) Mind and Cognition: A Reader. (2nd. Ed.) Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, pp. 35-45. 3. Lewis, David (1970). “An Argument for the Identity Theory.” Journal of Philosophy 63 (2):17-25. Week 5: Varieties of Functionalism Functionalism says that to be in a mental state is to be in a state that plays a certain causal role. We will survey and evaluate different types of functionalism, such as analytic functionalism and the distinction between role-functionalism and filler-functionalism. Required Readings: 1. Kim, PoM, Chapters 5 and 6. Week 6: Physicalism I: Defining the View Physicalism says that ultimately there is nothing over and above the physical. To properly define this view we need to know what is meant by ‘physical’. If we are confined to what current physics tells us then physicalism is most certainly false, but if we also include properties, etc., in a future, complete physics then physicalism seems trivial. This problem is called Hempel’s Dilemma. Required Readings Stoljar, P, Chap 2-5. Recommended Readings Crane, EoM, Chap 12. Barbara Montero, ‘What is the Physical?’ in OHPM. Daniel Stoljar (2001) ‘Two Conceptions of the Physical’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXII, 253-281. Week 7: Physicalism II: Reduction and the A Priori We continue to explore disagreements within the physicalist camp. In particular, some physicalists hold that mental and other special science properties are reducible to physical properties, and some physicalists claim that all the truths of our world are in principle a priori deducible from the physical truths. We will look at various objections to both of these claims. Required Readings Stoljar, P, Chap 6-8. Recommended Readings Crane, EoM, Chaps 12, 14 and 15. Chaps 9 and 10 (on reductive physicalism) and chaps 11 and 12 (on a priori physicalism) in CDPM. Jaegwon Kim (2005), ‘Reduction, Reductive Explanation and Closing the “Gap” and “Explanatory Arguments for Type Physicalism and Why They Don’t Work” in his Physicalism or Something Near Enough, Princeton University Press. Julie Yoo, ‘Anomalous Monism’ in OHPH. Lynne Rudder Baker, ‘Non-Reductive Materialism’ in OHPH. Week 8: The Causal Exclusion Argument The causal exclusion argument presents a challenge to non-reductive physicalism according to which mental states are distinct from, yet metaphysically necessitated by, physical states. How can mental states cause behavioural states if no effect has more than one cause and those behavioural effects have distinct physical causes? Required Readings Jaegwon Kim, ‘The Supervenience Argument Motivated, Clarified, and Defended’ in his Physicalism Or Something Near Enough, Princeton University Press, 2005. Kim, PoM, Chap 6/7. Recommended Readings Crane, EoM, Chaps 17, 18 and 19. Stoljar, P, Chap 11. Chaps 13 (Kim’s ‘Causation and Mental Causation’) and 14 (Loewer’s ‘Mental Causation, or Something Near Enough’) in CDPM. Jaegwon Kim, ‘Mental Causation’ in OHPM. Jesper Kallestrup (2006), ‘The Causal Exclusion Argument’, Philosophical Studies 131, 459-485. David Papineau, ‘The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism’ in OHPM. Yablo, S. ‘Mental Causation’, The Philosophical Review, Vol. 101, No. 2, 1992. N. Block, ‘Can the mind change the world?’ in Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam, ed. G. Boolos, Cambridge University Press, 1990, 137-170. T. Horgan, ‘Kim on Mental Causation and Causal Exclusion’, Philosophical Perspectives 11 (1998), 165-84. Week 9: Kripke's Argument against the Identity Theory We now turn to arguments against physicalism. The first is Kripke’s conceivability argument against the mind-body identity theory. In order to assess this argument, we shall examine underlying issues in philosophy of language such as the putative rigidity of phenomenal terms as well as the distinctive way in which such terms have their reference fixed. Required Readings S. Kripke, Naming and Necessity, Lecture III, Oxford: Blackwell, 1980. Recommended Readings Stoljar, P, Chap 10. Jesper Kallestrup (2008), ‘Three Strands in Kripke's Argument against the Identity Theory’, Philosophy Compass 3, 1255-1280. Week 10: Chalmers' Zombie Argument If physicalism is true, then zombie worlds, i.e. worlds that are void of consciousness despite being physically identical to our world, are metaphysically impossible. We will look at Chalmers’ anti-physicalist argument that such worlds are metaphysically possible, because they are conceivable and conceivability entails metaphysical possibility. Required Reading David Chalmers, ‘The Two-Dimensional Argument Against Materialism’ in OHPM. Recommended Readings Kim, PoM, Chapter 7. Crane, EoM, Chapter 3, Sec. 29, 30. D. Chalmers, Chapter 4 in his The Conscious Mind, Oxford University Press, 1996. S. Shoemaker, ‘Functionalism and Qualia’ in his Identity, Cause and Mind, Cambridge University Press, 1984. C. Hill, ‘Imaginability, Conceivability, Possibility and the Mind-Body Problem’, Philosophical Studies 87, 1997, 61-85. R. Stalnaker, ‘What is it Like to Be a Zombie?’, in Gendler, T., and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility, Oxford University Press, 2002. D. Stoljar, ‘The Conceivability Argument and Two Conceptions of the Physical’, in Philosophical Perspectives 15, (ed.) J. E. Tomberlin, Blackwell, 2001, 393-413 Week 11: Jackson's Knowledge Argument After presenting Jackson’s knowledge argument against physicalism, based on his thought experiment about black-and-white Mary, we will examine some influential responses, e.g. to do with the distinction between propositional knowledge and know-how, and the possibility of acquiring new knowledge of a fact that one already knew in some other way. Required Readings F. Jackson, ‘What Mary didn't know’, Journal of Philosophy 83, 1986, 291-295. D. Lewis, ‘What Experience Teaches’, in his Papers in Epistemology and Metaphysics, Cambridge University Press, 1999. Recommended Readings J. Kim, PoM, Chapter 7. T. Crane, EoM, Chapter 3, Sec. 26, 28. F. Jackson, ‘Consciousness’, in the Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, (eds.) F. Jackson and M. Smith, Oxford University Press, 2007. 8. MSc Tutorials MSc students will meet with Prof Kallestrup on 16th October 3.00 - 5.00, 6th November 3.00- 5.00 and 27th November 3.10 - 5.00 in the Dugald Stewart Building, room 401. 9. Assessment Information The UG version of this course is assessed by two essays: 1st Essay (1,500 words) 40%; due Thursday 23rd October 2014, by 4pm. 2nd Essay (2,500 words) 60%; due Thursday 11th December 2014, by 4pm. The MSc students will write one essay (2,500 words); due Monday 15th December at 12 noon. Essay Questions Essay one: (1) (1) Present the causal pairing problem for substance dualism, and discuss how the substance dualist might respond. (2) Is it the case, as stated by Block (1978), that functionalism is guilty of liberalism? (3) (3) Is it plausible that mental states can be identified with physical states of the brain if mental states are multiple realisable? Essay two: (1) (1) Present the causal exclusion problem for non-reductive physicalism, and discuss how the nonreductive physicalist might respond. (2) How might one argue that Zombies are conceivable but not possible? (3) Does the ability hypothesis satisfactorily answer the knowledge argument? Notes on referencing for an essay A clear referencing system is essential for any good essay. As this is a relatively easy thing to achieve, there should be no excuse for poor referencing. Quotations Quotations must be accompanied by the author, date and page number. E.g. ‘Mirror neuron activation can easily be interpreted as part of the neuronal processes that underlie social perception.’ (Gallagher, 2008a, p. 541) Some of the articles we use are pre-prints. When possible, use the page number from the actual publication (if this is a journal article, then you can find it online). If this is not possible, then write ‘quote’ (forthcoming) or ‘quote’ (on-line source). Bibliography References should be in alphabetical order by author, and, if there is more than one entry for an author, in date order for that author (using 'a', 'b' etc, if there is more than a single reference for that author in a given year) . Below are some examples of difference types of reference. Burge, T. (1979) Example of a journal article reference. Synthese, 40, 265-81. Csibra, G. (2005, January 2). Example of an online paper or forum discussion. Retrieved from http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/4. Dummett, M. (1973) Example of a Book Reference. London: Duckworth. Kripke, S. (1979) Example of an article in an edited collection. In A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Dordrecht: Reidel, 32–56. Hutto, D.D. (2010a) Example of a journal article reference. Philosophical Explorations, 32, 5690. Hutto, D.D. (2010b) Example of a journal article reference. Philosophical Quarterly, 25, 1 - 11. Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (eds) (1999) Example of an Edited Book Reference. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press. Please note: do not use the format of the course readings as your template for the bibliography, as I’ve collated them from different sources so they are not uniform. Word Count Penalties Essays must not exceed the word limit, which includes footnotes but excludes bibliography. The precise word count must be written on the coversheet. Overlong essays will be penalised according to the following rule: 5% will be deducted for every 100 words, or part thereof, over the word limit. So, 1-100 words over lose 5%; 101-200 words over lose 10%; 201-300 words over lose 15%; and so on. Penalties for Late Submission of Essays Unless an extension has been granted, essays must be submitted by the dates shown in the table of Submission Dates below. Essays submitted late without an extension may not be marked, but, if marked, will incur a penalty (in accordance with section 3.8 of the University Undergraduate Assessment Regulations at: http://www.ed.ac.uk/schools-departments/academic-services/policiesregulations/regulations/assessment For each working day that the work is late there will be a reduction of the mark by 5% of the maximum obtainable mark (e.g. a mark of 65% on the common marking scale would be reduced to 60% up to 24 hours later). This penalty applies for up to five working days, after which a mark of zero will be given. Plagiarism Essays will be checked for plagiarism using Turnitin. The University treats plagiarism by honours students as a disciplinary offence, and anyone caught plagiarising will be referred to the College’s Academic Misconduct Officer. If you are unsure what constitutes plagiarism or need further guidance, you should consult the University’s guidelines: http://www.ed.ac.uk/schools-departments/academicservices/students/undergraduate/discipline/plagiarism Students can read more about plagiarism and proper referencing practices, and use Turnitin on a trial copy of their essays, in the Philosophy Tools course on LEARN. Extensions Students are expected to monitor their workload, be aware of all deadlines, and organise themselves accordingly. Extension requests should be submitted before the submission deadline. They must be submitted to the Teaching Office for approval, and must include details of the assessment(s) affected and the length of extension requested, together with supporting evidence if required. Other than in exceptional circumstances, extensions will only be granted in cases of illness or family emergency. If students are seeking extensions for more than one week, they must provide medical evidence and/or discuss the request with the Student Support Officer. Extension requests due to time mismanagement, personal computing/printing problems or ignorance of deadline will not be accepted. The Teaching Office will email the student to tell them whether the extension has been granted. The decision conveyed in this email is final; if students feel that they have been unfairly denied an extension they should make a case to the special circumstances committee for the removal of late submission penalties at the examination board. Retrospective extensions will not be granted. However, late submission penalties may be waived if a student requests an extension on the day of the deadline but cannot get medical evidence until some days later. Students with Adjustment Schedules. Extension requests from students with adjustment schedules that allow ‘short notice extensions’ will be treated sympathetically where possible. Students should however be prepared to give a reason for the extension request; simply citing an adjustment schedule is not an adequate reason. If students are seeking extensions for more than one week, they must provide medical evidence and/or discuss the request with the Student Support Officer. Special Circumstances. Students may apply for consideration of special circumstances if they feel that events out with their control have resulted in poor exam performance in comparison to their previous coursework record or even missing an exam. These circumstances most commonly include illness or bereavement but can be submitted for a variety of issues. It is the student’s responsibility to complete a Special Circumstances form giving as much detail as possible and providing supporting evidence. All submissions must be accompanied by medical or other documentation. Please note - Regulation 14 Assessment deadlines: Student responsibilities It is a student’s responsibility to ascertain and meet his or her assessment deadlines, including examination times and locations. Feedback You will get many feedback or feedforward opportunities in your courses. Feedback could be in the form of an essay, a draft write-up, self-generated or peer feedback, small group discussions or quizzes within lectures etc. Feedforward might include a discussion of how to write an essay, or prepare for an exam. Feedback is essential to learning and it takes many forms. We strongly encourage you to use all forms of feedback, including: Asking and answering questions in lectures or classes Asking questions of your Course Organiser or lecturer in their office hours Discussing your work with lecturers and examiners on Philosophy's dedicated Feedback Days (Honours students) Actively participating in your tutorials (pre-Honours students) Actively participating in Autonomous Learning Groups (Honours students) Talking about your ideas outside class with fellow Philosophy students Taking your essay to PhilSoc essay surgeries Participating in PhilSoc discussion groups and study-skills events Participating in PhilSoc debates and talks: http://euphilsoc.weebly.com/ Participating in the British Undergraduate Philosophy Society, including undergraduate conferences: http://www.bups.org If you have any suggestions on how to improve feedback further, please contact either: Your Tutor (pre-Honours students) Your Course Organiser Your Personal Tutor Sarah Nicol, PPLS Student Support Officer ([email protected]) Dr Mark Sprevak, Director of Undergraduate Teaching ([email protected]) 10. Learn This year the majority of courses will use electronic submissions for Honours coursework. For essay submission instructions please see the instructions on LEARN. Please note you should not include your name or matriculation number on coursework, only your exam number. 11, Autonomous Learning Groups One of the best ways to learn, and get feedback, is from talking to each other. In order to facilitate this, each of your Honours courses now has dedicated Autonomous Learning Groups. In week 2, you will receive an email from our Student Support Officer (Sarah Nicol, [email protected]) asking if you would like to be part of an Autonomous Learning Group (ALG) for each of your Honours courses. If you agree, Sarah will form the ALGs for you and email you with details of which group you are in, and the email addresses of the other members of the group. It is up to you, the members of the ALG, to organize the meetings. You decide how often to meet and what to do in your ALG. ALGs are designed to help you learn and get to know your classmates; they are not a formal requirement of the course. It is important to note that assessment in your courses is non-competitive: you are not competing against your classmates, only against the general grade criteria. It is in your interests to help each other. As a rough guide, we suggest your ALG meets every 2-3 weeks. You could use the meetings to: Read and discuss the papers together Discuss essay-writing and time-management techniques Constructively critique each other's draft essays or plans Read some of the further readings or related papers Work on presentations or discussion posts that the class may involve Share tips on career advice Sarah will be able to help you with room booking (you can also do this yourself through MyEd). Please email the CO of the course if you feel that it would be useful for the group if she or he joined one of your sessions. Please contact Sarah if you find it necessary during the semester to transfer into a different group. ALGs are a new initiative by Philosophy and we appreciate your thoughts. If you feedback on how to make ALGs even better, please email Sarah Nicol ([email protected]) or the Director of Undergraduate Teaching, Dr. Mark Sprevak ([email protected]). 12. Useful Information Office Hours Prof Kallestrup’s office hour is Thursday 2.00pm - 3.00pm or by email appointment. Dr Ranalli’s office hour is by email appointment only. Office hours are a good time for you to come and discuss ideas for your essays. Please don’t think you need a ‘problem’ to come to office hours. We are always willing to use this time to chat through any thoughts you may be having about topics covered in the course, or topics for your essays. Attendance by ALL students at University classes, seminars and tutorials etc The University expects all students to attend all their University classes, lectures and tutorials etc, whether or not these are described as “compulsory” by the School. This includes participating fully in the requirements of all courses, including submitting assignments, contributing to tutorials and workshops or laboratories, attending meetings with Personal Tutors and sitting examinations. Your attendance will be monitored by the School, so that staff can help you to manage your progress through the courses. We will do this so we can be quickly alerted to any additional pastoral or academic support needs any student might require, and so that the School can provide advice, guidance or support in a timely and useful manner. WEEK 6 INNOVATIVE LEARNING WEEK (16-20 February 2015). Normal teaching slots will be suspended and in their place will be a range of other activities such as master classes, a research day, a science fair, and guest lectures. More information will follow nearer the time so please check the School website where details will be available on the PPLS Events page: http://www.ed.ac.uk/staff-students/students/academic-life/studies/innovative-learning 13. Common Marking Scheme http://www.ed.ac.uk/schools-departments/registry/exams/regulations/common-marking-scheme A1 90100 Excellent Outstanding in every respect, the work is well beyond the level expected of a competent student a of study. A2 80-89 Excellent Outstanding in some respects, the work is often beyond what is expected of a competent student a level of study. A3 70-79 Excellent Very good or excellent in most respects, the work is what might be expected of a very competent B 60-69 Very Good Good or very good in most respects, the work displays thorough mastery of the relevant learning C 50-59 Good The work clearly meets requirements for demonstrating the relevant learning outcomes. D 40-49 Pass The work meets minimum requirements for demonstrating the relevant learning outcomes. E 30-39 Marginal fail The work fails to meet minimum requirements for demonstrating the relevant learning outcomes F 20-29 Clear fail The work is very weak or shows a decided lack of effort. G 10-19 Bad fail The work is extremely weak. H 0-9 Bad fail The work is of very little consequence, if any, to the area in question. The Philosophy Department has also adopted a set of grade-related marking criteria which are worth bearing in mind when writing essays: Grade Bands Fail (less than 40) Third Class (40–49): • Writing is generally unclear. Frequent spelling or grammar mistakes, incorrect language, and/or excessively convoluted sentence structure. • Neglects clearly to state a thesis or position and/or fails to support this with arguments. Contains irrelevant material, or material whose relevance is not adequately explained. • Demonstrates a barely adequate understanding of central issues. Contains several errors in exposition or in explanation of concepts. • No evidence of independent thought or critical engagement. Merely rehashes arguments from readings or lectures. • Where arguments are given, these are weak, depend on invalid inferences or implausible premises. Fails to anticipate obvious objections. Lower Second Class (50–59): • Writing is generally clear, but there are occasional spelling/grammar infelicities and/or poorly constructed sentences. • A thesis/position is indicated but not clearly defined. Some arguments given, but their structure often unclear. • Demonstrates a basic grasp of key concepts, but occasional inaccuracies in exposition/explanation. • Little evidence of independent thought. Some suggestion of original ideas, but these are underdeveloped and/or expressed unclearly. • Arguments generally weak or unconvincing. Upper Second Class (60–69): • Writing is generally clear, marred only by the rare spelling/grammar infelicity or poorly constructed sentence. • A thesis/position is indicated and clearly defined. Arguments are given with relatively clear structure. It is generally clear what is going on in each section, why one section follows on from the previous one, and how the essay as a whole hangs together. • Demonstrates a solid understanding of the key concepts, and the exposition is generally accurate and thorough. • Substantial evidence of original thought – either an original argument of some kind for a familiar position or an original argument for a novel position. In either case, the argument should be reasonably well developed. • The author’s original arguments are interesting and promising, but fairly central or glaring problems with the argument are not discussed or addressed in any way, or are given only a highly cursory treatment. Low First Class (70–79): • Writing is very clear and engaging throughout. Where examples are used they are both relevant and memorable. The writing will also be concise. • The essay’s structure is not only clear and well defined; it also provides a satisfying narrative arc. • Demonstrates a deep understanding of the key concepts. Explains other philosopher’s ideas in the author’s own terms, clearly presenting those ideas in a way that indicates that the author has “made them his/her own.” Where technical terms are used they are always carefully defined. • Highly original thought, with well developed arguments. The exegesis will generally be sufficiently concise as to allow the author to develop his or her own arguments in considerable detail. • The author very carefully considers the most central and obvious problems with his/her original argument(s) and has interesting things to say about them. Mid-First Class (80–89): • Writing is crystal clear and highly engaging throughout. Memorable examples are used to underscore key points. The writing is concise without coming across as terse or stilted. • The essay’s structure is clear and well defined, with a highly satisfying narrative arc. • Demonstrates a deep understanding of key concepts. Not only explains the ideas of other philosophers in a way that shows he/she has “made them his/her own,” but that actually casts new light on how we might charitably understand the ideas of those philosophers. • Very original thought, above and beyond what we would normally expect from an undergraduate. These original ideas will be developed in great detail. • The author very carefully considers the most central and obvious problems with his/her original argument(s) and has prima facie convincing rejoinders. Author may also consider more subtle objections to his/her argument(s)/view(s). High First Class (90–100): • Writing is extremely clear, concise, and engaging — of a publishable quality. • The essay’s structure is extremely clear and well-defined, with a highly satisfying narrative arc. • Demonstrates a deep understanding of key concepts. Not only explains the ideas of other philosophers in a way that shows he/she has “made them his/her own,” but that actually casts new light on how we might charitably understand the ideas of those philosophers. • A highly original and well developed line of argument and/or novel view, such that the essay is publishable, at least in an undergraduate or postgraduate journal, perhaps bordering on being publishable in a mainstream professional journal. • The author considers the most important objections to his/her arguments/views. The replies are generally convincing and subtle. If space allows, less obvious objections may also be discussed in interesting ways. 2. Robert Van Gulick, ‘Functionalism’ in OHPM. 3. Putnam, H. (1967) “The Nature of Mental States”, in W. G. Lycan (Ed.) (1999) Mind and Cognition: A Reader. (2nd. Ed.) Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, pp. 27-34. Optional Readings: 1. J. Searle, “Minds, Brains and Programs”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:417-57: Available online at: http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/MindsBrainsPrograms.html 2. A. M. Turing (1950) “Computing Machinery and Intelligence”, Mind 49: 433-460: Available online at: http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000499/00/turing.html 3. Block, N. “The Mind as the Software of the Brain” Available online at: http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/msb.html 4. Horgan, T. 1984. “Functionalism and Token Physicalism”. Synthese 59:321-38. 5. Jackson, F., Pargetter, R. & Prior, E. W. 1982. “Functionalism and Type-Type Identity Theories”. Philosophical Studies 42:209-25. 6. David Lewis, “Mad Pain and Martian Pain”, in Problems in Mind, J. Crumley, ed., Mayfield Publishing Company, 2000, pp. 110-117. Originally published in Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. I, N. Block, ed., Harvard University Press, 1980, pp. 216-222.
© Copyright 2024