Copyright 0 1992 by the Genetics Society of America Perspectives Anecdotal, Historical and Critical Commentaries on Genetics Edited by James F. Crow and William F. Dove What Did GREGOR MENDELThink He Discovered? Daniel L. H a d * and Vitezslav Orel+ *Department of Genetics, Washington University School of Medicine, St. Louis,Missouri 631 10-1095, and +Museum of the Mendelianum, Brno, Czechoslovakia REGOR MENDEL is accorded a special place in the history of genetics. His experiments, beautifully designed, were the first to focus on the numerical relationships among traits appearing in the progeny of hybrids; and his interpretation, clear and concise, was based on material hereditary elements that undergo segregation and independent assortment. Poignantly overshadowing the creative brilliance of MENDEL’S work is the fact that it was virtually ignored for 34 years. Only after the dramatic rediscovery in 1900-16 years after MENDEL’Sdeath-was MENDEL rightfully recognized as the founder of genetics. Mendelian mythmaking?This orthodox interpretation of MENDEL’Scontribution has recently been challenged as G . . . a myth created by the early geneticists to reinforce the belief that the laws of inheritance are obvious to anyone who looks closely enough at the problem (BOWLER 1989, p. 103). This opinion reflects revisionistviews of MENDELand his intentions that have received considerable prominence in journals dealing with the history of science. The new perspectives come from several directions. One influential view is that MENDELwas not interested in heredity, as such, but in the role of hybrids in the generation ofnewspecies. This viewof MENDEL’S work . . . strips it of inflated Whiggish interpretations and places it squarely within the context of mid-nineteenth century biology (OLBY1979, p. 53). T h e iconoclasticconclusion is that ifyou define a Mendelian . . . as one who subscribes explicitly to the existence of a finite number of hereditary elements which in the simplest case is two per hereditary trait, only one of which mayenter a germ cell, then Mendel was clearly no Mendelian (OLBY 1979, p. 68). Genetics 131: 245-253 uune, 1992) A second view echoes the emphasis on MENDELas hybridist . . . concerned with the formation and development of hybrids . . . using empirical methods . . . [who did] not explain his results by employing invisible particulate determiners, paired or otherwise (MONAGHAN and CORCOS 1990, p. 268). A third view imputes to MENDEL a dark motive in performing his experiments: that he had actually set out to prove that hybrids gave invariant progeny (essentially anantidarwinian rejection of descent with modification) and that his work with Hieracium was not undertaken to demonstrate agreement withhis results with Pisum but rather to demonstrate the existence ofconstant (nonsegregating)hybrids (CALLENDER 1988). A fourth view goes well beyond the others in claiming that [Mendel’s monohybrid] experiments are fictitious in the sense that they have been carried out only on paper: the numerical data relative to them have been obtained by progressively disaggregating those from polyhybrid crosses. In otherwords, Mendel never carried outthese experiments in the garden,but rather only on the pages ofhis notebooks (DI TROCCHIO 1991, p. 515). We believe that it would be worthwhile to examine these claims in a forum accessible to geneticists. Most instructors in genetics, and most genetics textbooks, still put forth the orthodox interpretation of MENDEL’S work. STERNand SHERWOOD (1966), in the foreword to their translation of MENDEL’SVersuche uber P$anzen-Hybriden, point out that . . . in the history of Mendelism the eternal is strongly confounded with the ephemeral. There is the neglect of Mendel’s accomplishments during his lifetime and the futility of his years of writing to Nageli. There is the uneven history of the rediscovery of his work 34 years after its publication and its striking reanalysis [by FISHER(1936)l another 36 years later. 246 D. L. Hart1 and V.Orel Only time will tell whether the revisionist views of MENDEL’S work are ephemeral, but if the orthodox work is seriously flawed interpretation of MENDEL’S in any respect, then it ought to be adjusted. Why the neglect?Although the main themes of this paper are paraphrases of FISHER’S(1936) searching questions-What was MENDELtrying to discover? What did he discover? What did he think he discovered?there are additional issues concerning MENDEL’S work that warrant updating. First, why was the work neglected for so long? A comprehensive and thoughtful discussion of various categories of explanation is presented by SANDLER and SANDLER (1985). While granting a role to the relativeinaccessibility of the Verhan- dlungen des naturforschenden Vereines in Briinn (Brno), in which MENDEL’Spaper was published, to the overshadowingcontemporaryinterest in organic evolution, and to the strangeness andnovelty of MENDEL’S experimental approach, SANDLER SANDLER and nevertheless conclude that MENDEL’S paper was simply incomprehensible to his contemporaries since heredity and development were completely confounded conceptually in the latter half of the 19th century. T h e transmission of hereditary traits from parents to offspring was considered partof the same process as the development of traits in the offspring; heredity was but a moment in development with no need for a conceptual framework of its own. Hence, while Mendel . . . defined his problem in purely genetic terms, and produced a correct and amazingly completeanswer, [it was] to an asyet unformulated question! (SANDLER and SANDLER 1985, p. 69). The all too goodness of fit: Another issue is the excessive goodness of fit of MENDEL’Sratios (FISHER 1936; EDWARDS 1986). Itis unfortunate that FISHER’S . . . painstaking analysis and his defense of Mendel’s integrity havesometimesbeenincorrectly reported ashaving exposed a scientific fraud of major proportions. . . (EDWARDS 1986, p. 296). T h e truth is that, while the datashow a persistentlack of extreme segregations, as if there had been some trimming of highly deviant values (EDWARDS 1986), the bias toward expectation is slight (WRIGHT 1966). Considering the entirety of the evidence, EDWARDS (1 986) agrees with DOBZHANSKY’S conclusion: Few experimenters are lucky enough to have no mistakes or accidents happen in any of their experiments, and it is only common sense to have such failures discarded. The evident danger is ascribing to mistakes and expunging from the record perfectly authentic experimental results which do not fit one’s expectations. Not having been familiar with chi-squares and other statistical tests, Mendel may have, in perfect conscience, thrown out some crosses which he suspected to involve pollen contamination or other accident (DOBZHANSKY 1967, p. 1589). More recently, MENDELhas also been accused of a 1991). more subtle kind of deception (DI TROCCHIO From his analysis of the Versuche, DI TROCCHIO supposes that MENDELdid not actually do the crosses he reported.What he actuallydid,accordingtothis reconstruction, was to carry out no fewer than 484 crosses representing all pairwise reciprocal combinations of the 22 varieties of Pisum that MENDELhad available. Most of these crosseswouldhaveshown either no segregationor segregation for several traits. Among the latter,MENDELpooled the marginal totals and reported them as monohybrid segregations.Even if MENDEL followed this procedure, the marginal totals were obtained in realcrosses and could hardly be regardedas“fictitious.”Furthermore,it is hard to believe that MENDEL actually followed thisprocedure without saying so, since he roundly criticized GARTNER for not describing his experiments in sufficient detail to allow MENDELto repeat them: The results which Gartner obtained in his experiments are known to me; I have repeated his workand have reexamined it carefullyto find, if possible, an agreement with those laws of development which I found to be true for my experimental plant. However, try as I would, I was unable to follow his experiments completely, not in a single case! It is very regrettable that this worthy man did not publish a detailed description of his individual experiments . . . However, in most cases, it can at least be recognized that the possibility of an agreement with Pisum is not excluded (letter to NACELI,December 31, 1866, P. 57). [In the present account, all citationsto MENDEL’Swritings refer to the page numbers in STERNand SHERWOOD (1966).] MENDELas a hybridist: In considering MENDEL’S contributions, the greatest weight must be placed on his own writing o n hybridization, which is unfortunately limited to two papers (1866 and 1870) and 10 letters to CARL NAGELI (1866-1873). T h e principal source of information is the Versuche (1966), which was the text of MENDEL’S public lectures of February 8 and March 8, 1865, to fellow members of the Brno Natural History Society. In MENDEL’S letter of April 18, 1867, to NAGELI,he says, I made every effort to verify, with other plants, the result obtained with Pisum . . . I attempted to inspire some control experiments, and for that reason discussedthe Pisum experiments at the meeting of the local society of naturalists. I encountered, was as to be expected, divided opinion . . . When, last year [ 18661 I was asked to publish my lecture in the proceedings of the society, I agreed to do SO, after having re-examined my records for the various years of experimentation, and not havingbeenable to find a source of error. The paper which was submitted to YOU is the unchanged reprint of the draft of the lecture mentioned; thus the brevity of the exposition, as is essentialfor a public lecture (p. 60). Therefore, while the Versuche is written in remarkably Perspectives clear German (STERNand SHERWOOD1966), the account is abbreviated and addressed to a general audience. We have no way of knowing what revisions MENDELmight have madehad he foreseen that every word and phrase in the paper would still be parsed and analyzed morethan125 years afterward.For (199 1, p. 5 16)readily admits example, DI TROCCHIO that his allegation that MENDEL’Smonohybrid experiments were “fictitious” is based almost exclusively on the occurrence of two “unexpected” words: eintheilung (“breaking up into several parts”), which appears in the third subheading of the Versuche (p. 5); and wesentlich (“essential, substantial”), which appears in the statement that “plants were used which differed in only one essential trait” (p. 17). Did MENDELhave an agenda to disprove descent with modification that led to his choice of Hieracium, with its constant hybrids, for his later experiments (CALLENDER1988)? T h e Darwinian theory waswell known by the time of MENDEL’Spresentation. The German translation of On the Origin of Species was published in 1863, and the monastery copy has marginalnotes in MENDEL’Shandwriting. InJanuary, 1965, at the monthly meeting of the Brno Natural History Society, A. MAKOWSKY,one of MENDEL’S friends, lectured on the theory of natural selection. MENDELgave the nexttwo lectures, and thushe could easily have focused on the evolutionary angle had he wished. However, the Versuche mentions evolution on only three occasions: on page2 in the phrase “the evolutionary history of organic forms,” on page 4 1 in the phrase “the evolutionary history of plants,” and on page 47 where MENDELcites GARTNER’Sview that “a species has fixed limits beyond which it cannot change” and says that this statement cannot be accepted unconditionally. Furthermore, a number of plant species other than Hieracium were chosen in making “every effort to verify, with other plants, the result obtained with Pisum” (MENDEL’Sletter to NAGELI, April 18,1867, P. 60). T h e reason MENDEL chose Hieracium is given in his 1870 paper: This genuspossessessuch an extraordinary profusion of distinct forms that no other genus of plants can compare with it (p. 51). MENDEL’S overriding interest was . . . the question whether and to what extent hybridization plays a part in the production of this wealth of forms (p. 5 1) knowing full well that . . . we may be led into erroneous conclusions if we take rules deduced from observation of certain other hybrids to be laws of hybridization,and try to apply them to Heiracium without further consideration (p. 52). At the beginning of his Pisum experiments MENDEL was certainly aware of the Linnean conceptof constant 247 hybrids and thought that they might be important exceptions tothe laws deducedfor Pisum. Inthe Versuche he remarked that there is . . . an essential dafference in those hybrids that remain constant in their progeny and propagate like pure strains (p. 41, emphasis his). He also understood that . . . this feature is of particular importanceto the evolutionary history of plants, because constant hybrids attain the status of new species (p. 41 , emphasis his). On the other hand, he had . . . proved experimentallythat in Pisum hybrids form d i e r ent kinds of germinal and pollen cells and that this is the reason for the variabilityof their offspring (p.4 1 , emphasis his). Far from providingthe constant hybrids that MENDEL was allegedly seeking, theexperiments with Hieracium, as recounted in the letters to NACELI,were one long chronicle of failure and frustration. On the other hand, there is no disputing that MENDEL was in the tradition of the plant hybridists, like KOLREUTERand GARTNER,whose work, among that of others, he cites in the Versuche. The question is whether he was so engrossed in this tradition that the process of heredity itself was either unrecognized or of little interest (OLBY1979; MONACHANand CORCOS 1990). OLBY(1 979,p. 67) claims that Mendel’s overridingconcern was with the role of hybrids in the genesis of new species . . . The laws of inheritance were only of concern to him in so far as they bore on his analysis of the evolutionary role of hybrids. It is certainly true that MENDEL’Smain interest was in hybrids. The answer to the question “What was MENDEL trying to discover?” is clearly given in the introductory remarks in the Versuche, inwhich MENDEL describes the experimental program necessary to discover a . . . generally applicable law of the formation and development of hybrids (p. 2) which he considered as alaw whose . . . significancefor the evolutionary history of organic forms must not be underestimated (p.2). On the other hand, in the very first sentence of the Versuche, MENDELexplains that the experiments were based on . . . artificial fertilization undertaken on ornamental plants to obtain new color variants (p. I), which seems also to imply a significant interest in heredity for its role in practical breeding. MENDEL also had little concern for the systematic status of his pea plants. He remarks that,in the opinion of experts, 248 and D. L. Hart1 most of the plants belong to thespecies Pisum sativum, but . . . the rank assigned to them in a classification system is completely immaterial to the experiments in question (p.5 ) . One will never know exactly what MENDELwas thinking, but one might reasonably have expected a less cavalier attitude toward species classification on the part of an authorwhose primary concern was the role of hybridization in the formation of newspecies. (MENDELwas not alone in regarding the distinction between species and varieties as purely arbitrary. The viewwas commonamong 19th century biologists, including DARWIN,and almost universal among the botanists. It was to cause MENDELgreat trouble after 1866 when he began making hybrids between what would now be regarded as distinct species. We are indebted to ERNST MAYR for pointing this out in a letter of December 17, 199 1, to DLH.) The Moravianconnection: If, as SANDLERand SANDLER (1 985) pointout, therewas no clear conceptual distinction between heredity and development, then how could MENDELhave been interested in heredity for its own sake? Even before MENDEL’Stime, there had been great interest in Moravia in the practical breeding of sheep, fruit trees, and vines, partly through the leadership of the naturalist, C . C. A N D R ~ (1 763-1 83 l), who in 1806, through the patronage of COUNTSALM-REIFFERSCHEID (1776-1 836), had organized in Brno the Royal and Imperial Moravian and Silesian Society for the Improvement of Agriculture, Natural Science and Knowledge of the Country (OREL and MATALOV;~1983). Manyof the monks of the monastery of St. Thomas were active in this society, including MENDEL’Spredecessor as abbot, F. C. NAPP (1 792-1 867), and MENDEL himself. NAPP had organized the Brno Natural History Society as one of the sections in thelargerorganizationuntil it become independent in 186 1. If MENDEL had a mentor in Brno, it was NAPP:he had supported the teaching of agriculture in thecontext of natural science, and MENDELattended these lectures in 1846; and he had MENDELsent to the university in Vienna in 18511853to study with, amongothers,theprominent plant physiologist F. UNGER and the physicistC. J. DOPPLER (of the DOPPLER effect). On the other hand, NAPP’S role in shaping MENDEL’Soutlook and research agenda is uncertain. What is clear is that NAPP,motivated by issues in practical breeding, was interested in heredity as a problem in itself. dn 1836 he attended a meeting of the Sheep Breeders Association and summarized the discussion of breeding methodsby noting that the crucial questions were: What is inherited? How is it inherited? (OREL 1984). Later, in 1840, ata meeting of agriculturalists, NAPP defended hybridization as a method of obtaining new varieties of fruit trees and drew attention to the element of chance in V.Orel this process (OREL 1983).That MENDEL himself was interested in practical breeding can hardly be doubted, since he chose to memorialize these interests in ceiling paintings on therenovated monastery reception room as well as on hisown tomb (MATALOV;~ 1983). MENDELeven ate thefruits of his pea breeding efforts: In 1859 I obtained a very fertile descendant with large, tasty,seedsfrom a firstgenerationhybrid.Since, in the following year,its progeny retained the desirable characteristics and were uniform, the variety was cultivated in our vegetable garden, and many plants were raised every year up to 1865 (MENDELletter of April 18, 1867 to NAGELI,p. 61). What did MENDELdiscover?If MENDELwas trying to discover a “generally applicable law of the formation and development of hybrids,” what did he actually discover? In the traditional view, MENDELdiscovered that hereditary traits are determined by cellular elements, now called genes, that exist in pairs, undergo segregation andindependent assortment, and persist unchanged through successive generations of hereditary transmission. A key passage in the Vers u c h that is relevant to this interpretation is as follows (p. 29ff): The difference of forms among the progeny of hybrids, as well as the ratios in which they are observed, find an adequate explanation in the principle [of segregation] just deduced. The simplest case is given by the series for one pair of differing traits. It is shown that this series is described by the expression: A A a a, in which A and a signify the forms with constant differing traits, and A a the form hybrid + + for both. The series contains four individuals in three different terms. In their production, pollen and germinal cells of form A and a participate, on theaverage,equallyin fertilization; therefore each form manifests itself twice, since four individualsare produced. Participating in fertilization are thus: Pollen cells A + A + a + a Germinal cells A +A +a +a It is entirely a matter of chance which of the two kinds of pollen combines with each single germinal cell. However, according to the laws of probability, in an average of many cases it will always happen that every pollen form A and a will unite equally often with every germinal-cellform A and a ; therefore, in fertilization, one of the two pollen cells A will meet a germinal cell A, the other a germinal cell a, and equally, onepollencell a will becomeassociatedwith a germinal cell A , and the othera. I’ollenzcllen A A a A a f Keirnzellen A a ! a The result of fertilization can be visualized by writing the designations for associated germinal and pollen cells in the form of fractions, pollen cells above the line, germinalcells Perspectives below. In the case under discussion one obtains A/A + A / a + a / A + ala In the first and fourth terms germinal and pollen cells are alike; therefore the products of their association must be constant, namely A and a; in the secondand third, however, a union of the two differing parental traits takes place again, therefore the forms arising from such fertilizations are absolutely identical with the hybrid from which theyderive. Thus, repeatedhybridization t a b s place. The striking phenomenon, that hybridsare able to produce, in addition to the two parental types, progeny that resemble themselvesis thus explained. Ala and a/A both give the same association Aa, since, as mentioned earlier, it makes no difference to the consequence of fertilization which of the two traits belongs to the pollen and which to the germinal cell. Therefore A/A + A/a + a / A a/a = A + 2 Aa + a This represents the average course of self-fertilization of hybrids when two differingtraits are associated in them.In individual flowers and individual plants, however, the ratio in which themembers of the series are formed maybe subject to not insignificant deviations. + In our opinion, this passage is strikingly perceptive and hardly betrays befuddlement or deep confusion as to whether the formative elements are paired in the plants and segregate in thereproductive cells. Although the passage does not use any of the words gene, genotype, phenotype, homozygous,heterozygous, or segregation, its meaning to modern geneticists is unmistakable. The only fault, which occurs on several occasions in the Versuche, is that the term trait (Merkmal) is used to mean either phenotype or allele, depending on the context, which indicates that the distinction may not always have been clear or entirely sharp in MENDEL’Sown mind. Particulate inheritance:At this point itis necessary to discuss several issues bearing on the level of MENDEL’S understanding of hisown work (OLBY1979; MEIJER 1983; MONACHAN and C o ~ c o s1990; DI TROCCHIO 1991). One issue is whether MENDEL thought of his “potentially formative elements (bildungsfuhigenElemente)”(Versuche, p. 43) as particles rather thanas fluids or emulsions (MEIJER1983; MONACHAN and CoRcos 1990). Nowhere in the Versuche is the physical nature of die Elemente discussed in enough detail to infer how MENDELmight have imagined them. On page 42, in the concluding remarks, MENDELrefers to “the material composition and arrangement of the elements . . . in the cell” (“in der materiellen Beschaffenheit undAnordnungderElemente. . . inderZelle”). This phrase would at least seem to imply that he was thinking in terms of some sort of material entities, but even this interpretation is disputed by KALMUS(1983), whodismisses it as “an afterthought” (p. 6 1)and arguesinstead that MENDEL must have been thinking of die Elemente in terms of nonmaterialistic scholastic metaphysics and invoking 249 the Aristotelian concept of the potential. But this opinion seems flatly contradicted by MENDEL’Sunselfconsciously materialistic statement that . . . the distinguishing traits of two plants can, after all, be caused only by differences in the composition and grouping their of theelementsexisting in dynamicinteractionin primordial cells (p. 43). It does not matter whether MENDELwas thinking in terms or particles or fluids, since he emphasized repeatedly the key point that differing elements emerge unchanged from theirassociation. For example,in the letter of April 18, 1867, to NAGELI,MENDELwrote, The course of development consists simply in this; that in each generation the two parental traits appear, separated and unchanged, andthere is nothing to indicatethat one of them has either inherited or taken over anything from the other (p. 62). (This passage also contains MENDEL’Sonly known use of the term inherited.) The use of A instead ofA A : MENDELroutinely used the symbol A in genetic formulas in which a modern geneticist would use AA, and this notation has been interpreted as meaning that MENDELdid not believe that hereditary elements occur in pairs (OLBY 1979; MONAGHAN and CORCOS1990). However,throughout most of the Versuche, MENDELused the symbols A and a in a very different sense than used in modern genetics with reference to genes. In his usage, A refers to a plant that breeds true for the dominant trait, and similarly with a for the true-breeding recessive. Occasionally he used the same symbols to refer to the hereditary determinants, as in the quotationabove from page 29ff, and in the context of this particular discussion it is quite clear that the expression A/A + A / a + a / A + a l a = A + 2 Aa + a summarizes the expected genetic constitutions of the progeny on theleft and gives their physical and breeding characteristics on the right. There are also other interpretations of MENDEL’Ssymbolism, including that of MEIJER (1983), who argues that MENDEL’Ssymbol A means “the potentialforcreating thedominant trait,” and hence the use of AA for the homozygote would be redundant, since the two A’s are logically equivalent. Lest we be too harsh in our anachronous criticism of MENDEL’Ssomewhat inconsistent use of symbols, it is worthwhile to bear in mind that modern Drosophila geneticists routinely use unpaired symbols when referring to homozygous recessives; for example, in referring to Drosophila strains, the symbol a1 means the genotype allal, and cn bw means the genotype cn bwlcn bw. Segregation in AA and aa genotypes: The segregation issue provides one of OLBY’S (1 979) principal arguments that Mendel was no Mendelian: V.Orel 250 and D. L. Hart1 [Mendel] did not conceive of pairs of elements in the cell representing and determiningthe pairs of contrasted characters. If he had this conception he would have allowed a separation between like membersof such pairs as well as between unlike members (OLBY1979, p. 66, emphasis his). T h e strongest evidence in the Versuche in support of OLBY’S view is the following passage: [The] differing elements [in hybrids] succeed in escaping from the enforced association only at the stage atwhich the reproductive cells develop. In the formation of these cells all elements present participatein completely free and uniform fashion, and only those that differ separate from each other (p. 43). FIELD 1985). However, by definition, alleles must be different: Allele . . . one of two or more alternate forms of a gene occupying the same locus on a particular chromosome . . . and differing fromother alleles of that locus . . . . (RIEGER,MICHAELIS and GREEN1968, p. 11); Allele . . . one of a series of possible alternative formsof a given gene . . , differing in DNA sequence . . . , (KING and STANSFIELD 1985, p. 14). Hence, MENDEL’Sview of segregation occurring only in the heterozygotes (i.e., with different alleles) could easily be defended as being completely consistent even with the modernuse of the term.Moreover, this usage provided MENDELwith the opportunity tosummarize in the following way what he clearly regarded as his main result: O n the other hand, the context of this passage clearly refers tohybrids that produce variable progeny. MENDEL never specifically addresses the question whether segregation occurs in homozygous genotypes, and we [Pea] hybrids form germinal and pollen cells that in their have noway of knowing how he might have responded composition correspond in equal numbers to all the constant forms resulting from the traits united through fertilization (p. if queried directly about the matter. MENDEL’S seem29, emphasis his). ing indifference to segregation in homozygotes was entirely consistent with his primary interestin hybrids This summary is the subject of further discussion and the principle that the hereditary determinants below. emerge unchanged after their association together in The P h a s e o h issue: In the Versuche MENDEL also hybrids. As ERNST MAYR has noted, “The homozycommented on his results with flower color in Phaseolus multijlorus, in which the F2 generation from an gotes, not being hybrids,simply did not interest him” original cross of white X crimson consisted of a whole (personal communicationto DLH, October 28, 199 1). range of colors from purple to pale violet and white, Also against OLBY’S argument is MENDEL’Sformula in theratio 30 coloredto 1 white, instead of the expected 3: 1. He then wrote, A / A A / a a / A a/a = A 2 Aa a + + + + + which clearly implies that the homozygous forms A and a each contain two hereditary determinants. In addition, MENDELwrites (p. 41), . . . it seems permissible to assume that the germcellsof those [plants] that remain constant are identical, and also like the primordialcell of the hybrid. T h e key question is whether the word identical (gleichartig) is intended to mean “identical in number” or “identical in type.” We presume that MENDEL meant identical in both senses, otherwise some qualification would have been included, which would imply that the germ cells from homozygotes must contain only one of each of the paired determinants, since this is the case in “the primordial cell of the hybrid.” In a wider sense, whether or not segregation may be said to occur in homozygous genotypes is largely a matter of semantics. In the contemporary mind segregation is often confused with the process of chromosome separation during meiosis, but MENDELknew nothing about chromosomes. Furthermore, in a precise technical sense, chromosomes undergo disjunction, not segregation. Segregation is a formal genetic phenomenon in which alleles are separated from one another and distributed into different germ cells (RIEGER, MICHAELISand GREEN 1968; KING and STANS- But thesepuzzlingphenomena,too,couldprobablybe explained by the law valid for Pisum if one might assume that in Ph. multzjlorus the colorofflowersandseeds is composed of two or more totally independent colors that behave individually exactly like any other constant trait in the plant. With blossom color A composed of independent traits A I + An . . . , which produce the overall impression of crimson coloration, then, through fertilization with the differing trait of white color a, hybrid associations Ala + Ana + . . . would have to be formed . . . (p. 35). + Hence, considering only A , and A2, the . . . terms of the [FPprogeny] seriescan enter into 9 different combinations, eachof which represents the designationfor another color: 1 AI A2 2 Ala AP 1 AP a 2 AI Ana 4 A l a Ana 2 Ana a 1 AI a 2 Ala l a a a The numbers preceding the individual combinations indicate how many plants of corresponding coloration belong to the series (p36). OLBY(1979) discusses this examplein some detail and wonders . . . why [Mendel] made no apology for putting both A I and AP with the same contrasted charactera . . . The chief rea- Perspectives 25 1 son for this obscurity was. . .that Mendel was thinking in terms of the white d o u r when he wrote down a . . . It may. of course. be objectedthatthe way Mendelset out his Phaseolw series [the matrix above] showsthat he was thinking of t w o gene loci for white, hencethegenotype u o . . .[However, the layout of the table] makes clcar the derivation of the c 1 a . w of offspring fromthe multiplication of terms andno more ( 0 t . w 1979. p. 6Off). As is clear from QLRY'S discussion, there is plenty of room for disagreement about MENDEL'S intentions in summarizing the Phaseolus situation in this manner. Although MENDEL undoubtedly associated the symbol u with the color white, he also clearly stated that the two or more colors are 'totally independent," that they "behave individually exactly like any other constant trait in the plant," and that 'hybrid associations Ala AM . . ." would be formed by fertili7ation with germ cells from a white plant. These comments, and particularly the latter formula. clearly suggest that he had independent factorsin mind, and that the u written as a partner for AI is different from the a written as a partner for An. MENDEL'S matrix and the symbol a u makes perfect sense if he were using positional notation; otherwise, consistency would require the white plants to be symbolized simply as a. At the risk of seeming Whiggish, we will point out herethat positional notation is commonly used in modern Drosophila genetics. although the wild-type alleles, rather than the mutant alleles. are designated For example, to a with the single symbol. namely modern Drosophila geneticist, the symbol+ + +/y w f clearly means the triple heterozygote for y. w , and/, without any ambiguity, and w is the double recombinant chromosome with the wild-type alleles ofy andf. We believe that it was this kind of positional notation that MENDEL had in mind when he wrote a a in his table of F? progeny in Phaseolus. The Notizblatt argument:A good deal of discussion hascentered on interpreting what appear to be genetic symbols in MENDEL'S handwriting found on a document called the MENDEL Kotizblatt (Figure 1). which hears theroughdraft of a letter on the overleaf containing material that dates the letter (though possibly not the putative genetic symbols) to about 1875, o r some seven years after MENDEL became abbot and two years after his last crossing experiments (RICHTER 1924). I t is not at all clear what the symbols in the Notizblatt refer to: results from I,ina+ia, Phaseolus, and Pisum have all been suggested (HEIMANS 1968). T h e Pisum suggestion comes from HEIMANS( I 968) and is based on the observation that the number of individuals in the class Win the Notizblatt (166)agrees with the total for white seed coat color in the trifactorial cross in the Vtrsuche (MENDEL, p. 21). T h e agreement could be coincidental, since the totals d o not agree (601 progeny recorded in the Notizblatt vs. 639 in the trifactorial cross). Whatever the case. the + I U P + +. + + L FIGUREI .--The ~IEWEI.Sotirhlarr.containing apprcnt KC netic s y ~ ~ h nin l s \ f F . w m . ' s llandwri~ing.dl14IO a1n-1~11875. Notizblatt suggests that MENDEL was playing with the data.apparentlytrying various wavs to groupthe phenotypes into classes. and he flirts briefly with a 7:3:2 ratio in the middle of the page(Figure 1). However, by the bottom of the page he has gotten to the ratio'/4:'/R:'/lfi:'/?:'/Ifi, which isa perfectly respectable Mendelian ratio found among the 147 theoretically possible ratios in the F? progeny of a dihybrid cross (HARI'L and MARUYAMA1968). I t should also be noted that 7:2:3 is quite close to 9:3:4, which is one of the conventional examples of a modified 9:3:3: 1. Nevertheless, much has been made of the 7:2:3 ratio. and OLRY (1979, p. 62) develops a model of what MENDEL might have been thinking when he wrote the markings and explains the model in a paragraph that OLRYimagines MENDEL might have written werethis the model that 1MmmLactu;dIv had in mind. However, MEIJER( 1 983) points out that OLRY'S model does not really explain the i:2:3 ratio anyway. These disagreements only serve to highlight the main problem with the Sotizblatt: it is an unpuh lished page of markings pertaining to unknown traits in an unidentified organism witten at an undetcrmined time and apparently of little importance to MENDEI. himself since he used the page as scrap for drafting a letterabout monastery business. (;iven these uncertainties, the Notizblatt is hardly the sort of thing to rely on in making inferences about MENDEL'S understanding of his work in Pisum. The issue of constant hybrids: In his argument 252 V.Orel and D. L. Hart1 that MENDEL was an opponent of the fundamental principle of descent with modification, CALLENDER (1988) also puts great emphasis on MENDEL’Sdiscussion of “constant” hybridsas evidence that he did not regard his findings as generally applicable to other plant species. Indeed, in what CALLENDER (1988, p. 56) regards as MENDEL’S“most important reference to constant hybrids,” MENDELwrote: We encounter an essentialdifference in those hybrids that remain constant in their progeny and propagate like pure highly fertile strains. Accordingto Gartner these include the hybrids Aquilegia atropurpurea-canadensis, Lauatera pseudolbia-thuringiaca, Geum urbano-riuale, and some Dianthus hybrids . . . The correctness of these observations is vouched for by the eminent observers and cannot be doubted (p.41). However, later in the text of the Versuche, MENDEL also wrote: Finally, the experiments performedby Kolreuter, Gartner, and others on transformation of onespecies into another by artijicial fertilization deserves special mention . . . Gartner himselfhas carried out 30 experiments ofthiskind with plants from genera Aquilegia, Dianthus, Geum, Lauatera, Lychnis, Malua, Nicotiana, and Oenothera . . . If one may assume that the development of forms proceeded in these experiments in a manner similar to that forPisum, then the entire process of transformation w‘ould havea rather simple explanation (p.44). It is importantto emphasize that, in this passage, MENDELpointedly and specifically includes all of the genera referred to earlier as containing constant hybrids as amongthose genera in whichone may assume that the laws for Pisum hold. While MENDELmay have been uncertain about the universal applicability of the laws for Pisum, particularly with regard to species with constant hybrids, he had already convinced himself that they were probably valid at least for all variable hybrids, since he asserted: Whethervariablehybridsof other plantspeciesshow complete agreementin behavior also remains to be decided experimentally; one might assume, however, that no basic difference couldexist in important matters sinceunity in the plan of development of organic life is beyond doubt (p. 43, emphasis his). What did MENDELthink he discovered?Whatever MENDELthought he had discovered, hewas certainly under the impression that it was important. In his letter of April 18, 1867, to NACELIhe says, I knew that the results I obtained werenot easily compatible with our contemporaryscientific knowledge, andthat under the circumstances publication of one such isolated experiment was doubly dangerous; dangerous for the experimenter and for the cause he represented (p.60). In a paper containingas much dataand interpretation as the Versuche, how should one decide what the author regardedas the main message? In our opinion, the key is found in the fact thatthe Versuche was written for oral presentation, and in an oral presentation the principal technique for emphasis is repetition. Thus, in order todiscern what MENDELregarded as the main message, one might examine the Versuche in order to identify any particular ideas or passages that are repeated. We have examined the document with this goal in mind, and have identified one idea that is expressed repeatedly in almost identical language. One version of the idea is as follows: . . . pea hybrids form germinal and pollen cells that in their compositioncorrespond in equalnumbers to all the constant forms resulting from the combination of traits united through fertilization (p. 29, emphasis MENDEL’S). This statement, or close variants of it, is repeated no fewer than six times in the Versuche, on pages 24, 29, 32, twice on page 43, and 44. Furthermore, since MENDEL refersto this formulation as the “law of combination of differingtraitsaccordingto which hybrid development proceeds” (p. 32), we may infer that he considered this statement as summarizing the “generally applicable law of the formation and development of hybrids” (p.2),the elucidation of which he clearly regarded as his main goal of his experiments. That MENDELregarded this law as widely applicable is supported by his statement that it . . remains more than probable that a factor that so far has received little attention is involved in the variability of cultivated plants. . . [Our]cultivated plants,with few exceptions, are members of difjferenthybridseries whose developis altered and retarded by frequent ment along regular lines intraspecific crosses (p. 37ff, emphasis his). T h e context of this paragraph clearly points to segregation as “the factor that so far has received little attention.” MENDEL’Sown one-sentence summary of what he thought he discovered is remarkably general and concise. It containsboth the lawsof segregation and independent assortment in a form that is generally applicable to hybrids of any numberofunlinked genes. Even amodern geneticist would be hard pressed to drafta sentenceof comparable clarity without using terminology unavailable to MENDEL. Conclusions: Our review of the issues and evidence regarding MENDEL as a Mendelian leads us to the following conclusions. MENDELshould certainly be regarded as a hybridist. He was in the hybridist tradition,and this is apparently how heregarded himself. However, his interest in hybridization didnot blind him tothe recognition of heredity as a process distinct from evolution. His outlook was conditioned by being in Brno,where there was aparticularinterest in the results of artificial fertilization for the improvement 253 Perspectives of sheep, fruit trees, and vines, in which colleagues of MENDEL,such as ABBOTNAPP,were leading participants, and conditioned also by MENDEL’Sown admitted interest in practical breeding as well as the colorMENation of ornamental flowers. On the other hand, DEL’S hybridist tradition did result inhis failure to emphasize the genetic composition of the constant (homozygous)forms, although the symbolism he used in the Versuche A/A + A / a + a / A + a/a = A + 2 Aa + a implies to us that he was quite aware that theconstant forms must contain paired hereditary determinants. Nowhere did MENDELstipulate that thehereditary determinants are particulate, as opposed to fluid, vapor, colloid, gel, plasma, or whatever. He did, however, assume that they are material entities, rather than metaphysical “potentials,” and asserted that the distinguishing traits of plants are caused only by differences in the composition and grouping of these hereditary elements. MENDELclearly considered segregation as a phenomenon that characterizes the hybrids. On the other hand, the issue whether segregation of genes, as abstract entities, canbesaid to occur inhomozygous genotypes is largely a matter of semanticsand can be debated even today. For MENDEL,the clear cut segregation in heterozygotes carried the critical implication that the hereditary elements remain unchanged by their association together in heterozygous genotypes. The laws of inheritance for Pisum were regarded by MENDELas quite generally applicable.He proposed explicitly that they would applyto all forms of variable (segregating) hybrids, and he also suggestedthat they might very well explain why genera that include constant (nonsegregating) hybridscan be transformed into new forms by meansof artificial fertilization. According to MENDEL’S ownwords,hisstudiesof Hieracium and otherspecies wereundertaken in order to “verify, with other plants, the result obtained with Pisum” (MENDEL’Sletter to NAGELI of April 18, 1867, p. 60). The key point of MENDEL’Sdiscovery is contained in a sentence that he repeated with minor variations no less than six times in the Versuche: . . . pea hybrids form germinal and pollen cells that in their compositioncorrespond in equalnumbers to all the constant forms resulting from the combination of traits united through fertilization (p. 29, emphasis his). This is the kind of “law of the formation and development ofhybrids” (p. 2) that he hadset out to discover, it is a remarkably concise statement of what he actually did discover, and it certainly represents the distillation of what he thought he discovered. We conclude that MENDEL understood very clearly what his experiments meant for heredity. He deserves, not only the eponymous credit for Mendelism, but also the historical credit and a considerable measure of respect and admiration for his remarkable insights. We are very grateful to ERNSTMAYRfor his advice, encouragement, and numerous helpful letters throughout the course of this study, and to MEL GREEN,ELENALOZOVSKAYA, and DANKRANE for their comments and suggestions. LITERATURE C I T E D BOWLER, P. J., 1989 The Mendelian Revolution.The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore. L. A., 1988 Gregor Mendel: an opponent of descent CALLENDER, with modification. Hist. Sci. 2 6 41-75. DI TROCCHIO, F., 199 1 Mendel’s experiments: a reinterpretation. J. Hist. Biol. 24: 485-519. DOBZHANSKY, T., 1967 Looking back at Mendel’s discovery. Science 1 5 6 1588-1589. EDWARDS, A. W. F., 1986 Are Mendel’s results really too close? Biol. Rev. 61: 295-312. FISHER,R. A., 1936 Has Mendel’s work been rediscovered? Ann. Sci. 1: 115-137. HARTL,D. L., and T. MARUYAMA, 1968 Phenogram enumeration: the number of genotype-phenotype correspondences in genetic systems.J. Theor. Biol. 2 0 129-163. HEIMANS, J., 1968 Ein Notizblatt aus dem Nachlass Gregor Mendel mit Analysen eines seiner Kreuzungsversuche. Folia Mendeliana 4: 5-36. KALMUS, H., 1983 The scholastic origins ofMendel’s concepts. Hist. Sci. 21: 61-83. KING,R. C.,and W. D. STANSFIELD, 1985 A Dictionary ofcenetics. Oxford University Press, New York. MATALOVA,A., 1983 Mendel’spersonality-still an enigma? pp. 299-308 in Gregor Mendel andthe Foundation of Genetics, edited by V. OREL andA. MATALOVA.Mendelianum of the Moravian Museum, Brno, Czechoslovakia. MEIJER,0.G., 1983 The essence of Mendel’s discovery, pp. 123172 in Gregor Mendel and the Foundation of Genetics, edited by V. OREL andA.MATALOVA.Mendelianum of the Moravian Museum, Brno, Czechoslovakia. MONAGHAN, F. V., and A. F. CORCOS,1990 The real objective of Mendel’s paper. Biol. Philos. 5 267-292. OLBY,R., 1979 Mendel, no Mendelian? Hist. Sci. 17: 53-72. OREL,V., 1983 Mendel’s achievements in the context of the cultural pecularities of Moravia, pp. 23-46 in Gregor Mendel and the Foundation of Genetics, edited by V. OREL and A. MATALOVA.Mendelianum of the Moravian Museum, Brno, Czechoslovakia. OREL,V., 1984 Mendel. Oxford University Press, Oxford. OREL,V., and A. MATALOVA(Editors), 1983 GregorMendeland the Foundation of Genetics. Mendelianum of the Moravian Museum, Brno, Czechoslovakia RICHTER,O., 1924 Ein kleiner Beitrag zur Biographie P. Gregor Mendel. Festschrift der Technischen Hochschule in Brunn 7: 130-139. RIEGER,R., A. MICHAELISand M. M. GREEN,1968 A Glossary of Genetics and Cytogenetics. Springer-Verlag, New York. SANDLER, I., and L. SANDLER, 1985 A conceptual ambiguity that contributed to the neglect of Mendel’s paper. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 7: 3-70. STERN,C., and E. R. SHERWOOD, 1966 TheOrigin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco. WRIGHT,S., 1966 Mendel’s ratios, pp. 173-175 in TheOrzgin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book, edited by C. STERNand E. R. SHERWOOD. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco.
© Copyright 2024