The Methodology of Analytic Philosophy: Intuitions, Concepts, and Conceptual Analysis Abstract: In this essay I defend intuitions and conceptual analysis as being crucial to a scientific analytic linguistic philosophy. This essay recognizes a distinction between world-view intuitions and linguistic intuitions as kinds of beliefs that motivate conceptual analyses. I argue that a theory cannot be constructed solely out of unbiased and neutral world-view intuitions, so that the analytic philosopher must provide a theory with hypotheses and examples that provide reasons to believe that a given world-view is true. The mediate philosophical theory that occurs between 'world-view intuitions' (e.g. the acceptance or non-acceptance of evolution theory, naturalism, possible-worlds realism, empiricism, theism, atheism) and 'linguistic intuitions' (involving beliefs about the use of particular concepts) is subject to debate as being true or false. The question about whose intuitions and what theory is to be believed will be based on the strength of a philosopher's argument, its clarity, and its intuitive plausibility. The question of 'what is proper philosophical methodology?' has become the subject of lively debate over the past three decades. While there is a long-running historical debate about methodology between rationalists and empiricists, there has recently been a more focused debate about the relevance of philosophical intuitions and the methodology of conceptual analysis. In this essay I defend the use of intuitions and conceptual analysis as being crucial to a scientific analytic linguistic philosophy. In doing so I will (1) characterize the status of intuitions and the explanatory strategy of -2conceptual analysis, (2) discuss what 'analytic philosophy' is, (3) defend the use of 'abductive arguments,' (4) clarify some assumptions about ontology and metaphysics, (5) define what a 'concept' is, (6) recognize six kinds of concepts that are frequently discussed in philosophy and psychology, (7) survey the kinds of concepts that are appropriate for analysis, including examples: 'justification,' 'relevant,' 'aesthetic experience,' 'axiom,' and 'analytic sentence,' and (8) defend the use of intuitions as a source of evidence for conceptual analysis. I. What are Intuitions? Jaakko Hintikka (1999, p. 127) credits Noam Chomsky as being a major source of contemporary talk about 'linguistic intuitions.' Intuitions came into fashion as a consequence of the popularity of Noam Chomsky's linguistics and its methodology. According to a widespread conception, generative linguists like Chomsky were accounting for competent speakers' intuitions of grammaticality by devising a grammar... that are intuitively accepted by these speakers. This kind of methodology was made attractive by the tremendous perceived success of Chomsky's theories in the 1960's and 1970's. For Chomsky the grammaticality of sentences is determined from the data of individual conceptual intuitions. These intuitions allowed construction of a set of (de facto) generative rules that produce all and only strings as 'grammatical.' The use of 'intuitions' gradually followed into analytic philosophy. What is an intuition? Charles Parsons (1995) defines an 'intuition' as what a person takes to be true at the outset of an inquiry, or as a matter of common sense (p. 59). -3David Lewis (1983), Peter van Inwagen (1997) and others similarly define an intuition as a kind of belief, or an opinion. Intuitions have been characterized as spontaneous mental judgments (Goldman & Prust, 1998). An intuition is a belief that we are pre-theoretically committed to, are inclined to believe, or seems intrinsically plausible. It is a report of 'what we would say' if asked our gut-level opinion about the correct answer to a given question. An intuitive belief can be a 'seems to be the case' and unreflectively tentative; or alternatively an intuitive belief can be strongly-held (but not infallible). On the view defended here, what distinguishes philosophical methodology from the physical sciences is its reliance on personal intuitions. Intuitions are the starting point for the development of a philosophical theory. Intuitions provide the data to be explained (and scrutinized) by a philosophical theory. The role of intuitional evidence in philosophy is analogous to the role of perceptual evidence in science. Our senses bring us perceptual evidence, while philosophical arguments bring us evidence from existing (bur changeable) world-view intuitions. We also have existing linguistic intuitions that express beliefs about the application and use of certain concepts. Both 'world-view intuitions' and 'linguistic intuitions' play a role in conceptual analyses. World-view intuitions are a person's (pre-theoretic) beliefs about the overall character of a phenomenon (or domain) being discussed. In contemporary analytic philosophy there are vast differences in world-view intuitions (e.g. realism or antirealism) about the subject matter of metaethics, aesthetics, the nature of mathematics and the practice of philosophy itself. The world-view intuitions characterizing a philosopher's overall viewpoint and interests are found in the preface, introduction, and -4abstracts of their published works. Within these world-views it is stated (1) what philosophical questions are important and require answers, (2) what distinctions and associated concepts are useful, and (3) the viewpoint to be articulated and defended. Among philosophers and laypersons the acceptance (or non-acceptance) of scientific evolution theory, rationalism, empiricism, idealism, logical positivism, naturalism, possible-worlds realism, theism, and atheism are all strong unifying world-views. Linguistic intuitions are narrower in scope and are about the proper application and use of particular concepts. Linguistic intuitions are pre-theoretical beliefs about sentence and concept use. They are judgments made on the basis of conceptual understanding and competence. Conceptual analyses using linguistic intuitions are the attempt to describe our linguistic practices and intentions and interpret various natural language uses of sentences and words. Most times our conceptual beliefs are implicit and rarely considered. However when philosophical and conceptual questions are made explicit, one's pre-theoretical intuitions may be conflicting or puzzling. Similarly there can be interesting philosophical questions that one has never explicitly thought about and one's answers to those questions may be unsuitably vague or confused. With conceptual analysis a philosopher tries to make explicit a reader's linguistic and world-view beliefs. The Explanatory Strategy of Conceptual Analysis Conceptual analysis is a practice that borders on the disciplines of philosophy, social science, linguistics, cognitive science and psychology. A scientifically-inclined linguistic philosophy seeks to provide theories with evidence obtained from both natural and artificial languages. These philosophical theories (systems of belief) are an -5intermediate result between how an individual interprets the world (as a world-view) and one's beliefs about the ordinary use of linguistic terms (and associated concepts). A conceptual analysis is the practice of analyzing terms (e.g. knowledge, justification, truth, evidence, relevance, art, beauty) by exploring the normal uses of terms and sentences and the intentions behind them that give a concept a significance (or meaning, intelligibility) in a context. The ordinary use of concepts in a normal context is the best guide for what a word designates and for forming their explicit definition. Having a concept makes one disposed to have beliefs (or intuitions) about the correct application of the concept in various cases. Individual conceptual analyses (within an associated theoretical network) can assist in the development of a set of true world-view beliefs about knowledge, ethical utterances, aesthetic judgments, mathematical assertions, counter-factual assertions, and so on. A philosopher's interest should be in developing a lay reader's conceptual and linguistic competence that allows for a better understanding of a natural world that includes the beliefs, values, desires, and intentions of persons in it.1 1 The ideal of communicating (and participating) in any way with laypersons is found repugnant by many philosophers. Herman Cappelen (2012, p. 20) embraces the opinions of philosophical specialists and experts and against an ordinary language conceptual analysis saying that "It is unlikely in the extreme that an 'intuition-expert' with minimal training in linguistics, semantics and philosophy of language can make constructive contributions to these debates. Constructive methodological reflections typically arise from inside the field and require deep understanding of specific subject matters." -6Who is best suited to lead a conceptual analysis? Not surprisingly conceptual analysis is best led by analytic philosophers who have thought long and hard about certain questions related to the ordinary use of the concept. Philosophers tend to have an explicit (or implicit) systematic hypothesis/theory for how words are used and how beliefs and knowledge are obtained. Alvin Goldman (2007) argues that the best way to understand one's personal psychological conception of a given concept is to contrast it to those conceptions found in analyses led by experts. Goldman observes that conceptanalyzing philosophers seek the intuitions of others as well as their own. A practitioner must be cautious about whether the proper use and applicability of a given concept in a hypothetical situation is the same for all people, but it must be assumed that there is a strong degree of similarity. We systemize our intuitions and test them against other intuitions. A conceptual investigation is a proto-scientific, quasi-experimental enterprise, where the aim is to reveal the contents of category-representing states as a starting point for seeking a derivative public concept (Goldman, pp. 17-20). A familiar form of 'conceptual analysis' is as follows: Describe one's own and other people's intuitions of whether or not a concept x or the word x applies to a case (real or imagined). A conceptual analysis attempts to develop (and test) a theory of x by participatory surveys and thought experiments. For example, if I'm a speaker of English and familiar with the concept of 'know,' then I have (to a large extent) mastered the use of 'know' and am capable of recognizing some situations as suitable for making a claim to know. With respect to the concepts of truth and knowledge, most persons judge (a) as being semantically well-formed but (b) is semantically ill-formed: -7(a) I thought Sue was ill, but it turned out that she wasn't. (b) I knew Sue was ill, but it turned out that she wasn't. Pre-theoretical beliefs about the semantics and proper use of 'know' are applied to various epistemic situations and possibilities. This thought experiment about the concept of 'knowledge' shows that it is widely-assumed that in order to know a proposition this implies the proposition is true. Our linguistic intuitions inform us of the ungrammaticality or semantic inconsistency of b. While there is often the attempt to be unbiased among philosophers using conceptual analyses seeking to identify the content of concepts in order to advance (true) theories of phenomena, there is a major complication. This complication is that conceptual analyses are always accompanied by the world-view intuitions of the analyzer. Every philosopher and every lay person have implicit and explicit worldviews. World-view intuitions affect how one understands the function and proper application of concepts and the underlying meaning of sentences when expressed in a context. In effect, a substantive analytic theory is an intermediate result between how an individual interprets the world and one's beliefs about the ordinary use of linguistic terms and sentences. Personal intuitions can differ. Intuitive beliefs about the nature of the world and use of concepts that are immediate, unreasoned, and non-inferential, shouldn't be expected to be reliable (or truth-connecting) as the foundations for a true theory. Intuitions are not indubitable. We are influenced by our social environment. Because a theory cannot be built solely out of a series of unbiased and neutral world-view intuitions, the analytic theorist must support one's world-view with hypotheses and examples that -8provide reasons to believe that a given world-view is true. In a sense, such theories are self-affirming. But an analytic exposition can be even-handed without persuading like an advertising campaign or highly partisan politics. II. The Characteristics of Analytic Philosophy Before discussing how intuitions function in conceptual analyses in determining the content of a concept, let us first consider what 'analytic philosophy' is. Analytic philosophy is a method of doing philosophy that is wider than the practice of conceptual analysis. The ancient Greeks were the early originators of analytic philosophy. Plato and Aristotle strove to define 'knowledge' and 'virtue.' But what is this analytic tradition? Hans-Johann Glock (2008) recently sought to define what 'analytic philosophy' is by examining its history. He found that analytic philosophy is best explained with a historical and 'family resemblance' approach (p. 223). The tradition is held together by a network of influence and communication. The concept of analytic philosophy is best understood as a set of loose identifying principles. Rather than describe the details of Glock's conclusions, I'm going to suggest that the following list contains the primary characteristics of what 'analytic philosophy' is (or should be): (1) Analytic philosophy has a critical scientific ethos. It is secular, not following religious authority, (2) Analytic philosophy describes, classifies, clarifies, interprets and to some extent formalizes its content. Analytic philosophy pays attention to arguments, explanations, and the reasons used to defend a belief. Speculative possibilities cannot be offered without cogent reasons, (3) Analytic philosophy is written with a respect for clarity and rigor. (4) The problems and answers offered by an analytic -9philosopher need not directly respond to traditional philosophical questions. New questions and problems may be presented. (5) Analytic philosophy oftentimes features a linguistic emphasis (e.g. logical positivism, ordinary language philosophy, and conceptual analysis). (6) Analytic philosophy should answer substantive questions and eliminate vagueness and incompatibilities among our ordinary thoughts, and (7) Analytic philosophy should strive to be accessible and relevant to non-philosophers. III. Argumentative Methodology Historically, the favored argumentative form of analytic philosophers has been that of deduction. A deductive argument consists of reasons expressed as premises in an argument that entails a conclusion using the standard rules of deductive inference. The premises should be true or plausible to someone who might not already accept the conclusion of the argument in question. With the possibility of finding agreed-on (and true) premises, the goal of a deductive argument is to prove the necessary truth of a conclusion. Russell and Quine strongly believed that philosophers should paraphrase sentences into a perspicuous logical language in order to deductively resolve pertinent philosophical paradoxes. But in philosophical practice it is often found that it is difficult to find agreement on a particular set of premises and to state premises using informative, non-technical, and non-idiosyncratic concepts. Everyday deductions using ordinary vocabulary (e.g. that 'Socrates is mortal' given that he is a man, and all men are mortal) are easy and transparent. But when it comes to complex philosophical questions a deductive argument -10often fails to produce an argument that is consensually accepted as sound. The form of a deductive argument is not often disputed (as invalid) because most philosophers are capable of presenting valid deductive arguments. Instead the premises are in dispute. A primary benefit of a deductive argument is that it routinely leads to the valuable identification of premise(s) that are in dispute. This is where arguments about truth of certain premises and the adequacy of concepts can be debated. Attention is given to whether the premises are true and whether the concepts contained in the premises can be expected to be fruitful in resolving a question. Deductive logic is best viewed as a tool in the practice of philosophy, but not as its standard or required methodology.2 In actual philosophical practice, analytic arguments include the frequent use of abductive inferences. 'Abduction' is defined as 'an inference to best explanation.' This contrasts to deductive modes of inference and standard inductive inferences. A comparison between deductive arguments, causal inductive inferences, statistical inductive arguments, and abductive inferences is illustrated with four examples: a) Deductive argument: (1) Every dog has sharp teeth, (2) Shaggy is a dog. (3) Therefore, Shaggy has sharp teeth. If the premises are true, then the conclusion cannot be false. b) Inductive inference (causal): If a dog bites me and penetrates my flesh, then I will bleed. 2 Williamson (2007) vigorously disagrees and maintains that philosophers should make greater use of deductive methods, not less. -11c) Inductive argument (statistical): (1) 99% of the people living in Springfield own a dog, (2) Jones lives in Springfield. (3) Therefore, it is likely that Jones owns a dog. d) Abductive inductive inference: (1) Smith sees a line of small muddy footprints across the kitchen floor from near the back door. (2) Smith has a young son and owns a dog Shaggy. (3) It is raining outside. (4) Smith infers that his son must have recently let Shaggy inside from the rain. Philosophers and psychologists tend to agree that abductive inference-to-bestexplanation reasoning is frequently employed in everyday reasoning. Another example of abductive (i.e. best-explanation) reasoning is the following: Imagine that you are walking down a city street in Boston in early spring and you overhear a woman on a cell phone saying 'I'm not going to shovel it because it is going to melt in three days.' One abductively infers the 'it' in her conversation designates 'snow' (with a background knowledge context of a recent snowfall and an expected spring warming). Not only is abduction used in everyday situations such as this, it is also used by professionals. Medical doctors often initially diagnose a patient's specific ailment as a best-explanation inferential hypothesis based upon their symptoms. In the judicial system, lawyers, judges, and juries typically rely on inductive evidence and make best-explanation inferences to decide whether a person is innocent or guilty. Conceptual analysis centers upon the evaluation of competing philosophical theories using best-explanation inferences. Analytic philosophy should be viewed as a social science with some techniques being similar to linguistics. Participants are asked to -12critically assess their linguistic and world-view intuitions (that are subject to change and clarification). Analyses will often include functional explanations and hypotheses about how language is used and the intentions of particular users. Functional explanations provide a theory of a person's reasons, assumptions, and goals for making an assertion. IV. Metaphysics Metaphysics and more particularly ontology is the discipline within philosophy that is concerned with the question 'what exists?' The term 'metaphysics' originates with the categorization of the miscellaneous writings of Aristotle where he considers the notion of being and substance, the first causes (or principles) of things, the notions of one and many, the problem of change, and the existence of mathematical objects. In modern times, in arguing what categories there are, and how they are related to one another, the practitioners of metaphysics often understand this discipline as concerned with the fundamental structure of reality as a whole. Metaphysics reached prominence as a highly speculative brand of philosophy as practiced by Leibniz (1646-1716) and Spinoza (16321677) in the seventeenth century. Hume (1711-1776) and the logical positivists of the early twentieth century became the most prominent critics of metaphysical theories that were idiosyncratic and without ties to any possible verification. In recent times, metaphysics has found both resurgence and criticism about its epistemic merit. Quine (1908-2000) was skeptical of the pretensions of realist metaphysics. Kripke in Naming and Necessity (1980) resuscitated metaphysics using the concepts of identity, necessity, a priori and a posteriori knowledge, and essential de re properties. -13Recently criticisms of the discipline of ontology have been voiced by numerous authors (e.g. Chalmers et. al. 2009). There is a suspicion that many metaphysical debates are mere pseudo-disputes that arise from attempts to respond to defective, unanswerable questions. For example, with respect to questions about what there is, and the principles of identity for persistent objects, there is skepticism whether such potential answers are truth-evaluable. In this essay I am skeptical of metaphysics and especially the epistemic claim that there are a priori truths. On the view here, analytic philosophy is best served by avoiding the excessive use of the concepts of 'thing,' 'universal,' 'particular,' 'object,' 'individual,' 'property,' 'possible world,' 'meaning,' 'rationality,' 'fact,' 'norm,' 'speech act' and an alleged distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge. If we can ask philosophically-interesting questions and avoid the excessive use of these loaded concepts when explaining the semantics and pragmatics of assertions in ordinary epistemic contexts, then philosophy will be in better position to inform critical inquirers. V. What Exists? What is a Concept? But even with a tentative and explicit rejection of some of the pretensions of metaphysics, the question still remains, in a general form, 'what exists?' A reply by a number of contemporary philosophers is that the question of 'what exists' is asked and answered relative to specialized disciplines. The astronomer asks whether there exist 'black holes?' The biologist asks what kinds of 'antibodies' exist? Archaeologists ask whether the lost city of El Dorado exists? The ordinary sense of 'existence' is contextrelative according to an inquirer's interests. When evaluating the truth of existence claims, one normally presumes a category (or kind) of entity that is being discussed. -14Although realist metaphysicians ask 'what exists?' and 'what are the fundamental existents?' assuming that there are a priori true answers, it is doubtful that there are any absolute answers to these generic questions. Instead it can be suggested that the concept of 'existence' is a 'group resemblance concept' having cluster senses. What 'exists' is postulated by the different physical sciences (e.g. physics, chemistry, geology, etc.), mathematics, social sciences, literary fiction, ordinary pragmatic stipulations, and so on. Quine and Carnap maintained that ontological issues are ultimately settled by pragmatic considerations, depending on various interests and purposes. With this anti-realist approach, it can be assumed that there is no true metaphysics about what 'really exists.' Materialism But with regard to what is the fundamental existent, we can hypothesize that physical (or material) entities are the primary existent from which all other entities are composed of. Materialism (or physicalism) is the doctrine that only material entities exist, and that any other entities are constituted as physical entities. According to Stoljar (2010, p. 2) the materialist position has become "something like a consensus position within analytic philosophy in the 1960's and has remained so, or very nearly so ever since. Philosophers such as Quine, Smart, Lewis, Armstrong, and many others are all materialists." On a world-view level, the answer to 'what exists' is answered here on the foundations of 'materialism' and 'a theory of concepts.' Concepts A 'concept' is understood as a functional physical entity that is found in the mental systems of sentient creatures (and perhaps in artificial intelligence devices) that in -15humans can be expressed by words and sentences. This definition of a 'concept' as being a mental particular is accepted by many contemporary psychologists and cognitive scientists (e.g. including Laurence and Margolis, 1999, p. 8). Concepts as the subject of 'conceptual' analyses are not just beliefs; they have a different form of existence and a different function than beliefs. To possess a concept is to have a capacity for having beliefs about the applicability of a concept in certain contexts. Concepts are subpropositional mental representations. We hold mental representations of categories with associated thoughts (or tacit beliefs) about entities that these words represent. Concepts function to categorize entities. For example, the non-corporal existence of a 'triangle' is physically instantiated (i.e. encoded) as a concept in humans by its standard definition as 'a plane figure with three-sides and three angles.' The explicit definition of the content of a given concept is the same across individuals to the extent that individuals have similar (or identical) characteristic properties in mind for items that fall under that concept or where there is substantial agreement of what constitutes the definiens of a definiendum.3 The practice of a critical self-examination and inter-subjective comparison of linguistic concepts is part of the reflective participation in traditional philosophic 3 This materialist-functional analysis of a 'concept' competes with the semantic view of concepts. On this traditional semantic view, concepts and words refer to 'things' typically independent of persons. The meaning of a word (or concept) is what it denotes, refers to, 'picks out,' or names. Concepts are the constituents of thought where words express concepts, and two words express the same concept if and only if they are semantically complete and synonymous. This dominant semantic view is challenged here. -16discourse. Being critical of one's own and others' intuitions can help to resolve certain questions and puzzles. Rejecting or modifying theses in the face of convincing examples and counter-examples is a characteristic of philosophic argumentation.4 Introspection of one's intuitions as well as interactive questions concerning others' thoughts expressed in a language are certainly not sense experiences, nor are such reflections independent of sense experience. The measurement of intentions, meanings, and references of speakers lends philosophy to being categorized as a social science, and not an 'armchair' pursuit. VI. Six Kinds of Concepts We now turn to the notion of what kinds of 'concepts' there are. As stated, for a human to possess a concept is to have a capacity for having beliefs about the applicability of the concept in certain contexts. A major scientific goal in psychology is to understand what kind of mental representations there are. Let us pursue this goal by surveying the kinds of concepts discussed among physical scientists, social scientists, philosophers, psychologists, mathematicians, and persons using ordinary language.5 4 Williamson (2007) in contrast, condemns this methodology of examining intuitions as the 'error of psychologizing the data' because philosophical questions are not typically psychological questions. How can we use psychological data such as intuitions (about what we believe) to answer questions that aren't psychological? Williamson says that philosophical methodology should be rid of its internalist preconceptions (p. 5). 5 The so-called 'classic theory' or 'standard view' of concepts holds that every concept has some necessary and sufficient conditions for its correct application and that philosophers seek analytic 'conceptual truths' in a bi-conditional form. I don't assume -17In reviewing recent literature involving the notion of 'concepts' there seems to be distinctions (although not a consensus agreement) between six kinds of concepts: natural kind concepts, group resemblance concepts, fixed definiens concepts, fictional entity concepts, definite description concepts, and proper name concepts. Below is a rudimentary summary of the intuitions and speaker intentions that frame these categories. (1) Natural kind concepts are about natural kind entities. A natural kind entity is thought to have intrinsic properties (and/or extrinsic properties) with an independent nature. Water is a natural kind. Natural kinds need not be physical nor found in nature. For example, the concept of 'knowledge' can be analyzed as a natural kind. Also for example, synthetic plastics (not found in nature) can be artificially created by scientists to form homeostatic natural kinds. (2) Group resemblance concepts are about entities (or things) that have a superficial resemblance or loose similarity, but that may not have a set of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions that defines the entity as a kind. These nouns, predicates, verbs, and adjectives are sometimes called 'cluster concepts.' These concepts may be subject to precise descriptive characterizations or precise disjunctive definitions. Examples of group resemblance terms include this, and neither do most contemporary philosophers. There are two other alternative viewpoints that are also rejected here: 1) conceptual analysis is the decomposition of complex concepts into simpler concepts (e.g. G.E. Moore) and 2) conceptual analysis is the hierarchal regressive axiomatic enterprise of determining what concepts fall under other broader basic concepts (e.g. Aristotle). -18'game,' 'chair,' 'statue,' 'virtue,' 'poverty,' 'toothpaste,' 'sports bar,' 'rude,' 'generous,' 'democracy,' and 'art.' (3) Fixed definiens concepts have two characteristics that make up their uniqueness: (a) a fixed definiens concept is a term that is stipulatively defined to unequivocally identify any item(s) that fall under its definition, and (b) a fixed definiens concept is stable and not subject to alteration, without creating a new concept. Examples of fixed definiens concepts occur in (a) kinship/gender vocabularies (e.g. a 'bachelor' is an unmarried male; a 'vixen' is a female fox), (b) the deductive sciences (e.g. a 'valid deductive argument' is an argument where if the premises are true, it is impossible for the conclusion to be false; the 'successor' of ordinal number x is the next ordinal number, or x +1)6, (c) grammatical concepts; indexicals (e.g. 'I' refers to self or to a speaker), connectives (e.g. 'not' is to make negative a given proposition), and (d) miscellaneous instances (e.g. the 'equator' is an imaginary circle around the earth). (4) Fictional entity concepts are about entities created (or brought into existence) at a certain time through the acts of an author or story-teller. We ordinarily accept that we can talk about fictional entities to account for the truth of various intuitively true sentences that purportedly refer to fictional things. 6 Frege preferred that definitions and concepts should have a sharp boundary and unambiguously determine whether any item falls under a concept. In proof theory, concept formation and assumptions are fixed in such a way that a strict formalization of proofs is possible using the expressed means of symbolic logic. -19(5) Definite description concepts are phrases used to designate, denote, or specify certain entities that may or may not exist (or may be fictional). For example, the concept of 'the first man on the moon' designates Neil Armstrong. The concept of 'the first person on Mars' designates nothing. (6) Proper name concepts are understood to designate or denote particular existing or fictional entities (when used in a context). A proper name is normally used in a context where a listener can infer the speaker's intended denotation. The same proper name can designate different entities in different contexts. Some entities have more than one proper name. Following this conception, persons can understand 'testosterone' and 'estrogen' as natural kind chemicals found in men and woman. If one understands the group resemblance concept of 'house' one can identify its extensions with variable materials and designs. If one understands 'square' one identifies its instances as four-sided. If one understands the fictional concept Spiderman one is able to identify a portrait of him. If one understands 'the tallest president of the United States' one can do research to identify the entity. If one hears 'Springfield' in a context, one will likely infer that it is the proper name of a city. Of course, many words fall outside of this categorization (and have no intentional content) and are conceptualized (and defined) only according to their use. Words and concepts that lie outside these six categories have just reported uses and definitions.7 7 For example the word 'there' is defined by an ordinary dictionary as having three senses/uses: 1) as an adverb 'to indicate in or at that place' (e.g. there is the cat), 2) as a pronoun (e.g. there's a pen here), and 3) as a noun (e.g. get away from there). -20VII. What Concepts are Subject to Analysis? Alvin Goldman (2007) states that "concepts that correspond to natural kinds should be privileged, those that don't, shouldn't" (p. 17). Goldman says that given that natural kind concepts should be given attention, the major problem is that it's doubtful that every target of philosophical analysis has a corresponding natural kind. What are the natural kind concepts in philosophy? Besides the concepts of knowledge, reference, identity, and causation (all mentioned by Goldman), the concepts of truth, belief, justification, reason, representation, fact, intention, explanation, mind, mentality, consciousness, pain, freedom, beauty, art, goodness, virtue, happiness, justice, number, set, infinity, existence, meaning, proper name, and necessity have all been subject to philosophical analysis. With respect to this list of concepts, which of these can be interpreted as natural kind concepts? The answer will depend on a philosopher's broad world-view beliefs. For example, a moral realist, an aesthetic realist, and philosophers inclined toward strong realist metaphysics will have a different viewpoint about what concepts denote natural kinds from those who hold anti-realist positions. The only way to clarify alternative positions is to compare best-explanation arguments with the mediation of one's given world-view intuitions and linguistic-conceptual intuitions. While Goldman is correct that natural kind entities should be given priority, there is a need to analyze some 'group resemblance' concepts (e.g. 'justification,' 'relevant,' 'aesthetic experience') and 'fixed-definiens' concepts (e.g. 'axiom,' 'analytic sentence'). We will examine these examples. Whether a conceptual analysis is judged to be true depends partially upon the explanatory success of the theory in which it is embedded. -21The Concept of Epistemic 'Justification' The group resemblance term 'justification' has two standard senses that are not always recognized by philosophers. When speaking of epistemic justification, we can speak either about a person S being justified in holding a belief, or about a belief p being justified. The first sense is concerned with what it takes for a person S to be justified in believing a proposition, and the second sense is concerned whether a belief p has the property of being justified from an external perspective. With this distinction in mind, we can recognize the senses of 'personal justification' and 'belief justification' as follows: Personal justification (sense PJ): 'S is justified in believing p' if p is acquired as an immediate non-inferential belief, or S has reasonably (non-recklessly) acquired strong evidence and used good inferential reasoning for believing p. Belief justification (sense BJ): 'p is a justified belief' if p is believed from inductive evidence (or deductive reasoning) that is relevant (i.e. truth-connecting, pertinent, non-defective) for why p should be believed true. These two senses of 'justification' are not arbitrary stipulations. They reflect a real difference in the domains of discussion: persons and beliefs. The Concept of 'Relevance' Another group resemblance concept in epistemology that is ambiguous and not typically noticed by philosophers is the term 'relevant.' Suppose that a house in a residential neighborhood is substantially damaged by a fire. The cause of the fire is initially unknown. Local fire investigators are called in to determine 'why did the fire start?' Pre-theoretically, we believe that there are relevant reasons for why a house -22catches on fire. When seeking the cause(s) of why a fire started, fire investigators want to discover whether an arsonist was involved, or if there was careless smoking, or an electrical problem, or a lit candle, or lightening and so on. In order to obtain knowledge of the cause, the investigators seek objectively relevant evidence and relevant reasons for why the house caught fire, and wish to discard the consideration of any extraneous (and irrelevant) states-of-affairs not associated with the cause of the fire. Let us suppose that fire investigators offer this final report that explains why the fire started: 1) an upended candle was found in the bedroom of the home, where most of the fire damage occurred, 2) the pattern of how the fire spread, and resulting damage suggests that the fire started in the bedroom near the fallen candle, 3) a resident of the home admits having left a candle burning while leaving the home several hours earlier, 4) there is no other evidence (indicating arson, electrical problems, etc.) suggesting that the candle was not the cause of the fire, so therefore 5) p: the fire was caused by an unattended lit candle that fell and ignited nearby combustible materials. Whether the four premises stated by the investigators are 'relevant' for why the fire started is not something we decide. Instead, if these are the relevant reasons for why the house caught fire, it is because the reasons (i.e. evidential premises) are truthconnecting, objective, and independent of us. This sense of 'relevant' is consistent with ordinary use. The objectivity and truth-connectedness of relevant evidence is presumed by physical scientists (e.g. chemists, physicists, etc.) seeking the causal factors for physical processes. A dictionary definition states that 'relevant' (an adjective) means 'bearing on the matter at hand, germane, material, applicable, pertinent.' -23With this sense of 'relevance' it is assumed that an evidential proposition e can be either: (1) true and relevant for why p should be believed or (2) e is true and coincidental, and irrelevant for why p should be believed or 3) e is false and irrelevant for why p should be believed. In other words, it is assumed that S's body of evidence (or reasons) for believing p might contain true and/or false propositions. It is assumed that persons may (unintentionally) have false beliefs as 'evidence' (or reasons) for believing p.8 With respect to another common sense of 'relevant,' it is also oftentimes said that what counts as 'relevant evidence' is any evidence that is 'somehow related' or 'might have some significance or probability' for why p is true or false. For instance, the fire investigators at the start of their inquiry will be interested in any relevant evidence that may have a bearing on why a fire started. Pragmatic interests guide investigators to what items are considered 'relevant.' In this sense, any and all evidence (e.g. the electrical system, smoking materials, etc.) that might have some significance, are considered as items 'relevant' to determining the cause of the fire. This is a wider sense of 'relevant'.9 8 This is consistent with Williams (2001) that "empirical evidence, which provides the premises for empirical arguments, is itself only contingently true..." (p. 41). It is contrary to Williamson (2000) who says "knowledge, and only knowledge, constitutes evidence" (p. 185) and Leite (2013) who claims if e is false, it is not evidence for anything (p. 84). 9 Many philosophers are accustomed to just the wider sense of 'relevant.' Gail Stine (1976) says that an alternative is 'relevant' only if there is some reason to think that it is true. Stewart Cohen (1988) says that "factors pertaining exclusively to S's own evidence affect whether alternatives become relevant.... an alternative h is relevant, if S lacks -24The Concept of 'Aesthetic Experience' The group resemblance concept of 'aesthetic experience' can be characterized: An 'aesthetic experience' (AE) is a mental state where one comes in contact with an object x, and x produces a feeling, emotion, or intellectual stimulation, where one is engaged with x in a way to have some release from practical concerns, where x is experienced as an object of appreciation. An aesthetic experience is unique or 'stands out' from routine experience. A positive-AE is a feeling of reward (or appreciation) when experiencing an item x. A negative-AE is a feeling of disappointment (dislike, emptiness) when experiencing an item x. Typical items of aesthetic appreciation include the experiences of the arts, nature, culinary taste, olfactory scent, and tactile qualities. The Concepts of 'Axiom' and 'Analytic Sentence' In mathematics, the fixed definiens term 'axiom' can be systematically and conceptually analyzed despite not being a natural kind concept. An 'axiom' is an independent foundational prescriptive assertion that underlies a set of stipulative definitions, grammar-syntax, and inference rules that measure a specified domain. An axiom is typically (but not always) adopted if it helps map (or represent) the physical world (or linguistic discourse) in a fruitful way. In contrast, the definition of an 'axiom' as being 'a self-evident truth' is rejected. Similarly with the analysis of an 'analytic sentence,' it can be defined as 'a sentence that sufficient evidence (reason) to deny h..." (p. 103). John Hawthorne (2004) says that "What counts as relevant depends on the interests and intentions of the user" (p. 55). -25is true relative to and entailed solely by the fixed definiens of the definitions-vocabulary and grammar-syntax rules of a language without explicitly using any discrete axioms or inference rules.' In contrast, the vague conception of an 'analytic proposition' as being true solely in virtue of its meaning is rejected. The truth or falsity of these motivated definitions of 'axiom' and 'analyticity' is not the issue here; it is just that (fixed definiens) concepts are subject to analysis without representing natural kind entities. Conceptual analyses involve clarifying, resolving ambiguities, and promoting consistency. Conceptual analysis is not the discovery of necessary, non-empirical truths about the meanings (or natures) of things, but involves a dialectic among language users. With natural kind concepts, our attention is paid to the (objective) nature of the phenomena involved. With group resemblance concepts, attention is paid to how persons use a term in natural language and its correct application. With fixed-definiens concepts, the consistency of concepts and their relations are sought. VIII. The Status of Intuitions: How can they be Evidence in the Study of Concepts? The question arises however, as indicated above, how does a conceptual analysis proceed when there are disputed pre-theoretic world-views of the phenomena under consideration (about the nature of morality, aesthetics, mathematics, knowledge, semantics)? Further how does a conceptual analysis proceed when there are disputed pre-theoretic beliefs associated with a contested concept? It is obvious that a theory cannot be built solely out of a series of neutral pre-theoretic world-view and linguistic intuitions because the beliefs of various people can be contradictory. Let's examine some example cases of conflicting world-view intuitions and then revisit these questions. -26Example Cases of Divergent World-View Intuitions In Ethics, a secular moral realist maintains that ethical assertions are true or false and that when considering a moral question we search about who is right, and where our obligations lie. With this world-view, there are true moral answers awaiting discovery. Mark Schroeder (2010) suggests that it is intuitively the case that there is objective moral wrongness that is not relative to the interests of (groups of) persons. He cites the practice of infibulation as a conduct that is wrong in any circumstance, no matter what any person believes or values.10 In contrast, a secular anti-realist believes that moral value owes its existence to the interests and desires of humans. A human consensus is sought to prescribe conduct. (Most persons, of course, deny any secular position and believe that a god is the source of objective moral law). In Aesthetics up to the 18th century most philosophers believed that 'beauty' was an objective property of an aesthetic item (e.g. a painting). With attention to a broader view of aesthetic predicates (e.g. engaging, amusing, suspenseful, horrifying, thoughtprovoking), a dispute has arisen between 'realists' and 'anti-realists' in aesthetics. An aesthetic realist will say that an aesthetic judgment 'this painting is beautiful' is about the painting, and that the particular painting has the property of 'beauty' that emerges from its 10 Infibulation is a kind of genital cutting and as many as 300,000 different girls undergo this procedure every year according to the World Health Organization. There are no known health benefits of this procedure, but it can lead to bacterial infection, open sores, recurrent bladder and urinary tract infections, and increased risk of transmission of HIV. It also substantially raises the risk involved in child birth (Schroeder, p. 1). -27base physical properties. There are objective perceivable properties that explain why one can make a true or false assertion about the painting having beauty. An aesthetic subjectivist, on the contrary, believes that 'this painting is beautiful' reports a subjective experience, and is about whether the painting satisfies one's interests and tastes. In Mathematics an ontological realist contends that mathematics is about the discoverable objective features of the world. For example, numerals denote objective numbers, and numbers are abstract and eternal. In order for numerals to exist, and for mathematical knowledge to exist, their propositions must be about something. In contrast an anti-realist formalism focuses upon the use of stipulation and contends that the socalled 'truths' of formal deductive systems should be understood as 'true-in-a-language.' In Epistemology with respect to the problem of radical skepticism, some epistemologists have a strong pre-theoretic world-view belief that a person can know that one is not a brain-in-a-vat (by affirming a closure principle) while others argue that one cannot know this (denying the closure principle). In considering whether one can know that one isn't a disembodied brain-in-a-vat, Keith DeRose (1995) argues that one can know this, while Dretske (1971) argues that one cannot. There are strong opposing positions about what the discipline of Philosophy should be about. Should philosophers only be concerned about what is necessarily true (as opposed to what is contingently true)? Should deductive arguments be its standard methodology? Is there a priori knowledge? Should philosophers proceed with strong materialist-naturalist assumptions? Should philosophy be studied as a social science with linguistic, conceptual, and world-view intuitions as its primary data? -28Linguistic Intuitions as Data and Evidence in Support of a Word-View In a defense of world-view intuitions, philosophers offer conceptual thoughtexperiments with a motivation to resolve an apparent ambiguity or complexity, or from a background of a creative systematic hypothesis (e.g. principles) that requires dialectical inquiry. The plausibility of a given conceptual analysis is found in its appeal to persons who are adequately informed but not strongly-committed to a theoretic position. If a theory or set of principles generates hypotheses or predictions about whether 'S knows p' or 'x is art' in given thought-experiment situations, and if an open-minded audience to those experiments agrees with the predictions and the results of a hypothetical or realworld case, then that theory will be respected as truly explaining the details of a sharedconcept. A person's final post-theoretic beliefs are sometimes said to be in 'equilibrium' where plausible ordinary beliefs and intuitions coincide with a theory's prediction or explanation (and endorsed world-view). As Gary Gutting (2009, p. 225) states "Prior to philosophic reflection our convictions are not very well articulated and can be profitably regarded as expressing general pictures, that is, general schemes for thinking about some major aspect of the world. One of the main projects of philosophical thinking is the development of the precise and detailed formulations of important pictures... called theories." IX. A Reply to Experimental Philosophy: Yes, Intuitions Aren't Neutral/Reliable Surveys of the intuitions of ordinary speakers by so-called 'experimental philosophers' have shown that hypothetical thought experiments and conceptual intuitions can be diverse and conflicting. Philosophers such as Machery, Mallon, Nichols & Stich -29(2004) have raised the objection that because intuitions are culturally variable, they cannot serve as the fixed-point for philosophical theorizing. Joshua Alexander (2012) identifies the irrelevant static interference from the ethnicity, gender, affectivity of persons and presentation order of thought experiments as a reason for dispensing with intuitions (p. 3). Because intuitions are not reliable for ascertaining truth, it is argued that these kinds of beliefs should have no evidential role for philosophy. In response to this finding, it has been maintained here that neither personal world-view nor conceptual intuitions should be interpreted as the foundational neutral data that is in need of explanation. The goal of analytic philosophy isn't to just measure and interpret existing ordinary intuitions. Instead analytic philosophy and conceptual analyses are an attempt to sharpen linguistic/conceptual intuitions in order to support (or show false) a given world view. Intuitions surveyed from 'folk theory' opinion polls about various thought-experiments might undermine a theory (if the folk intuitions were in fact self-consistent and there was a consensus) but a strong explanatory philosophical theory can account for (or lead to reconsideration of) conflicting intuitions. One largely unnoticed problem associated with arguments about the diversity of responses is that experimental philosophers presume that one (or another) of the extant theories to certain philosophical issues must be genuinely plausible. One much-discussed example is that of 'reference' and theories about the use/function of proper names, such as with Kripke's example of 'Godel.' But what if the competing 'descriptivist' and 'causal' -30theories are both substantially in error?11 If philosophers currently argue over two false and misleading theories about 'linguistic reference' it seems natural that there will be differences in thought-experiment intuitions. That two bad philosophical theories lead to diverse layperson intuitions in thought-experiments isn't surprising. A better theory (e.g. about 'speaker reference') might lead to a greater cross-cultural consensus in intuitions. X. Conclusion Intuitions are not always truth-connecting (or reliable) sources of theoryconstruction. Since a theory cannot be constructed solely out of unbiased and neutral world-view intuitions, the analytic philosopher must provide a conceptual analysis with hypotheses and examples that provide reasons to believe that a given world-view is true. The mediate philosophical theory that occurs between world-view intuitions and conceptual intuitions is subject to debate (as being true or false). Contradictory worldviews cannot all be true, nor can contradictory conceptual analyses. The question about whose intuitions and what theory is to be believed will be based on the strength of a philosopher's argument, its clarity, and its intuitive plausibility. 11 I have argued in previous essays that 'semantic theories' (i.e. descriptivist and causal) are both in error because they falsely assume that (1) linguistic entities literally refer to (or 'pick out') things in a context (when this is only a metaphor), and (2) the 'principle of compositionality' is indispensible (when it actually may be dispensed with, or set aside). -31References Alexander, Joshua. 2012. Experimental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Polity Press. Cappelen, Herman. 2012. Philosophy Without Intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chalmers, David; Manley, David; Wasserman, Ryan (eds) 2009. Metametaphyics. New York: Oxford University Press. Cohen, Stewart. 1988. 'How to be a Fallibilist.' Philosophical Perspectives 2: 91-123. Depaul, Michael and Ramsey, William (eds.) 1998. Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. DeRose, Keith. 1995. 'Solving the Skeptical Problem.' Philosophical Review 104: 1-52. Dretske, Fred. 1971. 'Conclusive Reasons.' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 1-22. Glock, Hans-Johann. 2008. What is Analytic Philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Goldman, Alvin 2007. 'Philosophical Intuitions: Their Target, Their Source, and Their Epistemic Status.' Grazer Philosophische Studien 74: 1-26. Goldman, Alvin and Prust, J. 1998. 'Philosophical Theory and Intuitional Evidence.' in Depaul and Ramsey 1998. Gutting, Gary. 2009. What Philosophers Know. New York: Cambridge University Press. Hawthorne, John. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hintikka, Jaakko. 1999. 'The Emperor's New Intuitions.' Journal of Philosophy 96: 127-147. Knobe, Joshua & Nichols, Shaun (eds.) 2008. Experimental Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. Kripke, Saul A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Laurence, Stephen & Margolis, Eric. 1999. 'Concepts and Cognitive Science' in Margolis and Laurence (eds.) 3-81. Leite, Adam. 2013. 'But That's Not Evidence; It's Not Even True!' The Philosophical Quarterly 63: 81-104. Lewis, David. 1983. Philosophical Papers: Volume I. New York: Oxford University Press. Machery, Edouard, Mallon Ron, Nichols Shaun, & Stich Stephen. 2004. "Semantics, CrossCultural Style." Cognition 92, B1-B12. Reprinted in Knobe & Nichols (2008). -32Margolis, Eric and Laurence, Stephen (eds.) 1999. Concepts: Core Readings. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Morris, Charles W. 1938. Foundations of the Theory of Signs. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Parsons, Charles. 1995. 'Platonism and Mathematical Intuition in Kurt Godel's Thought.' The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1, 44-74. Schroeder, Mark. 2010. Noncognitivism in Ethics. New York: Routledge. Soames, Scott. 2003. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume 2, The Age of Meaning. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Soames, Scott. 2010a. Philosophy of Language. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Soames, Scott. 2010b. What is Meaning? Princeton: Princeton University Press. Stine, Gail. 1976. 'Skepticism, Relevant Alternatives, and Deductive Closure.' Philosophical Studies 29: 249-261. Stoljar, Daniel. 2010. Physicalism. New York: Routledge. van Inwagen, Peter. 1997. 'Materialism and the Psychological-Continuity Account of Personal Identity.' Nous 31, 305-319. Williams, Michael. 2001. Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press. Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. New York: Oxford University Press. Williamson, Timothy 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
© Copyright 2024