Mälardalen Mälardalen University University Press Press Dissertations Dissertations No. 156 No. 156 MATHEMATICAL MODELS OF SOCIAL NORMS AND PETTY CORRUPTION Alexander Funcke 2015 School School of of Education, Education, Culture Culture and and Communication Communication Copyright © Alexander Funcke, 2015 ISBN 978-91-7485-187-8 ISSN 1651-4238 Printed by Arkitektkopia, Västerås, Sweden Mälardalen University Press Dissertations No. 156 Mälardalen University Press Dissertations No. 156 MATHEMATICAL MODELS OF SOCIAL NORMS AND PETTY CORRUPTION Alexander Funcke MATHEMATICAL MODELS OF SOCIAL NORMS AND PETTY CORRUPTION Alexander Funcke Akademisk avhandling som för avläggande av filosofie doktorsexamen i matematik/tillämpad matematik vid Akademin för utbildning, kultur och kommunikation kommer att offentligen försvaras fredagen den 27 mars 2015, 13.00 i Delta, Mälardalens högskola, Västerås. Akademisk avhandling Fakultetsopponent: professor David Sumpter, Uppsala Universitet som för avläggande av filosofie doktorsexamen i matematik/tillämpad matematik vid Akademin för utbildning, kultur och kommunikation kommer att offentligen försvaras fredagen den 27 mars 2015, 13.00 i Delta, Mälardalens högskola, Västerås. Fakultetsopponent: professor David Sumpter, Uppsala Universitet Akademin för utbildning, kultur och kommunikation Akademin för utbildning, kultur och kommunikation Abstract Corruption is a problem all around the world, but the extent of the problem varies between countries and situations. In this thesis, I focus on how corruption levels can change when they are culturally determined. For this reason, I study the dynamics of the cultural underpinnings: social norms and conventions. The dissertation consists of six papers. In the first paper, I expand a common definition of social norms. The aim of the extension is to capture the fact that the scope of a social norm may be larger than just a single specific situation. I introduce a similarity measure and develop a mathematical model according to which all situations' social norms are interconnected, and affect each other, but those situations that are most similar and most recent have the greatest normative effect on a current situation. Given this model I test the effect of bringing about norm change by temporarily dismantling institutions and then reestablishing them. In the second paper, I show in a mathematical model how it is possible to design fine and reward mechanisms that make it superfluous for individuals to form beliefs about how others will act. Through this mechanism, it should be possible to circumvent the problem that norm change typically will be successful only if it is synchronized across a large part of the population. In the third paper, I and my co-authors, first conducted a survey. The results of which demonstrate that there is a general tendency among people to consider themselves to be less prone to corrupt behavior than the average person. Such an "everyone-is-better-than-average" effect is a well-established phenomenon in social psychology but not previously demonstrated in the corruption domain. We then show in a mathematical model that such systematic biases in estimation of own versus others' corruption make it more difficult to achieve norm change in the direction of less corruption. In the fourth and fifth paper we again consider the "everyone-is-better-than-average" effect and see how in certain value based groups the effect can be reversed. This changes the insight from the third paper slightly. The last paper considers a classic question of how a collective can succeed in collective action when it is risky to be among the first individuals to act. I and my co-author investigate how the collective can benefit from access to a set of signal acts that signal an individual's level of commitment to the collective cause. The problem is modeled as a threshold model where an individual's inclination to conduct a specific act depends on the previous commitment level in the population. ISBN 978-91-7485-187-8 ISSN 1651-4238 PA P E R S I N C L U D E D I N T H E S I S 1. Instilling norms in a turmoil of spillovers Alexander Funcke Published in PPE Working Papers, Philosophy, Politics and Economics, University of Pennsylvania, 4 (2015) 2. A mechanism for optimal enforcement of coordination: sidestepping theory of mind Alexander Funcke, Daniel Cownden Published in PPE Working Papers, Philosophy, Politics and Economics, University of Pennsylvania, 3 (2015) 3. Biased perception may trump rational intention: most people think they are less corrupt than average Alexander Funcke, Kimmo Eriksson, Pontus Strimling Submitted to Rationality & Society 4. Humble self-enhancement: religiosity and the better-than-average effect Kimmo Eriksson, Alexander Funcke Published in Social Psychological and Personality Science 5(1) (2014): 7683 5. A stairway to revolutionary collective below-average effect with respect to american political stereotypes on warmth and competence Kimmo Eriksson, Alexander Funcke In press with Political Psychology. Published online before print September 30, 2013. doi: 10.1111/pops.12093 6. A stairway to revolutionary collective action Alexander Funcke, Ulrik Franke Submitted to Rationality & Society 3 ACKNO WLEDGMEN T I am grateful to the Swedish Research Council, the Ratio Institute, the Edmond J. Safra Center for Ethics at Harvard University, the Behavioral Ethics Lab at University of Pennsylvania, the Center for Study of Public Choice at George Mason University and in particular the Centre for the Study of Cultural Evolution at Stockholm University, for hosting me, funding me and (at least by proxy) having some belief in me. I acknowledge Kimmo Eriksson and Pontus Strimling; my Ph.D. advisors and co-authors. I tip my hat to my other co-authors Ulrik Franke and Daniel Cownden. And I will keep tipping it to each and everyone who has worked with me, or who have made this effort more delightful, such as Alberto Acerbi, Anna Jon-And, Anna-Carin Stymne; Arne Jarrick, Elliot Aguilar, Cristina Bicchieri; Fredrik Jansson, Ida Envall, Jan Willem Lindemans; Jiang Ting, Johan Lind, Laila Nauman; Magnus Enquist, Maria Wallenberg Bondesson, Marijane Luistro Jonsson; Mark Somos, Markus Jonsson, Micael Ehn; Mícheál de Barra, Molly Sundberg, Patrik Lindenfors; Sven Isaksson and William English. Lastly, I am grateful for the support from those that have been close to me. 5 Part I INTRODUCTION 1 OVERVIEW This thesis is part of a larger research project on corruption funded by the Swedish Research Council. It is written within the Ph.D. program in applied mathematics at Mälardalen University. In this thesis, I apply mathematics to the domain of corruption and social norms. From a mathematical point of view, the research is truly applied in the sense that my intended audience is not specifically mathematicians, but scholars from all disciplines interested in work on corruption and social norms. These will include scholars from philosophy, economics, sociology, political science, and psychology. Consequently, my thesis is written with such an audience in mind. It will not have the look and feel of a typical thesis in mathematics, but there will be no mistaking that mathematical modeling is what I do. For mathematical modeling in the area of corruption, game theory is indispensable. After all, corruption has a definite aspect of individuals acting in narrow self-interest, which is what game theoretic analyses assume. There are however other aspects, not least social ones. In particular, I will argue that there are forms of corruption that is in large part norm driven. Research on corruption, particularily the empirical research, has flourished in the last few decades. It is typically based on some country measures of corruption, such as the Corruption Perception Index. Researchers employ econometric methods to such data to relate corruption to other important things, such as growth, health, development, and democracy. In this literature, and often also in the related experimental and theoretic literature, corruption is often spoken about as if it was a phenomenon that could be covered by a single theory. Corruption, even if narrowed down to bribery, contain a large 9 1 overview set of distinct strategic situations. From a potential multi-million dollar bribe in an arms deal to an average citizen bribing an officer to obtain a driving license. This thesis interests itself with the latter, the small-scale day-to-day corruption. The established term for this is petty corruption. I will start with the premise that petty corruption is largely norm driven, and that the dynamics of petty corruption fruitfully can be understood as an example of the dynamics of social norms. The dissertation may, for this reason, also be read as a text on social norm dynamics. The thesis is divided into two parts. The first part discusses various fundamental issues: What is corruption? What is known about the process by which regularities in corrupt behavior can be disturbed? What are norms and how can they be modeled in mathematical language? What methodologies are available to modelers of social phenomena? How do the contributions of the six papers of this thesis relate to the discussion and what do they contribute? The second part of the thesis consists of six research papers. Four of the papers builds on the background and methodological stances argued for in the first part. Papers 4 and 5 are of a more psychological nature and considers how the phenomenon at the core of paper 3 is affected by the presence of value based social groups. 10 2 BACKGROUND 2.1 corruption Transparency International, a major anti-corruption organization, uses the following definition of corruption (Eicher, 2012): “Corruption is the abuse of entrusted power for private gain.” Other anti-corruption actors, such as the United Nations and the World Bank, adopt similar ones. This definition is but one example, be it an important one, another example is: “corruption is a transaction between private and public sector actors through which collective goods are illegitimately converted into private regarding payoffs” (Heidenheimer et al., 1989). The extension of either of the two definitions is vast. Including everything from a questionable gift to a preschool teacher to a multi-billion dollar bribe facilitating an arms deal. The definitions provide ethical categories and help to recognize violations. If our goal, however, is to map, measure and model corruption, the broad scope of the definitions pose problems. E.g., how would one make a questionable gift commensurable to a billion-dollar bribe? Do we expect the two cases to share the same dynamics? Probably not. Despite these challenges, a large portion of corruption research uses these broad definitions. Notably, the significant body of econometric work that employ Transparency International’s Corruption Perception Index, which among other things suggest causes of corruption (Treisman, 2000; Pellegrini, 2011) and correlations between corruption and growth (Méndez and Sepúlveda, 2006). To the extent that we lack reasons to believe that distinct types of corruption share causes and effects, these econometric papers are challenging to 11 2 background interpret. Unsurprisingly, we find more fine-grained taxonomies of corruption. One common differentiation is by type of act, e.g. bribery, embezzlement, fraud, extortion or favoritism (Andvig et al., 2001). It is also common to contrast grand and petty corruption (Doig and Theobald, 2013). Grand corruption, defined as corruption occurring at the highest levels of government such that it subverts political, legal and economic systems. Petty corruption, defined as the smaller-scale corrupt behavior taking place with-in a particular social framework. In this dissertation, we choose not to explore corruption in the broad sense, but rather to hone in on petty corruption. Typically in the form of bribery. Initially, the economics literature on petty corruption and bribery modeled the phenomena as situations where the interacting parties have asymmetric information. E.g. agents do corrupt deals in secrecy and by that know more about what goes on than their counterparts outside of the deals. This, and other approaches that stem out of micro economic theory tend to capture important aspects of the setting, sometimes they, however, prove insufficient. As Alam (1989) put it: this [. . . ] perspective on corruption [. . . ] stems from two sources: the failure to perceive its often systemic character. And an unwillingness to examine its effects in a dynamic perspective. The systemic character that Alam alludes to, we will assume is explained largely by social norms. This assumption has empirical support. One illustrative example is the natural cross-cultural experiment in the Fisman and Miguel (2007) article: Corruption, norms, and legal enforcement: Evidence from diplomatic parking tickets. It suggests that diplomats from more corrupt countries are more prone to receive and ignore parking ticket. Thus providing support for our assumption, as corruption levels vary with culture and social norms. There is a handful of micro level cross-country economic lab experiments supporting the social norms hypothesis too: i) The correlation between a student’s likelihood to act corrupt and the corruption level of her home country (Barr and Serra, 2010); ii) The propensity to engage and punish corruption vary with the regional corruption level at the lab location (Cameron et al., 2009). iii) Similar subject pool effects are also found comparing public servants and students in Indonesia (Alatas et al., 2009). On the macro level, the 12 2.1 Corruption social norm assumption about petty corruption is corroborated by the impressive sector correlations of corruption levels in cross-country surveys such as Transparency International’s Global Corruption Barometer (Riaño et al., 2010). The cross-cultural variation have received attention before, but the focus has traditionally been on formal institutions, rather than social norms, e.g. as in Myrdal (1970): before the power structure has been changed by evolution or revolution, it will be difficult to decrease corruption or even to hinder its continual increase. One notable exception is the Karklins (2005) book: The system made me do it. It offers an attractive case-study of the importance of social norms to explain corruption. Depicting how the malign norms of state-avoidance and corruption were fostered by Soviet institutions, and how they spilled over into the setting of fragile democracies in the 1990s. Our assumption about social norms being a key determinant for systemic petty corruption was not least inspired by Bo Rothstein’s so-called “big bang theory” of anti-corruption (Rothstein, 2007). In summary Rothstein’s paper holds that systemic petty corruption can only be quenched by a massive resolute institutional overhaul. This as the overhaul would cause citizens to reconsider what is the “way to behave” in relation to the state. Their old behavioral script for interaction, which upheld social norms of corruptive behavior, would no longer apply. They would, as a result, need to reason about how to interact, while being aware that the other citizens are reasoning how to behave too. This is important as social norms are coordinative (more about this in the next section), and a citizen’s change in behavior is conditional on the other changing too. This rare type of big bang situation could thus facilitate a new social norms for avoidance of petty corruption. The purpose of this dissertation is to further the understanding of the dynamics of systemic petty corruption, which we by assumption equate with the dynamics of social norms. 13 2 background 2.2 social norms In the previous section, we reduced systemic petty corruption to a social phenomenon determined by social norms. That is, a society may, or may not, have a social norm to avoid acts of petty corruption. Exploring the dynamics of systemic petty corruption thus translates to exploring the dynamics of social norm change. This section aims to give some background to what social norm change have entailed by looking at a few excerpts from the relevant history of ideas. The concepts of social norms and conventions have history in all the social sciences. In both sociology and anthropology the concepts can arguably be said to be at the very core. To differentiate between the two: Conventions are informally held understanding with-in a population causing regularities in social behavior. Social norms, serve a similar purpose but tend to prescribe a normative behavior in situations where the individual and the social interests do not align. The concepts of social norms and conventions are not only key, they are old too. Already in ancient Greece social norms (nomos) were discussed. An example is the “proto-cosmopolitan” Hippas urging the gentlemen gathered to stop quarreling. Arguing that the differences in citizenship was no more than mere convention (Plato, 1967, Protogoras 337c-d): Gentlemen, he said, who are here present, I regard you all as kinsmen and intimates and fellow-citizens by nature, not by law: for like is akin to like by nature, whereas law, despot of mankind, often constrains us against nature. In the history of ideas, David Hume has served as the pivotal figure stressing the importance of conventions and norms. Conventions were at the core of his views on everything from esthetics to justice. Hume defines a convention in Appendix III of the Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals (Hume, 1739/1896, Appendix III): a sense of common interest; which sense each man feels in his own breast, which he remarks in his fellows, and which carries him, in concurrence with others, into a general plan or system of actions, which tends to public utility 14 2.2 Social norms Note two things. First, that Humian definition of conventions is closer to what we today at least colloquially would regard as a social norm. Secondly, the Humian account is of a psychological nature, in contrast with the formal definitions that later will serve as the social norm definition throughout most of this dissertation. The detail of how individuals ponder and feel about norms do, however, matter. In Paper 3 of the thesis we consider one such case. We consider the so-called better-than-average bias, the tendency to overestimate oneself compared to the average person, and how taking this into account makes escaping a bad social norm or convention even harder. Conventions are ubiquitous in social life. They give meaning to utterances, coordinate what side we drive on, and explain how money retains value. They also are also often proto-social norms, as conventions may become established to the extent that a population develop a liking for the convention and are ready to police it. To highlight for how long conventions and social norms have been a topic of study, consider how the idea of money as a convention has developed through history. Aristotle wrote (Aristotle, 1980, Nicomachean Ethics, V.5): Money has become by convention a sort of representative of demand; and this is why it has the name ‘money’ (‘nomisma’) – because it exists not by nature but by law (nomos) and it is in our power to change it and make it useless David Hume picked up the same topic centuries later and explicated the dynamic in On Money (Hume, 1752/1987), as well in the following paragraph (Hume, 1739/1896, p. 490): [G]radually establish’d by human conventions without any explicit promise [. . . ] gold and silver become the common measures of exchange, and are esteem’d sufficient payment for what is of a hundred times their value. A century later, the process of becoming conventional was refined further by economist Carl Menger (1892) in The Origins of Money. The refinement is not in the language of abstract conventions but suggests by example how the liquid asset of choice changes. I.e. how the convention can be shocked out of an equilibrium and into a new one by innovation and changes in technology. As 15 2 background we explore the dynamics of social norms this process of change as a response to a changing context will be of major importance. 16 3 METHODOLOGY In this thesis, we will treat the subject matter of social norms and systemic petty corruption using the language of mathematics. We therefore need to capture the properties of the phenomena involved and to model them formally. The formal models let us deduce information about the dynamics, which may later be tested against real world data. A model is by definition an incomplete description of a phenomenon. What constitute a good model is an area of dispute. Qualities may be balanced against one another: Simplicity, predictiveness, fit to historical data, contribution to understanding, etc.. This section does of course not give a full-fledged overview of the philosophy of social science, but it attempts to summarize some of the debates and thereby put the papers in context. 3.1 instrumentalism v. realism A common reaction to the enterprise of modeling social phenomenon is: “How can people be reduced to numbers?” It is a sensible reaction. The short answer is: They can not. At least not in the sense that the social scientists do. If we allow us to be less defeatist, it seems clear that we at least seem able to say something. One way to rescue formal discussion in social science is not to care about whether models represent any aspects of the social world, but instead focus solely on its proven predictability. This position is called instrumentalist, and is perhaps best summarized by its poster boy, Milton Friedman, recipient of the 1976 Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences (Friedman, 1953, p.14): 17 3 methodology Truly important and significant hypotheses will be found to have ‘assumptions’ that are wildly inaccurate descriptive representations of reality, and, in general, the more significant the theory, the more unrealistic the assumptions. This perspective of what science is, and should do, do not need to claim that people can be reduced to equations. Instead, the claim is that equations may be predictive about outcomes of social interaction. In opposition to the instrumentalists, there is another stance, the realist. The realists critique the instrumentalism of reducing scholarly activity to the craft of forecasting. For a realist, a good model should not only be able to make predictions, but also provide understanding. That is, the realist requires that the entities within the model represent aspects of the target phenomenon. Thus, the realist’s perspective may outperform an instrumentalist method if relevant aspects of the situations suddenly start to change. Now, how do the realist answer the sensible reaction to “reducing people to numbers”? One thinkable reply is to claim that she does not do anything of that sort. That modeling human behavior is to isolate part of what people are, and then reason about this simpler entity. Paraphrasing Uskali Mäki (2002, p. 11): The realist’s account is that a model M is a simple system used as a representation of a more complex system X. The intention is that by studying the properties and dynamics of M we learn something about X. However, why would examination of one system, M, convey information about another system, X? To make it plausible that it does, M should represent X in relevant aspects. In this thesis, the modeling intends to commit to a realistic stance in Uskali Mäki’s sense. A further distinction that one may find apt is Mäki’s ideas of horizontal and vertical isolation (Mäki, 1992). “Horizontal isolation” entails methods of abstraction and omission, while “vertical isolation” entail a change in the level of abstraction. Both kinds of isolation are of course distortions of any real world representation. That being said, horizontal isolation do allow us to talk about an isolated dynamics of actual entities in the real world. In contrast, vertical isolation invents new “aggregation entities” without direct real world counterpart. Horizontal isolation is thus compatible with an isolationist realistic view of science. In the dissertation, vertical isolation has 18 3.2 Methodological holism v. Individualism mostly been avoided, but it for instance not honored in the “societal commitment level” construct in Paper 6, the idealization of a shared metric in Paper 1 may also be questioned. 3.2 methodological holism v. individualism A methodological strife among those not committed to sheer instrumentalism is what entities a model ought to represent. Is it possible to reduce a complex social system to behavior among “atoms”? Or, is the only honest representation of the system to consider it as a whole? In social science, these contrasting views are called methodological individualism and methodological holism respectively. That is, holism is an anti-reductionist stance, where the whole is purposefully studied in itself. The textbook proponent of the holistic approach is Émile Durkheim (Durkheim, 1895/1982). Others do too, not least structuralists, such as Claude Lévi-Strauss and Michel Foucault (Lévi-Strauss, 2008; Foucault, 1970/2001). Methodological individualism, on the other hand, emphasizes that social phenomena are but patterns in individual behavior, beliefs, and so forth. Individualism is thus a method of horizontal isolation where the “atoms” are black boxed individuals. This perspective tends to be the one taken in micro economics. It is also the view taken in relation to social norms by e.g., Max Weber and Fredrich Hayek (Weber, 1978; Hayek, 1979). In this dissertation, as a corollary to avoiding vertical isolation, we will commit to methodological individualism. Note that methodological individualism versus holism is not a proper dichotomy and that the meaning of the two varies between scientists (Udehn, 2002). 3.3 simulation v. analytical method Try to model social norms with assumption true to the real world, and one will quickly realize that analytical methods are unfeasible. Subjective utility functions, asymmetric discounting factors, and non-trivial interaction networks are only the most well-known aspects that analytical analysis tend to 19 3 methodology ignore. (Beinhocker, 2007) In recent decades, computer simulations of complex (adaptive) systems have established themselves as an alternative to analytical analysis of mathematical models; opening up analysis of systems that previously were out of reach. A popular simulation paradigm in social science is the agent-based modeling (ABM) approach. The approach entails having agents, representing say individuals, firms or countries. Each agent is given some, simple or complex, rule of interaction. The simulation then gives the agents an interaction pattern under which the micro rules may make interesting macro regularities emerge. E.g. segregation, social norms or efficiency of environments. Note that ABM is compatible with methodological individualism. The ABM literature is a substantial part of the literature on social norms. Perhaps most notable is the Robert M. Axelrod (1997) book The complexity of cooperation: Agent-based models of competition and collaboration which among other thing illustrate how “social norms” can emerge out of interaction and learning. Another important contribution is the Joshua M. Epstein (2006) book Generative social science: Studies in agent-based computational modeling that consider cases of cultural and social norm change. The Eric D. Beinhocker (2007) book The Origins of Wealth is another convincing book about the aptitude of ABM. The book is a formidable sales pitch for the methodology, and how being able to take more of the real-world complex system into account will benefit science. I will share my experience with ABM, not as an argument about ABM as a method, but only as an explanation of why I chose not to extensively use ABM. My first large ABM-project was to re-implement an agent-based model of the transition dynamics in corruption (Hammond, 2000). My implementation could not replicate the findings. I tweaked the implicit assumptions of my implementations, and all of a sudden it did. Next, I modified the original model, and after considerable debugging I had an implementation of an ABM that showed what I had presupposed. However, it left me uncertain to what degree I should feel that I had corroborated the hypothesis. I ended up feeling that, for my ends, ABM gave too many degrees of freedom. That said, ABM is an immensely powerful method. It is not least an excellent tool for exploring and testing theoretical models, and used with care it can certainly corroborate theory too. 20 3.3 Simulation v. Analytical method My limited experience is not a basis for much reasoning, but others have thought about these issues. First, are simulation and analytical methods qualitatively different epistemologically? The black box nature of simulations, where we sometimes are left unable to explain why, or upon what assumptions some macro phenomenon hinges, may be considered as such a qualitative difference (Humphreys, 2009). More convincingly, I think, Frigg and Reiss (2009) argue that the simulation method is “the same old stew”, and that it is only a difference in degree of what Humpreys calls “epistemically opaqueness”. That said, there are still reasons to think differently about a simulated corroboration compared to an analytical one, given the typically higher level of opaqueness. Proceeding to the challenges I experienced. Till Grüne-Yanoff (2009) argues that a simulation typically is a weaker corroborator than an analytical result as the space of possible simulations, especially realistic ones, is far greater than the number of systems open for analytical analysis. Further, he argues that the process by which one navigate this space, i.e. implement a simulation is problematic. Not only do implementing a simulation typically require a set of implicit assumptions. As the process is one of craftsmanship, the point at which debugging is discontinued may, as the system is somewhat opaque, risk being as the expected result is found. Again, this is not to say that agent-based modeling is not a powerful tool, it is. Especially for exploration, understanding the implication of a theory, or in critiquing problematic simplifications (Funcke, 2011). Through most of the thesis, I opt for analytical methods. In Paper 3 we use an ABM simulation to illustrate the skewed norm dynamics implied by biased agents. 21 4 MODELS 4.1 game theory In this thesis, all papers either use game theory or is motivated by its applications. This section will give a background to the concepts employed. Game theory is the study of strategic interactions among economic agents producing outcomes. An economic agent is taken to be an utility-maximizing rational agent with respect to its preferences. This representation of human strategic behavior is often dressed up in straw and ridiculed, and sometimes rightly so. Actual human decision-making is, of course, different. The simplified assumption does, however, provide a normative theory, and seems to isolate an important part of the underlying dynamics. Also, humans my not be fully rational, but will in a stable environment over time often tend toward rational behavior. Not necessarily thanks to individual smarts, but by other social processes, such as cultural evolution and ecological feedback. Even with-in the scope of the game theoretic literature there are strains considering agents with non-perfect rationality. In what has been dubbed evolutionary game theory individuals with fixed (not rationally chosen) strategies are set to play each other. Individuals are born with the same fixed strategy as their parents or a random mutation. The individuals with the most successful strategies will have the greater reproductive success and/or survival. Thus, their strategy will eventually dominate the population. Another strain is the so-called bounded rationality literature, it tries to model and understand how human decision-makers act given their limited cognitive apparatus. There are many operationalizations, but most common 23 4 models is to divide reasoning into two systems, a slow, costly rational process and a toolbox of fast and frugal heuristics employed widely (Gigerenzer and Selten, 2002; Kahneman, 2011). That is, agents are equipped with simple behavioral rules for classes of situations that they employ without rational questioning. The game, in game theory, is a description of the strategic situation together with the possible payoff outcomes relative the agent’s preferences. Each agent chooses a strategy; the combination of all strategic choices of all the players is a tuple. A Nash equilibrium is a strategy tuple that if selected, no player have an incentive to individually deviate from it. If the equilibrium is unique, then this is what the economic agents are predicted to play. 4.1.1 Coordination problems Coordination games is a class of games in game theory that have multiple Nash equilibria. In this thesis, all papers are either about coordination problems or motivated thereof. The motivation for why coordination problems will be central to this thesis will be properly spelled out in Section 4.2. Coordination problems take many forms, let us consider two games, the pure coordination game, and the stag hunt. Left Right Left 2 0 Right 0 1 Figure 4.1: A pure coordination game example In Figure 4.1 an example of a pure coordination game is depicted in 2 × 2 normal form game notation. That is, there are two players with a simultaneous choice between two strategies. The game is symmetric; both players may view the game from the perspective of the row-player. They may thus choose between the Left and the Right strategy while considering her opponent as the column-player choosing between the Left and the Right strategy too. The payoffs are given by the cell indexed by the two player’s strategic choices. Since coordination games have multiple equilibria, the Nash equilibrium concept fails to predict what will be the strategies played. Empirically, how- 24 4.1 Game theory ever, we see that some equilibria are selected more often than other (Sugden, 1989). Payoffs may differ between equilibria, but that fact alone fails to explain differential selection of equilibria. To improve predictiveness, a myriad of Nash equilibrium refinements have been designed to make one of the Nash equilibria unique (Myerson, 1978; Samuelson, 1998; Govindan and Wilson, 2008). Each refinement is informative for some cases, but no approach is universal (Fudenberg et al., 1988). Other branches of the literature venture outside of the specifics of the game in order to make one equilibrium unique. E.g., formalizing salience (Binmore and Samuelson, 2006; Sugden, 2011), learning (Fudenberg, 1998) or the process of belief formation overall (Perea, 2012; Kawagoe and Takizawa, 2009). In pure coordination games, the interests of players align. In the example in Figure 4.1 both the row and column player prefer to end up in the upperleft equilibrium (Left, Left). In a one-shot interaction, coordination is thus easily achieved by rational players with rational expectations. Under repeated interaction, it may be more complicated as players tend to form expectations using history. If, for one reason or the other, history would be dominated by play of the inferior lower-right equilibrium (Right, Right) the population may very well be stuck playing it. Stag Hare Stag 2 0 Hare 1 1 Figure 4.2: A stag hunt game example Another coordination problem of major importance is the stag hunt (Skyrms, 2004) depicted in Figure 4.2. This is again a symmetric game and both players will see their strategic situation from the perspective of the row-player. In this game, agents have a hard time predicting the choice of the other in the one-shot interaction. The upper-left equilibrium (Stag, Stag) is more risky while the lower-right equilibrium (Hare, Hare) pays less. It is easy to see that this is the case, if a player chooses Hare, then she will receive a payoff of 1. If she instead chooses Stag she will possibly receive a payoff of 2, but only if her opponent chooses Stag too. If not, she will receive a payoff of 0. The 25 4 models equilibrium (Hare, Hare) is therefore said to be a risk-dominant equilibrium, and the equilibrium (Stag, Stag) a payoff-dominant equilibrium. In essence, what a player needs to do in a coordination problem is to form a belief about the other’s choice. Rational choice depends on beliefs about other agent’s beliefs, which makes it hard to uniquely determine a strategic choice due to indeterminacy of the belief (Bicchieri, 1997, p. 41). A rational choice analysis of an agent’s choice in a repeated game would thus required to make strong assumptions about common knowledge concerning rationality, inductive standards, preferences, background information, etc.. A seemingly insurmountable task. 4.1.2 Case-based decision making Game theoretic analysis usually rests on the assumption that agents maximize expected utility. In Paper 1 we step out of the paradigm of expected utility theory and instead consider case-based decision theory. Case-based decision theory was introduced by Gilboa and Schmeidler (2001) as an alternative to the expected utility theory and rule-based decision-making. As argued above, expected utility theory is not enough to predict if people will end up in one rather than the other equilibrium. Case-based decision-making can arguably be seen as a dynamic version of the rule-based decision-making but without an a priori carve-up of what situations belong to what rule. Following Gilboa and Schmeidler (2001), let P be a set of problems, A a set of acts, and R a set of outcomes. The set of all conceivable cases is then C ≡ P × A × R. Case-based decision theory assumes that problems are to varying degrees similar to each other, captured by a dissimilarity function s : P × P → [0, 1]. Further, different outcomes are to varying degrees preferred, represented by a utility function u : R → R. 26 4.2 Models of petty corruption A decision maker faced with a problem (p ∈ P) is assumed to base her decision on her memory of past cases (M ⊂ C) in order to maximize expected utility. Expected utility will thereby depend on how similar previous cases were to the problem currently faced: U(a) = Up,M (a) = s(p, q)u(r). (q,a,r)∈M David Hume might have predated the framework by two and a half century, but still argues for it well: “From causes which appear similar we expect similar effects. This is the sum of all our experimental conclusions.” (Hume, 1748/2000, p. 31) 4.2 models of petty corruption In Section 2.1 we went through a variety of perspectives taken on corruption, and in particular on systemic petty corruption. This section will give an overview of previous modeling pertinent to systemic petty corruption. There is a vast literature that tie into this problem one way or another. If we, for instance, consider systemic petty corruption as a phenomenon idealizable as, say, a classical prisoner’s dilemma or a trust game, then we have shelves upon shelves of material analyzing these cases. Two prevalent schemes to reach the “non-corrupt” equilibrium in these settings are either to impose institutions or to instill social norms. Before moving on with discussing the modeling of social norms let us take a broader look at previous efforts. This basic game perspective is far from the only viewpoint, there is a fair number of work that characterize bribery and corruption as principal-agent problems (Rose-Ackerman, 1978; Kurer, 1993; Rose-Ackerman, 1999; Bowles and Garoupa, 1997). That is, as agency-problems, where an agent’s decisions affect a principal, or where an autonomous single official’s actions affect the society as a whole. Other interesting perspectives are given by e.g. the Acemoglu and Verdier (1998) paper that introduces a “general equilibrium”-style model of corruption. The model assumes that the government’s task is to uphold private contracts. The private agents are dishonest and cheat whenever 27 4 models they get the chance, and government officials are equally dishonest too. The private agents are divided into “producers” and “suppliers”. The game is one of asymmetric information. First, the supplier may invest in her intermediate good, which potentially increase the quality. The producer does not know whether an investment took place or not. Secondly, the producer finds out the quality of the intermediate good, when he puts the final good on the market. The supplier, however, will still not know what the quality of her intermediate good was. They contract so that suppliers will reap a benefit from having provided high-quality intermediate good, and thus have an interest to invest. In the absence of a contract-upholding government, producers would always cheat, and thus suppliers would not invest. With a perfect government, the result is reversed. Acemoglu and Verdier (1998) goes on to introduce various variations on the incentive structure of the government officials. They may thereby produce theoretical results concerning salary levels and disciplinary actions; they also ponder if paying officials too much remove talent from the private sector. We choose a game theoretic framework for analysis as it respect methodological individualism and can handle the systemic aspect that we believe is important. Other types of models do also capture the self-enforcing feedback loop that make us deem the behavior systemic. One such example is Andvig and Moene (1990) who in a supply and demand setting show how the profitability of petty corruption may be related to its frequency and suggest a mechanism for explaining this stylized fact. Hauk and Saez-Marti (2002) develops a model in a cultural transmission setting, also explaining the stylized fact. Mishra (2006); Basu et al. (1992) are two interesting papers that hones in on the interaction between different levels of bureaucracy and their “weakest link of the chain”-dynamics. I.e., having honest officials in a bureaucracy does not help to fight corruption if their supervisors are corrupt. Even though this is an important aspect, the hierarchical aspects of corruption are largely omitted from the analysis in this thesis. Other omitted yet interesting aspects include whether corruptees and corruptors require a large portion of trust (Granovetter, 2007), and how occasions for corruption only exist given corruptor-entrepreneurs (Granovetter, 2007; Coyne et al., 2010; Baumol, 1990). 28 4.3 Models of social norms 4.3 models of social norms In economics, social norms tend to feature, if at all, as an exogenous factor. Either as a constraining institution or as an unexplored coordination device. The literature on sanctions in relation to social norms is however a big topic, as well as how efficient the social outcomes they create are (Elster, 1989; Wenzel, 2004; Fehr and Fischbacher, 2004). Another strand of the literature, spearheaded by the David Lewis (1969) book Conventions, treats conventions and social norms as the subject matter, rather than as exogenous phenomena. Before coming back to Lewis, let us acknowledge that for questions about how social norms emerge, other approaches have been more fruitful, such as the simulation work by Axelrod (1997); Epstein (2006) and the Young (1993) work using Markov processes. As the title suggests, Conventions is a book that first and foremost is interested in conventions rather than social norms. Lewis do provide a definition of social norms too, but let us consider his seminal definition of a convention (Lewis, 1969, p. 76): A regularity R in the behavior of members of a population P when they are agents in a recurrent situation S is a convention if and only if it is true that, and it is common knowledge in P that, in any instance of S among members of P, 1. everyone conforms to R; 2. everyone expects everyone else to conform to R; 3. everyone has approximately the same preferences regarding all possible combinations of actions; 4. everyone prefers that everyone conform to R, on condition that at least all but one conform to R; 5. everyone would prefer that everyone conform to R , on condition that at least all but one conform to R , where R is some possible regularity in the behavior of members of P in S, such that no one in any instance of S among members of P could conform both to R and to R. 29 4 models He later in the book introduces a more realistic version of the definition where the specification “almost” is inserted before every instance of “everyone” (Lewis, 1969, p. 78). The definition captures the coordination problem that Lewis discusses in game theoretic style in his first chapter. Instead of contrasting his definition of social norms to conventions, let us instead consider the related definition of social norms from the Cristina Bicchieri (2006) book The Grammar of Society: Let R be a behavioral rule for situations of type S, where S can be represented as a mixed-motive game. We say that R is a social norm in a population P if there exists a sufficiently large subset Pcf ⊂ P such that, for each individual i ∈ Pcf : 1. Contingency: i knows that a rule R exists and applies to a situation of type S; 2. Conditional preference: i prefers to conform to R in situations of type S on the condition that (a) and either (b) or (b’) holds. (a) Empirical Expectations: i believes that a sufficiently large subset of P conforms to R in situations of type S; (b) Normative expectations: i believes that a sufficiently large subset of P expects i to conform to R in situations of type S; (b’) Normative expectations with sanctions: i believes that a sufficiently large subset of P expects i to conform to R in situations of type S, prefers i to conform, and may sanction behavior. (Bicchieri, 2006, p. 11) One problem with Lewis’s definition is that a convention is defined per “recurrent situation”. Trivially there are no such things as recurrent situations. Every situation is unique in at least its extension in time and space. This suggests that Lewis intended something more like “type of situation”, which is the concept Bicchieri’s definition explicitly employs. Starting out with static types of situations may still be problematic though. In Paper 1 we 30 4.3 Models of social norms show why and generalize the categorization such that social norms are defined per dynamic set of situations. Another aspect of Lewis’s definition that is limiting, which Bicchieri’s avoids, is the use of common knowledge. Common knowledge implies that something is not only known by everyone, but also that everyone knows that everyone knows and that this fact is known by everyone, and so on. This idealization lead to quite different behavior than more relaxed, and thereby more realistic, assumption of knowledge. The use of common knowledge in Lewis’s definition has been widely critiqued (e.g. Binmore (2008)). In Lewis’s definition, the coordinative nature of the situation under conventions is apparent. In Bicchieri’s definition less so, not least as she talks about mixed-motive games. The coordinative nature of social norms, however, stem from the condition (a) of her definition, the empirical expectations. I.e. given a social norm we only want to follow it if we think that a critical mass of the others will do so. To think about the definitions, and their game-theoretic implications, let us consider an example. First, note that social life is rife with conventions and social norms. Every day most of us just walk through conforming seamlessly. The equilibrium selection range from the arbitrary, such as on what side of the road to drive on, to cases where one equilibrium outcome is strongly preferred. Our example is of the latter kind: Imagine a population where everyone prefers a non-littered park to a littered one, even if it means that all (including themselves) must make an effort not to litter. This strategic situation is assumed to be a mixed-motive game. Agents prefer to be lazy, but would enjoy a pristine park. Let the payoffs be given by the matrix in Figure 4.3. This game has a unique equilibrium, to litter (Litter, Litter). The game is an instance of the well-known prisoner’s dilemma. A social norm may, however, Litter Do not litter Litter 1 3 Do not litter 0 2 Figure 4.3: A prisoner’s dilemma example — styled as littering make a second equilibrium possible. If there is an anti-littering norm, litter- 31 4 models ers may be frowned upon, or worse. This transforms the prisoner’s dilemma, with its unique bad equilibrium, into a stag hunt (recall Figure 4.2). In the new game (Do not litter, Do not litter) is the payoff-dominant equilibrium, and (Litter, Litter) is the risk-dominant one. Now, if an agent would expect the others to keep littering, there is still no reason for her to make an extra effort not to. Hence, the population may still be stuck in the risk-dominant equilibria despite the unanimous preference for the payoff-dominant one. Stated differently, it makes no sense for any one member of the population to change her behavior unilaterally. Any change needs to be synchronized. Not being able to credibly send such a synchronizing signal creates the hard problem of establishing a new social norm. This can be the case, e.g. if it is hard to predict what the others will do, or if it is unpractical to convey to a critical mass of the agents that a critical mass of the others will change from now on. Most challenging, however, may be the case where what would be “credible signals” already have been sent, but for some unknown reason failed to synchronize change. It begs the question: why would it work this time around? It is, unfortunately, not uncommon for groups or societies to get stuck in bad equilibria. Consider for instance parallels to the littering story above or systemic bribery and kickbacks (covered in the previous section). Another classic example is the prior non-use of helmets in the National Hockey League (Schelling, 1978/2006, p. 213). Players did want to wear a helmet, but being an early adopter made one look weak. When helmets were made mandatory, most players happily adopting the new standard. 4.4 in summary Many approaches have been taken to model corruption. In this thesis, we will only look at a particular type of corruption, namely systemic petty corruption. This kind of corruption is typically small-scale corrupt behavior taking place with-in a particular framework of social norms. This lead us to ask questions about how we can shift between frameworks, i.e. how we change social norms. 32 5 T H E PA P E R S 5.1 on fuzzy norms Social norms, as defined earlier, are instantiated per type of situation. This implies that a social norm is isolated from being influenced or influencing behavior in situations of a different type. In the real world, “types of situations” seem less hermetically sealed against influence. It is not least apparent if we consider a novel type of situation and agents are forced to guess what is “the right thing to do”. The guess will almost certainly hinge upon what they do in similar types of situations. The purpose of Paper 1 is to alter the Bicchieri (2006) social norm definition; and to make which situations a social norm has influence over dynamic. To achieve this, we employ the case-based decision framework, letting agents form belief about “the right thing to do” through a similarity and recencyweighted extrapolation of previous events. The dynamic categorization allows us to consider questions related to norm spillovers between situations. It also makes norm equilibria escapable and thus norm change, as we see in the real world, plausible. Before updating the definition, the paper showcases the dynamics of norm spillovers in a heavily idealized toy example. The example asks the question: When is it worthwhile to suspend all but one institution in order to reform the remaining one, given that we eventually will reintroduce all institutions as soon as the new behavior is established enough to spill over into them. 33 5 the papers 5.2 on coordination The obvious candidate scheme for a policy maker to change the prevailing social norm is to modify the incentive structure. The policy maker thus needs to ask herself: How much do one need to modify the payoffs to make a critical mass of the population believe that a critical mass of the population from this moment onwards will update their behavior? Classic game theory will not be very informative. The only thing a policy maker can learn from it is how much she would need to skew incentives in order to enforce her strategy of choice for any belief held about how others will play. This typically implies draconian fines. The need to skew incentives such that the preference ordering holds for all possible beliefs may seem extreme, but it is not just a theoretical fluke. Suppose that we draw a player randomly from the population, and the payoff is $1 if both players choose strategy A, and $2 if both choose strategy B. Everyone in this large population has been choosing A for as long as anyone can remember, and all players are indistinguishable. Now, suppose that the expected payoff of choosing A in the last two rounds have decreased by 1 cent per period; say by introduction of surveillance and policing. Until now, no one has updated their behavior. The expected payoff for A keeps shrinking. At what point will a critical mass of the population play B? Before the payoff for A vanishes? Perhaps, but in a large population of risk-averse members, perhaps not. The purpose of Paper 2 is not to give the perfect answer to the question “how big an incentive is required?”. This would require a fruitful theory about k-level belief formation. Instead, we show how in any coordinative situation we can introduce a fine and reward mechanism to sidestep the hard problem while the transfers tend to the infinitesimal as we get close to the benign equilibrium. We show how this mechanism can be implemented with two different types of surveillance. Even though this paper essentially does conceptual exploration it is evident given our discussion of social norms how the mechanism would relate to its coordinative game and thus to systemic petty corruption too. 34 5.3 On biases 5.3 on biases Sometimes belief formation makes us reflect deeply, employing rationality, history, incentives, signals, and estimations about the others’ belief formation process and so forth. In coordination games to ge a likelihood distribution of what a critical mass are likely to do. An introspective process, where one’s own ideas about the advantages of a certain strategic choice serves as a point of departure for reasoning. At any step of the belief formation there may be systematic biases skewing the outcome. The purpose of Paper 3 is to highlight how such biases interact with social norms and decision making. In particular we will look at a specific wellstudied bias called the better-than-average effect (BAE). BAE is the name for the tendency we have to overestimate our own good qualities compared to an average person in the population. For our purposes, imagine a population stuck in a bad equilibrium. A member of the population may feel that if there was a good enough chance of re-coordination he would take the chance and do the “right thing”. He is however biased to believe that he is more prone to do “the right thing” than the average member of the population, he will thus underestimate the chance of re-coordination and do nothing. We show that if this is systematically true in the population then the dynamic will be skewed such that signals need to be amplified considerably compared to an unbiased population. It would be possible to apply a more traditional game theoretic framework to examine what effect BAE has on the stability of petty corruption. The problem would then be viewed as a set of two player stag hunt games. In each of these games the players choose between the corrupt and the non-corrupt strategy. The outcomes are the same in all games except for the payoffs to being non-corrupt when the other player is corrupt. This payoff determines how risky it is to try for the Pareto-optimal outcome. Before deciding on what to do the players have formed a belief about at which level of risk other players become corrupt. The players also have a personal risk preference explicitly modeled since risk domination is a crucial part of a stag hunt game. These assumptions together with a reasonable updating rule for the belief formation would lead to the Pareto-optimal equilibrium in less risky games and the risk dominating in the riskier games. If we now introduce the BAE 35 5 the papers bias the threshold for how little risk there needs to be in a game to end up in the non-corrupt outcome shifts. Some games that previously were noncorrupt will now be corrupt due to the change in beliefs. This equilibrium shift is in line with the effect BAE has in the modeling framework we use in the paper. In Paper 4 and Paper 5 we show how BAE specifically may skew the dynamic in more than one direction. The papers empirically suggest how valueladen in-groups actually may reverse the bias. Specifically, one tend to overestimate the average in-group member in comparison to oneself. For our purposes here this showcase how even for well-established general biases the specifics of the networks, values and social identity can eliminate a bias, or even turn it on its head. 5.4 on collective actions Collective action and the dynamics of norms and conventions are related. Not least when change requires political action. In the case of corruption, we see how some kleptocracies manage to ramp up corruption levels to full state capture. In these cases there tend to be no formal democratic process, and for change to occur, some form of civil uprising may be needed. Less dramatically, collective action may also model the adoption of a novel social norms, where a few early adopters need to overcome the collective action problem. The purpose of Paper 6 is to suggest how we can extend the Mark Granovetter (1978) threshold model to include partial participation. In the new model, each individual has a de facto threshold per type of action. The per action threshold is made up of her idiosyncratic threshold, or “willingness to participate”, and how “effortful” she judge the given action to be for herself. Instead of the straightforward number of current participation that we get in Granovetter’s model we here have consider a “societal commitment level”. This level is the sum of the “signal value” of all actions taken, where the signal value is the median level of “effortfulness” of an action. To present the framework we consider the case of public uprisings. We show that if an instigator can invent ways to participate with any given signal value, then he can create a “stairway of actions”, such that half of the 36 5.4 On collective actions population (assuming that they initially would participate in some way) will escalate to full participation. We also show that a dictator may both increase and decrease the signal value of actions in order to undo an uprising. Collective action is of course also the problem faced by any population keen to adopt or abandon a social norm. 37 6 F UTURE RESEARCH Researchers have to make methodological choices; one such choice is where to land between methodological individualism and methodological holism. The Lewis (1969) book Conventions sparked a game-theoretical perspective on norms that since have been used to explore many aspects on how, why and to what extent social norms are formed. Some aspects of the social norm dynamics have however been reserved for holistic approaches. The intention with the case-based decision making in Paper 1 is to suggest a methodological individualist path forward to be able to explore questions previously reserved for holistic reasoning. Questions about how established norms change, how they can co-exist, and how to think about competing norms in the context of e.g. migration and multiculturalism. The theoretical framework of Paper 1 is in need of corroboration. Experimental work could help towards this end, and perhaps also give a firmer grip on the somewhat elusive “similarity” concept. In Paper 2, we present a mechanism design solution (of sorts) to coordination problems. In doing so, we also make simplifying assumptions that need to be properly discerned. For example: How stable are the results to the introduction of subjective utilities? To heterogeneous interaction patterns? To non-perfect inspection? Another interesting question is if real world agents would trust the mechanism and act in accordance with it, or not. A behavioral experiment would serve well as a first test. The take-home message of Paper 3 is that biases do matter in coordinative dynamics. The better-than-average effect is just one among many possible systematical biases affecting the social norm dynamics. Extra attention to how the dynamics may be skewed should thus be spent on social norms con- 39 6 future research cerning topics related to strong emotional responses, such as disgust, aggression, and sexual attraction. The last paper sets up a model to suggest the importance of technological innovation in resolving collective action problems. We concern ourselves in this paper with the implications for revolutions. There are other interesting applications of the escalation model, not least in resolving the collective action problem that is facing members of a population trying to establish a new social norm. A well-based understanding of how to establish, change and abolish social norms would greatly aid the fight against corruption in the world today. 40 BIBLIOGRAPHY Jason P Abbott. Cacophony or Empowerment? Analysing the Impact of New Information Communication Technologies and New Social Media in Southeast Asia. Journal of Current Southeast Asian Affairs, 30(4):3–31, 2012. Robert P Abelson. Psychological status of the script concept. American psychologist, 36(7):715, 1981. Daron Acemoglu and Thierry Verdier. Property rights, corruption and the allocation of talent: a general equilibrium approach. The Economic Journal, 108(450):1381–1403, 1998. Fauziah Ahmad, Chang Peng Kee, Normah Mustaffa, Faridah Ibrahim, Wan Amizah Wan Mahmud, and Dafrizal Dafrizal. Information propagation and the forces of social media in Malaysia. Asian Social Science, 8(5):71–76, 2012. M. S. Alam. Anatomy of corruption: An approach to the political economy of underdevelopment. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 48(4): 441–456, 1989. Vivi Alatas, Lisa Cameron, Ananish Chaudhuri, Nisvan Erkal, and Lata Gangadharan. Subject pool effects in a corruption experiment: A comparison of indonesian public servants and indonesian students. Experimental Economics, 12:113–132, 2009. 10.1007/s10683-008-9207-3. Mark D Alicke. Global self-evaluation as determined by the desirability and controllability of trait adjectives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49(6):1621, 1985. Mark D Alicke and Olesya Govorun. The better-than-average effect. In Mark D. Alicke, David A. Dunning, and Joachim I. Krueger, editors, Social Judgment. Studies in self and identity. Psychology Press, 2005. 41 Bibliography Mark D Alicke, Mary L Klotz, David L Breitenbecher, Tricia J Yurak, and Debbie S Vredenburg. Personal contact, individuation, and the better-thanaverage effect. Journal of personality and social psychology, 68(5):804, 1995. Taghreed Alqudsi-ghabra. Creative use of social media in the revolutions of Tunisia, Egypt & Libya. International Journal of Interdisciplinary Social Sciences, 6(6):147–158, 2012. Nicholas Ambraseys and Roger Bilham. Corruption kills. Nature, 469(7329): 153–155, 2011. Jens Chr. Andvig and Karl Ove Moene. How corruption may corrupt. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 13(1):63–76, January 1990. Jens Chr Andvig, Odd-Helge Fjeldstad, Inge Amundsen, Tone Sissener, and Tina Søreide. Corruption. A review of contemporary research. Chr. Michelsen Institute, 2001. Rossella Argenziano and Itzhak Gilboa. History as a coordination device. Theory and decision, 73(4):501–512, 2012. Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford University Press, 1980. Robert M Axelrod. The complexity of cooperation: Agent-based models of competition and collaboration. Princeton University Press, 1997. Larry Baron and Murray A Straus. Four theories of rape: A macrosociological analysis. Soc. Probs., 34:467, 1987. Abigail Barr and Danila Serra. Corruption and culture: An experimental analysis. Journal of Public Economics, 94(11-12):862–869, 2010. Kaushik Basu, Sudipto Bhattacharya, and Ajit Mishra. Notes on bribery and the control of corruption. Journal of Public Economics, 48(3):349–359, 1992. William J. Baumol. Entrepreneurship: Productive, unproductive, and destructive. Journal of Political Economy, 98(5):893–921, October 1990. Gary S Becker. Crime and punishment: An economic approach. The Journal of Political Economy, 76(2):169–217, 1968. 42 Bibliography Jenna Bednar, Yan Chen, Tracy Xiao Liu, and Scott Page. Behavioral spillovers and cognitive load in multiple games: An experimental study. Games and Economic Behavior, 74(1):12–31, 2012. Eric D. Beinhocker. The origin of wealth: Evolution, complexity and the radical remaking of economics. Random House, 2007. Mamoun Benmamoun, Morris Kalliny, and Robert A Cropf. The Arab Spring, MNEs, and virtual public spheres. Multinational Business Review, 20(1):26– 43, 2012. Marianne Bertrand, Simeon Djankov, Rema Hanna, and Sendhil Mullainathan. Obtaining a driver’s license in india: An experimental approach to studying corruption. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 122(4):1639–1676, November 2007. Cristina Bicchieri. Rationality and coordination. Cambridge University Press, 1997. Cristina Bicchieri. The grammar of society: The nature and dynamics of social norms. Cambridge University Press, 2006. Ken Binmore. Do conventions need to be common knowledge? Topoi, 27(1-2): 17–27, 2008. Ken Binmore and Larry Samuelson. The evolution of focal points. Games and Economic Behavior, 55(1):21–42, 2006. Gordon A Bloom and Michael D Smith. Hockey violence: a test of cultural spillover theory. Sociology of Sports Journal, 13:65–77, 1996. Andreas Blume and Andreas Ortmann. The effects of costless pre-play communication: Experimental evidence from games with pareto-ranked equilibria. Journal of Economic theory, 132(1):274–290, 2007. Roger Bowles and Nuno Garoupa. Casual police corruption and the economics of crime. International Review of Law and Economics, 17(1):75–87, March 1997. 43 Bibliography Jordi Brandts and David J Cooper. A change would do you good.... an experimental study on how to overcome coordination failure in organizations. The American Economic Review, pages 669–693, 2006. Jonathon D Brown. Evaluations of self and others: Self-enhancement biases in social judgments. Social Cognition, 4(4):353–376, 1986. Elizabeth I Bryant. The Iron Fist vs. the Microchip. Journal of Strategic Security, 5(2):1–26, 2012. Lisa Cameron, Ananish Chaudhuri, Nisvan Erkal, and Lata Gangadharan. Propensities to engage in and punish corrupt behavior: Experimental evidence from Australia, India, Indonesia and Singapore. Journal of Public Economics, 93(7-8):843–851, 2009. Timothy N. Cason, Anya C. Savikhin, and Roman M. Sheremeta. Behavioral spillovers in coordination games. European Economic Review, 56(2):233–245, 2012. Christopher Coyne, Russell Sobel, and John Dove. The non-productive entrepreneurial process. The Review of Austrian Economics, 23(4):333–346, December 2010. P. Cross. Not can, but will college teachers be improved? New Directions for Higher Education, 17:1–15, 1977. Val Curtis, Wolf Schmidt, Stephen Luby, Rocio Florez, Ousmane Touré, and Adam Biran. Hygiene: new hopes, new horizons. The Lancet infectious diseases, 11(4):312–321, 2011. M. Dartnell. Insurgency online: Elements for a theory of anti-government internet communications. Small Wars & Insurgencies, 10(3):116–135, 1999. L. Diamond. Liberation technology. Journal of Democracy, 21(3):69–83, 2010. Mario Diani. Networks and internet into perspective. Swiss Political Science Review, 17(4):469–474, 2011. Alan Doig and Robin Theobald. Corruption and democratisation. Routledge, 2013. 44 Bibliography Bin Dong, Uwe Dulleck, and Benno Torgler. Conditional corruption. Journal of Economic Psychology, 33(3):609–627, 2012. Alexandra Dunn. Unplugging a nation: State media strategy during Egypt’s January 25 uprising. Fletcher F. World Aff., 35:15, 2011. Emile Durkheim. Rules of sociological method. Simon and Schuster, 1895/1982. Ms Sharon Eicher. Corruption in international business: The challenge of cultural and legal diversity. Gower Publishing, Ltd., 2012. Jon Elster. Social norms and economic theory. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, pages 99–117, 1989. Joshua M Epstein. Generative social science: Studies in agent-based computational modeling. Princeton University Press, 2006. Kimmo Eriksson and Alexander Funcke. A below-average effect with respect to american political stereotypes on warmth and competence. Political Psychology, 2013. Kimmo Eriksson and Alexander Funcke. Humble self-enhancement religiosity and the better-than-average effect. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 5(1):76–83, 2014. Kimmo Eriksson and Brent Simpson. Emotional reactions to losing explain gender differences in entering a risky lottery. Judgment and Decision Making, 5(3):159–163, 2010. Mikael Eriksson, Ulrik Franke, Magdalena Granåsen, and David Lindahl. Social media and ICT during the Arab Spring. Technical report, FOI, the Swedish Defence Research Agency, 2013. FOI-R--3702--SE. Patricia M Fabiano, H Wesley Perkins, Alan Berkowitz, Jeff Linkenbach, and Christopher Stark. Engaging men as social justice allies in ending violence against women: Evidence for a social norms approach. Journal of American College Health, 52(3):105–112, 2003. Ernst Fehr and Urs Fischbacher. Third-party punishment and social norms. Evolution and human behavior, 25(2):63–87, 2004. 45 Bibliography Raymond Fisman and Edward Miguel. Corruption, norms, and legal enforcement: Evidence from diplomatic parking tickets. Journal of Political Economy, 115(6):1020–1048, December 2007. Michel Foucault. The order of things. Routledge, 1970/2001. Milton Friedman. Essays in positive economics, volume 231. University of Chicago Press, 1953. Roman Frigg and Julian Reiss. The philosophy of simulation: hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese, 169(3):593–613, 2009. Drew Fudenberg. The theory of learning in games, volume 2. MIT press, 1998. Drew Fudenberg, David M Kreps, and David K Levine. On the robustness of equilibrium refinements. Journal of Economic Theory, 44(2):354–380, 1988. Alexander Funcke. A skeptic embrace of simulation. In AAAI Fall Symposium: Complex Adaptive Systems, 2011. Patricia Funk. Governmental action, social norms, and criminal behavior. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics (JITE)/Zeitschrift für die gesamte Staatswissenschaft, pages 522–535, 2005. Nuno Garoupa. The theory of optimal law enforcement. Journal of economic surveys, 11(3):267–295, 1997. Stefano Ghirlanda and Magnus Enquist. A century of generalization. Animal Behaviour, 66(1):15–36, 2003. Gerd Gigerenzer and Reinhard Selten. Bounded rationality: The adaptative toolbox. Mit Press, 2002. Itzhak Gilboa and David Schmeidler. A theory of case-based decisions. Cambridge University Press, 2001. Itzhak Gilboa, Offer Lieberman, and David Schmeidler. Empirical similarity. The Review of Economics and Statistics, 88(3):433–444, 2006. 46 Bibliography Dennis A Gioia and Peter P Poole. Scripts in organizational behavior. Academy of Management Review, 9(3):449–459, 1984. Srihari Govindan and Robert Wilson. Nash equilibrium, refinements of. In Steven N. Durlauf and Lawrence E. Blume, editors, The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, 2008. Mark Granovetter. Threshold models of collective behavior. American Journal of Sociology, 83(6):1420–1443, 1978. Mark Granovetter. "the social construction of corruption". In Victor Nee and Richard Swedberg, editors, On capitalism. Stanford Univ. Press, Stanford, Calif., 2007. Mark Granovetter and Roland Soong. Threshold models of diffusion and collective behavior. The Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 9(3):165–179, 1983. Till Grüne-Yanoff. The explanatory potential of artificial societies. Synthese, 169(3):539–555, 2009. Ross Hammond. Endogenous transition dynamics in corruption: An agentbased computer model. Working paper no.19., Center on Social and Economic Dynamics. The Brookings Institution, 2000. John C Harsanyi. Games with incomplete information played by “bayesian” players, i-iii part i. the basic model. Management science, 14(3):159–182, 1967. John C Harsanyi and Reinhard Selten. A general theory of equilibrium selection in games. MIT Press Books, 1, 1988. N. Hassanpour. Media disruption exacerbates revolutionary unrest: Evidence from Mubarak’s natural experiment. In APSA 2011 Annual Meeting Paper, 2011. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1903351. Esther Hauk and Maria Saez-Marti. On the cultural transmission of corruption. Journal of Economic Theory, 107(2):311–335, 2002. Friedrich Hayek. The counter-revolution of science. Liberty Press Indianapolis, 1979. 47 Bibliography Trey Hedden and Jun Zhang. What do you think i think you think?: Strategic reasoning in matrix games. Cognition, 85(1):1 – 36, 2002. Arnold J Heidenheimer, Michael Johnston, and Victor T Le Vine. Political corruption: A handbook. Transaction Publishers New Brunswick, 1989. Steven J Heine and Darrin R Lehman. The cultural construction of selfenhancement: an examination of group-serving biases. Journal of personality and social psychology, 72(6):1268, 1997. Josef Hofbauer and Karl Sigmund. Evolutionary game dynamics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 40(4):479–519, 2003. Sören Holmberg and Bo Rothstein. Dying of corruption. Health Economics Policy and Law, 6(4):529, 2010. Vera Hoorens. Self-favoring biases, self-presentation, and the self-other asymmetry in social comparison. Journal of Personality, 63(4):793–817, 1995. Philip N Howard and Muzammil M Hussain. Democracy’s Fourth Wave?: Digital Media and the Arab Spring. Oxford University Press, 2013. David Hume. A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume. Clarendon Press, 1739/1896. David Hume. An enquiry concerning human understanding: A critical edition, volume 3. Oxford University Press, 1748/2000. David Hume. Of money. In Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary. Library of Economics and Liberty, 1752/1987. Paul Humphreys. The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169(3):615–626, 2009. Arvind K Jain. Corruption: a review. Journal of economic surveys, 15(1):71– 121, 2001. Daniel Kahneman. Thinking, fast and slow. Macmillan, 2011. 48 Bibliography Michihiro Kandori, George J Mailath, and Rafael Rob. Learning, mutation, and long run equilibria in games. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, pages 29–56, 1993. Louis Kaplow. A note on the optimal use of nonmonetary sanctions. Journal of Public Economics, 42(2):245–247, 1990. Rasma Karklins. The system made me do it : corruption in post-communist societies. M.E. Sharpe, Armonk, N.Y., 2005. Daniel Kaufmann, Aart Kraay, and Massimo Mastruzzi. Governance matters iv: Governance indicators for 1996 – 2004. Technical report, World Bank, 2005. Toshiji Kawagoe and Hirokazu Takizawa. Equilibrium refinement vs. level-k analysis: An experimental study of cheap-talk games with private information. Games and Economic Behavior, 66(1):238–255, 2009. Justin Kruger. Lake Wobegon be gone! the “below-average effect” and the egocentric nature of comparative ability judgments. Journal of personality and social psychology, 77(2):221, 1999. Oskar Kurer. Clientelism, corruption, and the allocation of resources. Public Choice, 77(2):259–273, 1993. Kalliopi Kyriakopoulou. Authoritarian states and internet social media: Instruments of democratisation or instruments of control? Human Affairs, 21(1):18–26, 2011. Johann Graf Lambsdorff. How corruption affects productivity. Kyklos, 56(4): 457–474, 2003. Claude Lévi-Strauss. Structural anthropology. Basic Books, 2008. David Lewis. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1969. Steve Loughnan, Peter Kuppens, Jüri Allik, Katalin Balazs, Soledad de Lemus, Kitty Dumont, Rafael Gargurevich, Istvan Hidegkuti, Bernhard Leidner, 49 Bibliography Lennia Matos, et al. Economic inequality is linked to biased self-perception. Psychological science, 22(10):1254–1258, 2011. Ringo Ma. Spread of SARS and war-related rumors through new media in China. Communication Quarterly, 56(4):376–391, 2008. Uskali Mäki. On the method of isolation in economics. Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 26:316–351, 1992. Uskali Mäki. Fact and fiction in economics: models, realism and social construction. Cambridge University Press, 2002. Jean-François Médard. Corruption in the neo-patrimonial states of subsaharan africa. Political Corruption: A Handbook, page 379, 2009. Fabio Méndez and Facundo Sepúlveda. Corruption, growth and political regimes: cross country evidence. European Journal of Political Economy, 22(1):82–98, 2006. Carl Menger. On the origins of money. Economic Journal, 2:239–55, 1892. Ajit Mishra. Persistence of corruption: some theoretical perspectives. World Development, 34(2):349–358, 2006. Part Special Issue (pp. 324-404). Corruption and Development: Analysis and Measurement. Alina Mungiu. Corruption: Diagnosis and treatment. Journal of democracy, 17(3):86–99, 2006. R.B. Myerson. Refinements of the nash equilibrium concept. International Journal of Game Theory, 7(2):73–80, 1978. Gunnar Myrdal. The challenge of world poverty. A world anti-poverty programme in outline. London, UK: Allen Lane Penguin Press., 1970. Rosemarie Nagel. Unraveling in guessing games: An experimental study. The American Economic Review, pages 1313–1326, 1995. Mohamed Nanabhay and Roxane Farmanfarmaian. From spectacle to spectacular: How physical space, social media and mainstream broadcast amplified 50 Bibliography the public sphere in Egypt’s ‘Revolution’. The Journal of North African Studies, 16(4):573–603, 2011. Elinor Ostrom. Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge university press, 1990. Lorenzo Pellegrini. Causes of corruption: a survey of cross-country analyses and extended results. In Corruption, development and the environment, pages 29–51. Springer, 2011. Andrés Perea. Epistemic game theory: Reasoning and choice. Cambridge University Press, 2012. Linda S Perloff and Barbara K Fetzer. Self–other judgments and perceived vulnerability to victimization. Journal of Personality and social Psychology, 50(3):502, 1986. Anna Persson, Bo Rothstein, and Jan Teorell. The failure of anti-corruption policies: A theoretical mischaracterization of the problem. QoG Working Paper Series, 2010:19, The Quality of Government Institute, University of Gothenburg, 2010. Anna Persson, Bo Rothstein, and Jan Teorell. Why anticorruption reforms fail-systemic corruption as a collective action problem. Governance, 2012. Alexander Peysakhovich and D Rand. Habits of virtue: creating norms of cooperation and defection in the laboratory. Available at SSRN 2294242, 2013. Plato. Protagoras. In Plato in Twelve Volumes, Vol. 3. Harvard University Press, 1967. A Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell. A note on optimal fines when wealth varies among individuals. The American Economic Review, pages 618–621, 1991. A Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell. Enforcement costs and the optimal magnitude and probability of fines. Journal of Law and Economics, pages 133–148, 1992. 51 Bibliography Reuters. China threatens tough punishment for online rumor spreading. http://www.reuters.com/article/2013/09/09/us-china-internetidUSBRE9880CQ20130909, 2013. Published September 9, 2013, retrieved October 18 2013. Juanita Riaño, Robin Hodess, Alastair Evans, Rebecca Dobson, Andre Doren, Jesse Garcia, Lydie Gerboin, Gypsy Guillen Kaiser, Heather McRobie, and Michael Sidwell. Global corruption barometer. Transparency International, 2010. Susan Rose-Ackerman. Corruption: A study in political economy. Academic Press New York, 1978. Susan Rose-Ackerman. Corruption and government: Causes, consequences, and reform. Cambridge University Press, 1999. Bo Rothstein. Social traps and the problem of trust. Cambridge University Press, 2005. Bo Rothstein. Anti-corruption: A big-bang theory. QoG Working Paper 2007:3, The Quality of Government Institute, University of Gothenburg, 2007. Bo Rothstein and Daniel Eek. Political corruption and social trust an experimental approach. Rationality and Society, 21(1):81–112, 2009. Larry Samuelson. Evolutionary games and equilibrium selection, volume 1. The MIT Press, 1998. Roger C Schank and Robert P Abelson. Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: An inquiry into human knowledge structures. Lawrence Erlbaum, 1977. Thomas C Schelling. Micromotives and macrobehavior. WW Norton & Company, 1978/2006. David Schmidt, Robert Shupp, James M Walker, and Elinor Ostrom. Playing safe in coordination games:: the roles of risk dominance, payoff dominance, and history of play. Games and Economic Behavior, 42(2):281–299, 2003. 52 Bibliography Reinhard Selten. Spieltheoretische behandlung eines oligopolmodells mit nachfrageträgheit: Teil i: Bestimmung des dynamischen preisgleichgewichts. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Staatswissenschaft/Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, pages 301–324, 1965. Donald Shepard. A two-dimensional interpolation function for irregularlyspaced data. In Proceedings of the 1968 23rd ACM national conference, pages 517–524. ACM, 1968. Roger N Shepard et al. Toward a universal law of generalization for psychological science. Science, 237(4820):1317–1323, 1987. Elizabeth Shove. Beyond the abc: climate change policy and theories of social change. Environment and planning. A, 42(6):1273, 2010. Brian Skyrms. The stag hunt and the evolution of social structure. Cambridge University Press, 2004. Jakub Steiner and Colin Stewart. Learning by similarity in coordination problems. Technical report, CERGE-EI, 2007. Robert Sugden. Spontaneous order. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3 (4):85–97, 1989. Robert Sugden. Salience, inductive reasoning and the emergence of conventions. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 79(1-2):35–47, 2011. Ola Svenson. Are we all less risky and more skillful than our fellow drivers? Acta Psychologica, 47(2):143–148, 1981. Shelley E Taylor and Jonathon D Brown. Illusion and well-being: a social psychological perspective on mental health. Psychological bulletin, 103(2): 193, 1988. John Thøgersen and Folke Ölander. Spillover of environment-friendly consumer behaviour. Journal of environmental psychology, 23(3):225–236, 2003. Daniel Treisman. The causes of corruption: a cross-national study. Journal of public economics, 76(3):399–457, 2000. 53 Bibliography Lars Udehn. The changing face of methodological individualism. Annual Review of Sociology, 28(1):479–507, 2002. John B Van Huyck, Raymond C Battalio, and Richard O Beil. Tacit coordination games, strategic uncertainty, and coordination failure. The American Economic Review, pages 234–248, 1990. Max Weber. Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. Univ of California Press, 1978. Michael Wenzel. The social side of sanctions: personal and social norms as moderators of deterrence. Law and Human Behavior, 28(5):547, 2004. Simcha B Werner. New directions in the study of administrative corruption. Public Administration Review, pages 146–154, 1983. Paul F Whiteley. Economic growth and social capital. Political Studies, 48(3): 443–466, 2000. H Peyton Young. The evolution of conventions. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, pages 57–84, 1993. Yoshinobu Zasu. Sanctions by social norms and the law: Substitutes or complements? The Journal of Legal Studies, 36(2):379–396, 2007. Jinqiu Zhao. A snapshot of Internet regulation in contemporary China: Censorship, profitability and responsibility. In Friederike Assandri and Dora Martins, editors, From Early Tang Court Debates to China’s Peaceful Rise, pages 141–151. Internet Society of China, 2009. Ezra W Zuckerman and John T Jost. What makes you think you’re so popular? Self-evaluation maintenance and the subjective side of the “friendship paradox”. Social Psychology Quarterly, pages 207–223, 2001. 54
© Copyright 2024