49 Stan. L. Rev. 887 Stanford Law Review April, 1997 Note PLANNING FOR LOVE: THE POLITICS OF PRENUPTIAL AGREEMENTS Allison A. Marstona Copyright (c) 1997 Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University; Allison A. Marston This note challenges the stereotypes that define the role of prenuptial agreements in contemporary American society. Specifically, this note questions the assumption that only the rich, the selfish, or the mercenary can benefit from a prenuptial contract. Allison Marston examines the increasing use of prenuptial agreements over the past twenty years and describes the types of people who should consider drafting them. Ms. Marston summarizes the law about prenuptial contracts and the kinds of provisions that courts will and will not enforce. She then places prenuptial agreements in a legal, historical, and psychological context. Ms. Marston argues that the villification of prenuptials is a curious, and even irrational, response to a document that merely supplants state-written contracts governing the disposition of assets at the end of a marriage, has a long history in Anglo-American society, and potentially improves communication on important issues before marriage. Nevertheless, this note acknowledges that many prenuptial agreements have been signed that disproportionately hurt one of the marital partners. Ms. Marston argues that the solution to this problem is not to limit the enforcement of these agreements but to seek to ensure that each party has full knowledge of his or her rights and has the opportunity to negotiate the terms of the contract. To this end, she concludes that courts should require that each party entering into a prenuptial agreement have had the benefit of consulting with independent counsel prior to the signing of the contract. This reform, not yet embraced by any jurisdiction, would preserve parties’ freedom of contract while preventing the coercion possible in negotiations that take place in the highly-charged atmosphere of an impending wedding. *888 ”All is prepared for sealing and signing, The contracts has been drafted as agreed; Approach the table, oh ye lovers pining, With hand and seal come execute the deed!” --Gilbert & Sullivan, The Sorcerer1 “For to be wise, and in love, was not given to the Gods themselves.” --Aphra Behn, The Confession of the New Married Couple2 Introduction A prenuptial agreement does not conjure an image of marital equality. Viewed by many as the province of the wealthy, the age disparate, the heartless, or the simply greedy, prenuptial agreements are often regarded with distrust and hostility. However, prenuptials may not deserve this unseemly reputation. This note examines the cultural and legal context of prenuptial agreements and argues that, with the proper legal safeguards and sufficient trust between spouses, they can be useful, even relationship enhancing, documents. In 1990, Modern Bride featured a lengthy article on this increasingly popular contract. Between pages devoted to wedding etiquette and bridal fashions, the magazine explained: Current trends toward delayed marriage, cohabitation, and rising divorce and remarriage rates have combined to create a new awareness of the seriousness of the marital contract and the far-reaching consequences that contract, once made, can have on individual lives. Thus, more and more couples feel the need to mix a little realism with romance, and they’re filling that need with premarital agreements, also called prenuptial or antenuptial contracts.3 After detailing the background, purpose, and legal implications of prenuptial agreements, the magazine advised readers to “[s] hare this article and your feelings about premarital contracts and some of the issues they address with your fiancé. Even if the two of you decide that a premarital contract isn’t for you, discussion about it will prove enlightening and worthwhile.”4 Interest in prenuptial agreements is not confined to the pages of bridal fashion; articles on prenuptial agreements have been appearing with increasing regularity in both scholarly literature5 and the popular press.6 Magazines as diverse as Cosmopolitan *889 and Money have recently featured stories describing various premarital agreements.7 While many prenuptial agreements detail the division of property or other assets upon death or divorce, they may also include provisions regulating the ongoing marriage.8 One such agreement, drawn up by a New Mexico couple, has received national attention.9 The prenuptial that Rex and Teresa LeGalley created runs sixteen single-spaced pages and specifies minute details of their daily lives, such as how much money per week they get for expenses ($70), what kind of gas they will buy (Chevron unleaded), and how often they will engage in “healthy sex” (three to five times per week).10 Why such intimate specificity? Noting that the divorce rate for first marriages has reached 54 percent, Rex LeGalley comments, “[n] obody plans to fail. . . . But a lot of people fail to plan.”11 Popular reaction to the LeGalleys’ detailed planning has been mixed, revealing the controversy that surrounds contemporary prenuptial agreements. Marriage counselors have “extolled it as a progressive example of premarital guidance counseling that can solve problems before they arrive.”12 In contrast, a New York “celebrity” divorce lawyer condemns the agreement, stating that “[y]ou can’t legislate for the human heart. . . . You should have faith in the person you are marrying, not in a document.”13 For Teresa LeGalley, however, writing the contract constituted an integral part of their courtship.14 The responses to the LeGalley’s extreme prenuptial agreement reveal the vast range of attitudes engendered by these contracts, a hybrid of romance and optimism crossed with pragmatism and individualistic concerns. Many people have a viscerally negative reaction to prenuptials and declare they “would never sign one.” On the other hand, professionals in the field have extoled the agreements for the open communication and opportunity for ex ante problem solving they bring to a marriage. This note evaluates prenuptial agreements by examining their cultural and legal context. Despite the LeGalleys’ interesting example, this note focuses on prenuptial agreements that distribute assets upon divorce or death. Part I discusses the general purpose of prenuptial agreements, examines their rising popularity, and details those couples who, according to experts and the popular press, should enter into them. The note then discusses general objections to and endorsements of prenuptial agreements. Part II explores the basic law governing *890 prenuptial agreements and describes their treatment by courts, which has evolved from outright rejection to widespread acceptance. Part III argues that hostility towards prenuptials ignores the ramifications of the state-imposed marital contract, finds little support in Anglo-American marital history, and contradicts recent psychological literature about the importance of communication in marriage. The note then briefly describes the cultural context of marriage, contrasting the American ideal of romantic absolutism with other cultures’ beliefs about the marital relationship. Finally, Part IV argues that states should make consultation with independent legal counsel a prerequisite for the enforceability of prenuptial agreements. This reform preserves the benefits of the freedom to contract while seeking to ensure that parties do not unknowingly waive valuable legal rights. I. Contemporary Prenuptial Agreements A. The Purpose of Prenuptial Agreements Inescapably, prenuptial agreements are about money. They focus on property and support rights upon the legal or natural end of the marriage.15 Altering the state-imposed default formula for spousal rights provides a central purpose for many prenuptials.16 Since the agreements provide for the distribution of assets upon death or divorce, they can serve an important role in estate planning.17 Prenuptials also allow couples to specify which assets should be considered marital property and which assets should be treated as personal property upon the dissolution of the marriage.18 Prenuptial agreements allow couples to write a “road map,” that structures their finances according to a mutually predetermined plan.19 In addition, Prenuptial agreements enable an individual to protect a family business or specific piece of property from possible claims by a former spouse.20 *891 B. The Increasing Popularity of Prenuptial Agreements More couples are writing prenuptial agreements than ever before. One report estimates that the number of prenuptial agreements tripled between 1978 and 1988 and has steadily increased ever since.21 Of marrying couples, approximately 5 percent (about 50,000) sign prenuptials each year.22 Furthermore, an estimated 20 percent of remarriages feature a prenuptial agreement.23 Not surprisingly, prenuptials have attained prominence in the national imagination. As one commentator noted, “[w]hen a couple heading down the aisle today is well-off, the curiosity once centered on a dowry is likely to concern the terms of a prenuptial agreement.”24 Commentators have identified several reasons for the rising popularity of prenuptial agreements. The prevalence of divorce and remarriage has prompted couples to plan more carefully, realistically, and independently for their economic futures.25 Currently, over forty percent of American marriages involve a “second or higher-order marriage” for one or both of the parties;26 an estimated 60 percent of these higher-order marriages will end in divorce.27 As one government study concluded, “[a] large segment of the United States adult population flows into and out of several marital categories during [its] life course.”28 This pattern caused one commentator to note that, “[i]n the United States, there is now a fundamental right to marry, and marry, and marry.”29 In addition, women increasingly bring tangible assets to the marriage, as a result of both their rising participation in the labor force30 and the older age at which they are likely to marry for the first time.31 These women use prenuptial agreements to protect their individually held assets. Finally, courts’ greater willingness to enforce provisions of prenuptials provides an obvious reason for *892 the increasing use of these agreements.32 Whatever the reasons underlying a couple’s decision to write a prenuptial agreement, it is clear that the aggregate number of couples signing prenuptials has been steadily, even spectacularly, increasing. C. Who Needs Prenuptial Agreements? Although some experts assert that “everyone contemplating marriage should consider drawing up a prenuptial agreement,”33 most commentators believe that prenuptials are only occasionally necessary.34 Wealthy couples have long been prime candidates for prenuptials. Famous couples who have entered into prenuptial agreements include John F. Kennedy, Jr. and Carolyn Bessette, Michael Jackson and Lisa Marie Presley, and Madonna and Sean Penn. Besides protecting their fortunes, prenuptials allow the rich and famous to circumvent some of the unpleasant discovery proceedings endemic to a contested divorce.35 Couples in which one or both of the partners has been previously divorced may also have good reason to seek the protections of a prenuptial agreement. Often the parties wish to protect their assets for their children of former marriages. Likewise, a previously divorced fiancé may use a prenuptial agreement to prevent a reoccurrence of the bitterness engendered by the dissolution of the prior marriage.36 Parties also employ prenuptial agreements to protect family wealth or businesses from potential disputes that arise upon death or divorce.37 Financial experts advise people who have a “reasonable sum of money,” estimated by some at $500,000,38 and two-income families who wish to protect individual assets to enter into prenuptial agreements.39 Other favorable candidates for prenuptials include couples that purchase a home before the wedding,40 couples *893 in which one spouse bankrolls the other’s education,41 and couples in which one spouse has substantial debt.42 Although technically not a prenuptial agreement, gay and lesbian couples may also draw up agreements specifying the division of the couple’s assets in the event the relationship terminates.43 D. The Cost of Prenuptial Agreements The media report that drafting a prenuptial agreement costs between $1000 and $5000.44 A particularly complicated agreement may cost as much as $25,000.45 Articles written by lawyers for other lawyers stress the difficulty of drafting enforceable prenuptial agreements. As one article notes, “[t]here are few areas of our law which are so emotionally charged and expose attorneys to such ominous risks as antenuptial agreements. The stakes are inordinately high, and one misstep can spell disaster for both client and attorney.”46 Another publication warns that “improperly drafted or executed premarital agreements spawn litigation. And like wills, premarital agreements are unexploded mines ticking away in your closed-file storage room. Proceed with care.”47 Given the risks for lawyers and the resulting cost of drafting the agreement, it is unlikely that prenuptials will prove a feasible option for all couples. E. Common Objections to Prenuptial Agreements Detractors voice many objections to prenuptial agreements. First, they consider them a bad beginning for a marriage. As an article advising lawyers explains: You are viewed as an impediment by individuals focused on one of life’s strongest emotions: love. Your attempt to interject rational and logical problem solving to negotiate a complex contract is often unappreciated. Although your client may declare a need for the agreement and may have sought out your services, to a greater or lesser degree, neither party appreciates your intrusion into their idyllic expectations. No one wants to deal with a subject that is the antithesis of all of the other acts and thoughts at this moment in their lives. You have asked them to contemplate divorce and death.48 *894 In addition to these inherently grim features, prenuptial agreements can also be seen as betraying a lack of trust in one’s fiancé.49 Other objections include allegations that prenuptials dampen the romance of engagement,50 introduce the grasping “morals of the marketplace” into an intimate relationship,51 and place too much emphasis on the good of the individual at the expense of the good of the couple.52 Religious figures argue that prenuptials distract couples from the “five C’s” of marriage: “communication, commitment, conflict resolution, children, and church.”53 As one clergyman cautions, “[p]eople have to be prepared for the idea that marriage is work. It’s not just a merging of assets.”54 But the main attack against prenuptial agreements is the allegation that one party may not be treating his or her fiancé in a fair manner. Not surprisingly, the wealthier party may impose terms on the less well-off party.55 Many critics argue that prenuptial agreements overwhelmingly hurt women by virtue of their inferior bargaining position.56 Certainly, women are more likely than men to contest prenuptial agreements.57 However, some experts argue that prenuptials may actually benefit women because “[w]omen, who have traditionally had less power, may feel their rights are best protected if they are formalized.”58 These issues are explored in more detail in the last section of this note, which advocates that all contracting couples seeking the benefits of a prenuptial agreement be represented by independent counsel.59 F. The Benefits of Prenuptial Agreements Notwithstanding the concern voiced by detractors, advocates of prenuptial agreements argue that negotiating a prenuptial may save a couple from a disastrous marriage. A New York lawyer says of couples who break up during *895 negotiations, “I don’t think I prevented a marriage. I think I prevented a divorce.”60 Others argue, however, that negotiating and signing a prenuptial agreement has no effect on a couple’s relationship: “Many people sign an agreement, put it in a drawer and never look at it again . . . . They have a happy marriage, or contrary to what a spouse may be obligated to do, even if they’re divorced, they may give more than they’re required to.”61 From this perspective, prenuptial agreements certainly do not jeopardize a good marriage. Experts point out that prenuptial agreements force couples to grapple with a major source of disagreement before the wedding and allow for better communication about finances once couples are married.62 One article stated, “[c]ongratulations on your engagement! Have you brought up the ‘M’ word with your future spouse yet? That’s the ‘M’ word as in money, not marriage. If not, do it now, because the success of your marriage may depend on how you and your spouse communicate about money matters.”63 Rather than demonstrating a lack of faith in the motives of the other party, proponents of prenuptials contend that an agreement may actually be an act of good faith, demonstrating that no secrets exist between the parties.64 One sample prenuptial agreement reads: [X] and [Y] intend to marry subsequent to the date of this agreement; and because of their mutual feelings of love and honor for each other, the parties enter into this agreement to eliminate, as much as possible, any future impediment(s), to their marriage that might arise from uncertainties as to their respective financial responsibilities to each other.65 Thus, proponents believe the alleged negative effects of prenuptial agreements--such as weakened trust between the parties-may actually be less likely to occur with an agreement than without one.66 Yet these same advocates point out that the decision to enter into a prenuptial agreement “must be the result of a process the couple goes through and must not be imposed upon them by their lawyers.”67 Prenuptials often aid family harmony in second marriages, especially for children from the first marriage worried about their inheritance. “It’s good to get [property issues] out up front so the children [of previous marriages] feel good about the marriage . . . . It reduces family tension because everyone understands they are not being cut out of family assets.”68 *896 Since 50 percent of American couples divorce,69 people frequently sign prenuptials hoping to avoid much of the trauma associated with their break-up. “Prenuptial agreements seek to head off the nastier aspects of a divorce, if one does occur, and to avoid the maneuvering over assets that can escalate in the midst of a divorce.”70 Courts have argued that prenuptial agreements might actually encourage marriage: If previously married individuals can’t contract to avoid the most unpleasant aspects of divorce, they might simply choose not to get married.71 Some proponents even believe that prenuptial agreements should be mandatory for all couples wishing to marry.72 “Legal scholars and sociologists now generally favor such contracts as a way to protect individuality and to help clarify important issues for both parties in the relationship. Contracts allow the courts, attorneys, parties to the contract, and others to reflect on the priorities and commitments of the couple.”73 Whatever one might think of the social implications of such a requirement, it is unlikely that any state will institute such a policy given the costs associated with prenuptial agreements.74 As evidence of their effects is sparse, whether prenuptials help or hinder marriages may never be known. The individuality of each marriage decision makes generalization difficult. Nevertheless, prenuptial agreements continue to generate much controversy. That controversy arises from the central tension embodied in the agreements: their unique mix of a business and a romantic transaction. In the words of one lawyer, a prenuptial agreement “is like drawing up a divorce in advance. Philosophically, I don’t approve of them. As a lawyer, I do.”75 Judith Younger, a scholar who has written frequently about prenuptial agreements, notes, As a genre, [prenuptial agreements] exhibit a fascinating duality; on the plane of time, they are venerable, yet voguish; in terms of social policy, they are, at once, favorites and black sheep; and in order to be valid, they must comply with two sets of rules, those applicable to ordinary contracts and those designed especially for them.76 *897 The dualities Younger has identified inform the debate surrounding prenuptial agreements and must be acknowledged in any effort to reform the law governing these contracts. II. The Basic Law Governing Prenuptial Agreements A. The Pre-1970 Approach: Judicial Paternalism Until 1970, prenuptial agreements providing for the disposition of assets upon divorce were unenforceable in the United States. Prenuptial agreements that addressed the property rights of a surviving spouse at widowhood, however, had long been upheld in many states.77 Courts had voided prenuptial agreements that contemplated divorce for many reasons: the contracts were legally improper because they were “contrary to the concept of marriage”; they would cause the institution of marriage to lose its “dignity and sacredness”; they would mire the courts in ceaseless, minor litigation; they would impoverish wives and leave them dependent on state support; they would encourage “the property-owning spouse to abandon his marriage partner”; they would make people endure bad marriage conditions for fear of losing all material possessions; and they would usurp the traditional function of the equity courts to settle divorce rights.78 As the Alaska Supreme Court noted, The traditional common law view was that prenuptial agreements in contemplation of divorce . . . were inconsistent with the sanctity of marriage and the state’s interest in preserving marriage and maintaining the financial security of divorced persons. Courts uniformly viewed these agreements as inherently conducive to divorce and as allowing a husband to circumvent his legal duty to support his wife.79 Courts also treated the negotiations preceding prenuptial agreements with scepticism and outright paternalism. For example, one nineteenth century court worried that women would be unable to contract freely: “What person so exposed to imposition as a woman, contracting personally with her intended husband, just on the eve of marriage, at a time when all prudential considerations are likely to be merged in a confiding attachment, or suppressed from an honorable instinct and sentiment of delicacy?”80 In retrospect, it seems inevitable that these archaic attitudes would give way in the face of a changing American society. B. Prenuptial Agreements Enter the World of Contracts The bellwether case came from Florida. In 1970, the Florida Supreme Court held in Posner v. Posner81 that prenuptial agreements that contemplate divorce “should no longer be held to be void ab initio as ‘contrary to public *898 policy.’ “82 Other courts and states followed suit,83 and prenuptial agreements that include divorce provisions are now generally enforceable in all states. The paternalism demonstrated by earlier courts has decreased as overall enforceability has risen. “No longer will the courts in viewing antenuptial contracts invariably begin ‘with the realization that between persons in the prematrimonial state there is a mystical, confidential relationship which anesthetizes the senses of the female partner.”’84 Contemporary courts review prenuptial agreements for both procedural and substantive fairness. Procedural fairness demands that the parties enter into the agreement voluntarily and that each fully discloses to the other his or her assets.85 Prospective spouses are considered “to be in a confidential or fiduciary relationship . . . [and] are held to standards of the highest good faith and fair dealing.”86 Under the rubric of substantive fairness, courts may assess the parties’ objectives, their financial situations, their physical and emotional conditions, their other family commitments or obligations, their expected contributions to the marriage, their business or financial expertise, and their financial needs.87 In sum, prenuptial agreements must adhere to the normal rules of contract: They must be entered into voluntarily, “made by competent parties, supported by consideration, comply with any applicable statute of frauds and be consistent with public policy.”88 However, unlike ordinary contracts, the parties need not show consideration; the marriage itself fulfills that prerequisite.89 Nevertheless prenuptial agreements remain more vulnerable to attack than commercial contracts because of special standards that govern their enforcement. Provisions of prenuptial agreements that conflict with public policy will not be enforced. The most common types of provisions that courts have held invalid contravening public policy concern children, including waiver of child support, custody, or visitation rights.90 In addition, courts will void clauses that allow a party to profit from or otherwise “encourage” procuring a divorce from their spouse.91 However, courts have held that prenuptial agreements with unequal *899 provisions for the husband and wife, often the primary reason for entering into the agreement, are not contrary to public policy.92 In some states, courts have even allowed one party to eliminate completely the other party’s marital estate.93 Nevertheless, courts will invalidate agreements that make one party financially dependent on the state.94 C. Uniform Premarital Agreement Act Standardizes Review Courts’ treatments of prenuptial agreements have become further standardized since the promulgation of the Uniform Premarital Agreement Act (“UPAA”)95 in 1983, which has subsequently been adopted by over half the states.96 At the forefront of the trend towards greater enforceability, the UPAA treats prenuptials like ordinary contracts. Indeed, the Act has been strongly criticized because of its relative insensitivity to the doctrine of unconscionability, a standard defense to the enforcement of even purely commercial contracts.97 Under the UPAA’s section 6, an agreement must be unconscionable and there must have been nondisclosure by one of the parties to render it unenforceable; neither unconscionability nor nondisclosure is sufficient to void a prenuptial agreement.98 Despite the generous enforcement standard provided by the UPAA, many commentators call for greater scrutiny of prenuptial agreements. The features of antenuptial contracts that justify greater state supervision than is ordinarily exerted over commercial contracts include the special legal status of the marriage relationship in our society, the trust and confidence the law expects of marriage partners, the emotional intensity surrounding the desire to marry, the common belief that the marriage will last forever, and the potential lack of understanding of the economic rights that are being waived. This coalescence of factors, when viewed against the backdrop of persistent gender inequality in the marketplace, warrants a relaxation of the rules of contract to accommodate other social values.99 Whatever the standard courts use for evaluating prenuptials, they are currently much more willing to enforce prenuptials than they were thirty years ago. Couples who wish to write an enforceable contract need only decide what provisions to include. *900 D. The Scope of Prenuptial Agreements Many magazine articles and books offer advice on what provisions to include in a prenuptial agreement. A book written specifically for the layperson suggests that a prenuptial contain the following clauses: duration of the contract; division of property; division of income; treatment of debt; specification of support and living expenses; decisions about surnames, birth control, children, housework, domicile, religion, wills and inheritance; a blueprint for the resolution of arguments; and a provision for dissolution of the marriage.100 Nevertheless, courts generally will not enforce provisions of prenuptials that regulate conditions of the ongoing marriage, citing the “well-established rule that it is improper for courts to intervene in a married couple’s daily domestic affairs.”101 One wonders, however, if courts simply do not want to enforce agreements that provide that a treasured snowball collection may be kept in the freezer, that one party must walk the dog, or that a husband has the option to sue for divorce if his wife gains more than fifteen pounds.102 Another commentator has advanced a different theory for the unenforceability of these provisions. Citing a case in which the court would not enforce a provision that guaranteed that the husband’s mother could live with the married couple, the author notes, The court seemed to suggest that prospective spouses might, in their enthusiasm about their future marriage, make promises to one another that human nature would prevent them from performing as the marriage progressed. It is likely that many courts, while not saying so explicitly, have refused to recognize premarital contract regulating the ongoing marriage not because they violate “public policy,” but because they violate human nature.103 In contrast, courts will generally enforce agreements that detail property distribution at divorce or death. Mere legal enforceability, however, has not changed many people’s attitudes about prenuptial agreements. A true understanding of the potentials and pitfalls of prenuptials requires examination of the legal, historical, and psychological context surrounding the agreements. III. Prenuptial Agreements in Context Despite the increasing enforceability of prenuptials and the wealth of information available to couples contemplating such agreements, many couples still feel money and romance are incompatible subjects for a contract. Romantic love remains an important force in American culture--so strong that most *901 couples believe they will never divorce, despite the high divorce rate in the United States. In a study of engaged couples applying for marriage licenses, researchers discovered that there was a significant discrepancy between what most couples know about divorce and what they think their chances are of getting divorced. Respondents in the study correctly answered that the U.S. divorce rate is approximately 50 percent. As for their own futures, “the median response of the marriage license applicants was 0% when assessing the likelihood that they personally would divorce.”104 Only 1.5 percent of the respondents expressed any interest in entering into a prenuptial agreement, and only 4.5 percent indicated any interest in consulting with an attorney before marriage.105 As the authors of the study concluded, “the difficulty . . . for young adults . . . is coming to terms with the non-romantic aspects of marriage in a culture that exalts romanticism in personal relationships.”106 Nevertheless, prenuptial agreements should not be seen as antithetical to American culture. There are compelling legal, historical, and psychological reasons why these contracts hold an important and logical space in the marital cycle. A. The Legal Context of Marriage Many engaged couples fail to realize that even without a prenuptial agreement, any two people who marry enter into a contract. This contract is written by the state without any input from the marrying couple. It has been labeled the “marriage contract.”107 The idea of a contract within marriage will strike many as incongruous, for marriage is typically thought of as the most intimate and private social relationship, while a contract is typically regarded as the prototype of rational business transactions. And yet, upon closer examination, it will become clear that there is an implicit contract that governs every marriage--an unwritten contract that is imposed by law.108 The state’s involvement in the marriage “contract” reflects the special status marriage has long enjoyed in the common law tradition. In 1888 the Supreme Court declared of marriage: [It] is not so much the result of private agreement, as of public ordination. In every enlightened government, it is preëminently the basis of civil institutions, and thus an object of the deepest public concern. In this light, marriage is more than a contract. It is not a mere matter of pecuniary consideration. It is a great public institution, giving character to our whole civil polity.109 *902 This characterization of marriage as a “public institution” justified state intrusion into the intimate details of a marital relationship. As the California Civil Code declares, “[m]arriage is a personal relation arising out of a civil contract between a man and a woman, to which the consent of the parties capable of making that contract is necessary.”110 This contract includes the provision, for example, that “each [party] owes the other financial support.”111 Not only a contractual relationship, marriage is a legal status. “As soon as a couple marries, . . . the marriage relationship itself is defined as a legal status with consequences--economic and personal obligations during and after marriage--that are set and controlled by society through laws and judicial interpretations of laws.”112 The state also dictates the default terms of the marriage contract by governing the distribution of property and assets at the end of the marriage. When a man and woman are about to marry, “they are contemplating a uniquely state-supported relationship of human intimacy, a relationship that has always received special governmental protection. Only the state recognizes the means of creating the relationship, and it likewise holds a monopoly on the means of dissolution.”113 All states define marriage, in part, as an economic partnership, and the divorce statutes reflect that belief.114 Despite the importance of the state-created marriage contract, many engaged couples display a stunning lack of knowledge about the terms of the agreement. The marriage license applicants in the above study115 scored only slightly better than chance when questioned about various state divorce statutes.116 Not only are many couples ignorant of the laws on the books, there is also inherent uncertainty in judicial construction of these statutes. When you enter into this contract by saying “I do,” you are subscribing to a whole system of rights, obligations and responsibilities. Unlike most other contracts, however, you never get the chance to read the terms or the fine print provisions because the provisions are unwritten and the penalties for breach unspecified. In no other area are contracting parties so in the dark.117 Nor does the marriage contract, as currently written, take into account the many circumstances that a divorcing couple may face. Instead, the courts’ interpretation of these statutes is based on judicial perception of the “typical” couple. “When it comes to marriage and divorce, it is costly to be different.”118 *903 For example, traditional divorce law assumes that all families are first families.119 As a result, traditional law fails to specify how the claims of a family from a second marriage should weigh against the needs of the family from the first marriage.120 Despite the tradition of state involvement in the marital relationship, the states have been increasingly willing to let parties contract the terms of their own marriage. This development parallels a trend throughout family law in which private norm creation and decisionmaking have trumped state-imposed rules.121 This evolution is a response to the rapid social change in American family patterns over the last thirty years.122 Decisions construing family law have begun to place more emphasis on the individual than on the marital unit. In 1972, for example, the Supreme Court stated that “[t]he marital couple is not an independent entity with a mind and heart of its own, but an association of two individuals each with a separate intellectual and emotional makeup.”123 In one commentator’s view, the Court’s emphasis has evolved from viewing marriage as an important public institution, to viewing “marriage as essentially a private relationship, the main purpose of which [is] to promote individual happiness and personal fulfillment.”124 Prenuptial agreements allow couples to take advantage of this individual autonomy and construct their own version of the marriage contract. These agreements allow couples to contract out of the state model’s emphasis on the traditional family and, if they wish, to interject a more egalitarian model than that imposed by the state.125 There seems to be little opposition to the view that couples should be allowed to write prenuptial agreements. “It would be perverse to allow a prospective spouse more freedom to arrange the terms of a new car loan than to determine the structure of the most intimate of relationships.”126 Since the state already imposes a contract onto marrying couples who have not made alternative arrangements, it is ironic that many couples scoff at the suggestion that they enter into a prenuptial agreement. From a legal standpoint, prenuptial agreements give couples more freedom and autonomy than they *904 would have if they simply relied on the state default rules. It is undeniable, however, that many couples prefer to trust their future disputes to state resolution rather than endanger the aura of trust surrounding the impending marriage with a prenuptial agreement. B. The Historical Context of Marriage Contemporary divorce statutes are the current manifestation of a long tradition of social and legal mechanisms that distribute the assets acquired by a family unit at its dissolution.127 The conjunction of marriage and property has deep roots in AngloAmerican history.128 In Anglo-Saxon society, marriage had a distinctly contractual flavor. The groom purchased the wife’s guardianship, and thus the right to marry her, with a price fixed according to her rank in society.129 The contract was fulfilled, not by the religious ceremony, but by “the betrothal, the promise to marry and pay the weotuma,” or bride price.130 In the Middle Ages people viewed marriage as a contract that included a transfer of property. In the early middle ages all that marriage implied in the eyes of the laity seems to have been a private contract between two families concerning property exchange, which also provided some financial protection to the bride in case of the death of her husband or desertion or divorce by him.131 By the fifteenth century, couples were entering into marital contracts that guaranteed the wife a portion of her husband’s lands upon his death.132 England has enforced prenuptial contracts since at least the sixteenth century.133 The sixteenth and seventeenth centuries saw a continued emphasis on the importance of financial considerations at marriage. Issues of property and power dominated marriage negotiations.134 For people of property,135 a marriage featured *905 several stages. The first stage was a written contract between the parents of the bride and groom indicating the financial arrangements. The second consisted of the spousals, or contract, which was a formal exchange before witnesses of the promise to marry. The third stage was the obtaining of the license, the fourth the wedding in church, and the fifth the sexual consummation.136 Except for landed heiresses who brought real property to the marriage, prenuptial contracts most frequently treated the twin subjects of portion and jointure.137 The portion consisted of a substantial cash sum that the bride gave to the groom’s family, while the jointure guaranteed the bride an annuity if she survived her husband. If the couple did not contract for the jointure, upon the death of her husband the wife was entitled to her dower portion, “one-third of the [husband’s] lands and tenements.”138 “Marriage, therefore, always involved a transfer of a significant amount of real or personal property from the family of the bride to that of the groom, with a reverse commitment in the future of a significant proportion of annual income.”139 Despite the formality of the English system for people of means, there still existed a remarkable degree of independence in these marriages. Since the twelfth century, couples wishing to marry have needed neither their parents’ approval nor a religious ceremony to cement the matrimonial bonds.140 It was also normal for the parties to begin their courtship themselves, rather than rely on matchmakers or marriage brokers.141 In one historian’s words, “[t]he English, with their separate ownership system of marital property, . . . with their abundant evidence of do-it-yourself marriages, . . . with their apparent do-it-yourself system of separation, are, for the Middle Ages, an unusually individualistic people.”142 This principle that individuals should choose their own mates derives from canon law, which in turn has its antecedents in early Germanic customs of free contract.143 It is ironic that the principle of marrying for love should derive from notions of free contract, themselves the basis of modern prenuptial agreements. As a historical matter, prenuptials are not antithetical to the concept of romantic love. Indeed, much historical evidence points to the intermingling of love and property negotiations. Describing a collection of medieval letters, one historian has noted that “[w]hat is . . . interesting is the number of cases where marriages which had been preceded by extensive negotiations about property were also *906 obviously accompanied by depth of feeling.”144 Lawrence Stone, one of the preeminent historians in this field, describes a contemporary misconception about the early modern period: [T]hat there is a clear dichotomy between marriage for interest, meaning money, status or power, and marriage for affect, meaning love, friendship or sexual attraction; and that the first is morally reprehensible. In practice in the sixteenth century, no such distinction existed . . . .145 Historically, then, “marriage was both a psychological and an economic enterprise.”146 According to historians, at least, negotiation of these two impulses can be successfully accomplished. C. The Psychological Context of Marriage Psychologists counsel against the personal obfuscation that can result from an overly romanticized picture of one’s partner. Perhaps one of the clearest requirements for a successful romantic relationship is that it be based on a foundation of realism. This is the ability and willingness to see our partner as he or she is, with shortcomings as well as virtues, rather than attempting to carry on a romance with a fantasy.147 Negotiating a prenuptial agreement provides an opportunity to learn a great deal about one’s fiancé. “[N]egotiations in the marital context are not likely to be either hostile or adversarial. Instead, they provide an ideal forum for partners to learn each other’s goals and plans in a non-threatening, optimistic setting.”148 Similarly, psychologists stress the importance of communication in marriage.149 Signatories of prenuptial agreements attest to the ability of these documents to encourage open communication. Gail Koff, a founder of the California law firm Jacoby & Myers, herself entered into a prenuptial and found it to be a very constructive tool. “[I]t turned out to be a very positive vehicle for communication, and I think it helped set some of the ground rules for our relationship.”150 In fact, for several years Koff and her husband took the agreement with them on their yearly wedding anniversary vacation and reviewed the terms of the contract.151 *907 Successful marriages also include a profound element of sharing.152 Although a seemingly selfish act, a prenuptial agreement can promote this ideal of sharing and mutuality by guaranteeing that each party is treated identically upon divorce. 153 Fundamentally, prenuptial agreements can also promote honesty between two people. In a book advocating the use of these contracts, the author argues that “it might seem that this book is an argument against romantic love, in favor of a calculating affection. Not true. Just as knowledge tends to liberate rather than confine, love flowers in honesty.”154 However, there is no empirical evidence to support or deny the psychological benefits of prenuptials.155 While prenuptial agreements have the potential to enhance a marriage in ways recognized by psychologists and marital counselors, the effect of a prenuptial agreement on any particular couple, is highly individualized. D. The Cultural Context of Marriage Evolution and anthropology suggest that marriage is a phenomenon deeply rooted in the human psyche.156 However, many cultures emphasize the financial aspects of marriage in ways foreign to Americans. In most non-Western cultures around the world, some kind of transfer of money or goods occurs between the families of the bride and groom. The most common form of transfer is from the husband’s family to that of the wife. In a sample of 565 societies, 47 percent are characterized by this kind of transaction, that is, by bride price or bride wealth.157 In these cultures, romance is not likely to be an important factor in partner selection. In India, for example, “[n]obody really expects that adolescent crushes and affairs of the heart will lead through courtship to marriage, despite the celebration of romance in the popular media. In fact, romance has only dubious legitimacy, and marriage, quite clearly, some other function.”158 Thus, *908 in most societies romantic affection between the bride and groom is probably the least important cultural factor leading to marriage.159 In contrast, American culture places a uniquely high premium on the romantic sentiments between two partners entering marriage. “It is in the United States that perhaps the only, at any rate the most complete, demonstration of romantic love as the prologue and theme of marriage has been staged.”160 It is arguably this romantic premise in American culture that most militates against an American couple’s desire to use a prenuptial agreement. Scholars continue to debate the historical source of romantic love. Some believe it has a long tradition in both English and American history. “Companionate” marriages, those based on the affection of the parties, apparently became a widespread phenomenon in England in the eighteenth century.161 Lawrence Stone has pointed out the twin rise of the companionate marriage and the novel: [R]omantic love and the romantic novel grew together after 1780, and the problem of cause and effect is one that is impossible to resolve. All that can be said is that for the first time in history, romantic love became a respectable motive for marriage among the propertied classes, and that at the same time there was a rising flood of novels filling the shelves of the circulating libraries, devoted to the same theme.162 Other historians hypothesize an earlier beginning to the American tradition of romantic love. They argue that the Puritans brought the concept of companionate marriage with them from England, and that it has remained an important element of American society ever since.163 Still other scholars believe that the idea of marrying for romantic love arose in the nineteenth century, a product of capitalism. Engels posited: [Under capitalism] in ethical theory and in poetic description, nothing was more immutably established than that every marriage is immoral which does not rest on mutual sexual love and really free agreement of husband and wife. In short, the love marriage was proclaimed as a human right.164 Whatever its origin, romantic love has taken a central place in the American concept of marriage. In Stone’s words, “[l]ove has now become the only respectable *909 and generally admitted motive for mate selection, whatever the secret reality may be.”165 Emphasis on romantic love in family life, with its idealization of the concept of partnership, also stresses the collective good over that of the individual. Although premarital agreements need not subordinate the collective good to that of the individual participants, there is a widespread feeling that they do. This sentiment is heightened by the recognition that economics, the basis for all prenuptial agreements, is not founded on a romantic ideal. While romanticism stresses the uniqueness of each partner, economics derives from market theory, which is based on the limits of individual uniqueness.166 Hence, an agreement that presumes that the parties are interchangeable conflicts with the hyper-romantic sentiments surrounding marriage. The most crucial factor in the social context surrounding prenuptial agreements is the ubiquity of divorce in the American social fabric. “Critics like to point out that the country in which romantic love found its best home is also the country with the highest divorce rate in the world.”167 Although the idea of signing a prenuptial agreement is distasteful to many Americans, the country’s high divorce rate means that couples ignore the agreements at their peril. IV. Encouraging the Enforceability of Prenuptial Agreements: The Independent Counsel Requirement Despite the strong cultural basis for prenuptial agreements and the general shift in family law towards private contracting, courts reviewing prenuptials face a dilemma familiar to any student of contracts: To what extent should the court acknowledge and account for possible disparities in bargaining power when deciding whether to enforce a contract? As one scholar asks, Should the law’s response to premarital agreements be limited to eradicating disparate treatment of women by mandating equal treatment of men and women as contracting parties? Or should the law’s response run the risk of paternalism by recognizing that the achievement of gender equality requires more than equal treatment--it may demand protection of women as a disadvantaged socioeconomic class?168 Courts may review prenuptial agreements for both procedural and substantive fairness.169 However, as prenuptials become more common, courts are less willing to review the agreements for substantive fairness,170 instead limiting their review to procedural inquiries concerning whether the agreement was entered into “freely, knowledgeably, and in good faith, without the exertion of *910 duress or undue influence.”171 While the move away from substantive fairness review may be good policy, courts have been inconsistent in protecting the parties’ right to procedural fairness. In a seminal article, Robert Mnookin and Lewis Kornhauser examine the influence of legal rules on private bargaining and negotiation.172 The authors assert that, although the state has an interest in ensuring fair bargaining between the parties, legal rules affecting the parties’ relative negotiating power influence the outcome of the negotiations.173 Ideally, parties should be able to negotiate private bargains that are preferable to court-ordered solutions;174 however, their ability to bargain effectively is compromised by vague legal standards and unpredictable legal resolutions.175 The practice of reviewing prenuptials for substantive fairness only exacerbates the legal inconsistencies that hamper parties’ ability to negotiate mutually beneficial agreements. Indeed, courts have been forthright in declaring that substantive review of prenuptial agreements is a “difficult and arbitrary” task.176 As a Wisconsin court recently noted, “[r]arely, we suspect, will application of [the test for substantive fairness] lead to a clearly indicated resolution.”177 Given this lack of clarity and the potential for inconsistency, courts have been increasingly unwilling to review prenuptials for substantive fairness. However, reviewing prenuptial agreements for procedural fairness may lead to equally inconsistent and unsatisfying results. When evaluating prenuptial agreements, courts often focus on the fairness of the bargaining process that produced the agreement. To this end, courts enforce with greatest consistency the requirement of full and fair disclosure during the bargaining process of each parties’ financial holdings.178 This requirement assumes that disclosure of financial holdings is essential for effective bargaining.179 But while full disclosure may be one element of effective bargaining, disclosure alone is no guarantee of a fair negotiation process. Courts’ reliance on disclosure as an *911 indicia of fairness fails to consider the profound bargaining disparity that often exists between parties entering into a prenuptial agreement. Parties signing prenuptial agreements rarely enjoy equal financial or other bargaining resources. As one court noted, “candor compels us to raise to a conscious level the fact that . . . prenuptial agreements will almost always be entered into between people with property or an income potential to protect on one side and people who are impecunious on the other.”180 Not surprisingly, this disparity often has a distinctly gendered flavor. Because women are often financially or emotionally disadvantaged in the bargaining process, they contest prenuptials at much greater rates than men.181 For example, among remarried couples, who are most likely to sign prenuptials, “there may be a great age disparity, with the husband considerably older than the wife.”182 Regardless of age, empirical data indicate that women generally fare worse than men in economic negotiations.183 As one scholar argues, women may be disadvantaged in negotiations by their distaste for disagreement and their comparatively stronger “taste for cooperation.”184 This propensity may, in turn, create “hostages”: persons or things--including the relationship itself--which are valued more by one party and thus can be used as leverage by the opposing party. For example, a woman who values a relationship more than her fiance is less likely to make the “credible threats” vital to effective bargaining.185 Bargaining a prenuptial contract is not like bargaining a contract for a bushel of wheat. The bargaining position of the woman is totally out of line. The woman is usually more emotionally involved and reluctant to question the man’s motives or purposes. She wants to get married and doesn’t contemplate the agreement being tested in a divorce court. But if it is, she stands to lose.186 *912 This theory provides a powerful explanation of the dynamics surrounding prenuptial agreements. It also explains why so many women agree to sign premarital contracts on the eve of their wedding.187 Wealth, age, or emotional bargaining alone cannot preclude the drafting of a contract. But courts’ cavalier treatment of the inequities in prenuptial negotiations only heightens the unfairness of both the bargaining process and the results. Courts often fail to acknowledge the impact of unequal bargaining power on the provisions of prenuptial agreements by emphasizing the contract itself rather than the legal rights the parties have forgone by signing it. In a recent case, a widow contested the validity of a prenuptial agreement that was signed only hours before the wedding, that she had neither read nor reviewed with independent counsel, and that denied her any rights to her husband’s estate.188 In upholding the agreement, the court unsympathetically reasoned, In our view, respondent has established nothing more than her own dereliction in failing to acquaint herself with the provisions of the agreement and to obtain the benefit of independent legal counsel. Although this dereliction may have caused her to be ignorant of the precise terms of the agreement, . . . absent fraud or other misconduct, parties are bound by their signatures.189 The court was not concerned that the husband had been a “wealthy executive,” while the wife was “unemployed and brought no assets to the marriage.”190 The central problem here is not the disparity in the parties’ respective wealth, but rather the court’s refusal to acknowledge that the wife had been disadvantaged in the bargaining process, had received no legal advice, and therefore had unwittingly signed away her rights to the marital estate. Although these bargaining practices might be acceptable for arm’s-length transactions, they pose serious difficulties in the fiduciary context of prenuptial negotiations.191 In another case, a pregnant eighteen year-old woman signed a prenuptial agreement that she did not understand three days before her wedding which nullified her marital rights to her husband’s estate upon his death.192 Her husband’s lawyer neither explained the agreement to her nor advised her of her *913 right to independent legal counsel.193 When her husband drowned the following year, the wife contested the validity of the prenuptial. At trial, the husband’s lawyer justified his failure to inform the wife of her right to independent counsel: “[M]y basic experience with people coming into my office, is that people who aren’t mentally retarded generally know that they have a right to see a lawyer if they want to.”194 The court invalidated the prenuptial because the agreement was “overreaching” and because the husband’s attorney had advised the wife to sign the agreement without informing her of her right to independent counsel.195 However, in striking down the prenuptial, the court merely relied on the specific facts of the case, neither following nor establishing a clear legal rule. Such legal ambiguities give rise to real fears about parties unknowingly forfeiting valuable legal rights. These bargains cannot be considered fair and do not even seem to pass the test of procedural fairness that requires the parties to enter into agreements “knowledgeably.” In order to minimize inconsistencies and promote procedural fairness, courts need to define the elements that comprise equitable negotiation, such as what it means to enter a contract “knowledgeably.” One way to facilitate this goal is to require each party entering into a prenuptial agreement to consult with independent counsel. At present, no state makes consultation with independent counsel a prerequisite for the enforcement of prenuptial agreements. 196 Some states recognize the value of legal advice by requiring that each party have the opportunity to consult with a lawyer prior to signing the agreement, even if they reject that opportunity.197 Other states consider the opportunity to consult with independent counsel as one of several factors in evaluating whether a party knowledgeably entered into an agreement.198 Still others require that if the agreement’s provisions with respect to one of the parties are not “fair and reasonable,” then the agreement will not be upheld unless the party disadvantaged had independent counsel and acted with “full knowledge of her rights.”199 Occasionally a state will require the proponent of an agreement to prove the fairness of the agreement if he or she “played the dominant role in the relationship.”200 In *914 such situations, the retention of “independent competent counsel is a prerequisite” for showing that the weaker party voluntarily signed the agreement.201 Clearly, even these “rules” rely on subjective evaluations, such as what conditions comprise “fair and reasonable” negotiation and what actions reflect the assumption of a “dominant role.” The use of these vague standards may have a devastating impact on women (who are most often the focus of evaluation) and on the clarity of the laws governing prenuptial agreements. For example, in a recent case upholding a prenuptial agreement, a dissenting judge argued that a wife whose “education and experience did not provide her with a background in business and investment affairs” could neither evaluate her husband’s financial disclosure nor understand the prenuptial agreement on her own.202 In the judge’s paternalistic assessment, “[s]he did not complete high school. She has never made more than $5,000 a year.”203 These kinds of arguments do a disservice to the women they describe and to the clarity of prenuptial law. Judicial evaluations of what constitutes “knowledgeable,” “fair,” and “adequate” disclosure are too value-laden to provide guidance to couples negotiating to protect their rights and seeking to draft a legally enforceable contract. Rather than rely on subjective judicial judgments, a clear rule should be established to ensure that couples knowledgeably enter into a prenuptial agreement. This rule should specify that prenuptial agreements are unenforceable unless the party forfeiting his or her rights is represented by independent counsel, has received full disclosure from the other party, and is aware of any material circumstances that could affect the provisions of the agreement.204 Additionally, if one party cannot afford legal representation, the other party must pay for the counsel of the less wealthy party’s choice.205 If one party chooses to waive the right to counsel, counsel for the other party must explain the rights being waived, and both the explanation and the waiver should be documented in writing. Prenuptial agreements that satisfy the above requirements would be immune from legal challenge by either party.206 This proposal *915 would strengthen, not weaken, parties’ freedom to contract, with all its associated benefits. By providing an easily understandable safe harbor, this rule gives couples the security of knowing that, if each is represented by counsel, their prenuptial agreement will be upheld. The importance of retaining independent legal counsel has not escaped courts’ attention.207 Nevertheless, no court has required parties to consult independent counsel before signing a prenuptial. Some courts reason that such a requirement would depart too far from basic contract law.208 This argument, however, fails to consider the common law contract requirement that parties with a “special relationship,” or who “stand in a relationship of trust and confidence to one another, “must provide” full disclosure and knowledge of the benefits of the bargain and what is being bargained away.”209 Other courts view requiring independent counsel as “constitut[ing] a paternalistic and unwarranted interference with the parties’ freedom to enter contracts.”210 This position ignores the reality that judicial review of prenuptial agreements and the attendant evaluation of each party’s educational and financial background is already a paternalistic exercise. Instead, a rule that conditions the enforceability of prenuptial agreements on the retention of independent counsel would ensure greater freedom of contract than the existing rules of procedural and substantive review provide. Some commentators assert that lawyers have a proven record of making family negotiations more difficult and complicated than the parties themselves would have made them.211 Although advising parties of their rights in advance might complicate the bargaining process, it prevents the even more burdensome process of litigating the validity of a prenuptial agreement. Furthermore, if one of the parties does not wish to marry after the proposed agreement is explained, that realization is likely a divorce prevented. In addition, lawyers can perform a variety of useful functions; they can “make negotiations more rational, minimize the number of disputes, discover outcomes preferable to both parties, increase *916 the opportunities for resolution out of court,” and ensure that the agreements are enforceable after they are signed.212 On balance, this rule would increase both the enforceability and fairness of prenuptial agreements by establishing a clear and fair test. Courts would no longer need to conduct extensive subjective evaluations of each party’s background, education, and financial status to assess the procedural or substantive fairness of the agreement. The clarity of the test will avoid one court’s prediction that “debate will continue to rage concerning the proper function of reviewing courts in resolving the extent to which the special incidents of the premarital relationship should alter traditional contract analysis.”213 The early and equitable involvement of lawyers in negotiating prenuptials would increase the likelihood that the resulting agreements are fair by ensuring that both parties understand their legal rights and by helping them avoid common pitfalls in the negotiating process. Conclusion Prenuptial agreements have a long history in the Anglo-American tradition. Their continued use reflects a reality that many other cultures unapologetically acknowledge: Marriage has significant consequences for an individual’s wealth and property. Many couples may not realize that if they do not write their own prenuptial agreement, the state will provide one for them, and they will have no input in the terms that the state and courts enforce. Nevertheless, prenuptial agreements, with their emphasis on individual security and financial concerns, will always challenge the American ideal that romance is the only legitimate basis for marriage. Couples undoubtedly will continue to debate the merits of signing prenuptial agreements; hopefully many will objectively discuss the benefits and drawbacks in a way that allows them to determine whether or not the contractual approach is right for them. If they are able to look beyond the stereotypes, they might well be pleasantly surprised. In his book The Love Contract: Handbook for a Liberated Marriage, Robert Burger provides his readers with a sample prenuptial agreement and adds, “[t] his is the love contract. It can be helpful; it is not a panacea. It can help love flower and accordingly help love partners grow to their maturity.”214 Prenuptials do not deserve their reputation as the bastion of greed and selfishness in marriage. They can offer more than protection against scheming second wives or social climbing husbands. Rather, prenuptial agreements can promote greater love, communication, and, ultimately, happiness in marriage. A legal framework incorporating an independent counsel requirement would promote fairness and full knowledge by both parties, which increases the potential for prenuptials to be a positive, relationship-enhancing experience. Footnotes Third-year law student, Stanford Law School. I am indebted to Professors Deborah Rhode and Janet Halley for their a critical insights and encouragement during the writing of this piece. Special thanks to the members of the Spring 1996 Gender Law & Public Policy seminar. Finally, I would like to thank the staff and editors of the Stanford Law Review, especially Laura Bradford, Jessica Gonzalez, Dan McBride, and Gail Mosse. 1 Jonathan L. Alpert, Gilbert’s Law, Case & Com., Nov.-Dec. 1970, at 44, 45 (compiling legal aphorisms from the works of William S. Gilbert, lyricist of the song-writing team Gilbert & Sulllivan). 2 A. Marsh, The Confession of the New Married Couple, reprinted in The Ten Pleasures of Marriage 225 (John Harvey ed., The Navarre Soc’y 1950) (1683) (attributed to Aphra Behn). 3 Stephanie H. Dahl, Prenuptial Agreement: Is It for You?, Mod. Bride, Dec. 1990-Jan. 1991, at 326, 326. Throughout this note, the terms “prenuptial” and “prenuptial agreement” are used interchangeably. 4 Id. at 468. 5 See, e.g., Gail Frommer Brod, Premarital Agreements and Gender Justice, 6 Yale J.L. & Feminism 229 (1994). 6 See, e.g., Laura Castaneda, Inside Story About Prenuptial Agreements: Even If You’re Not Rich, or Famous, It Can Pay to Have One, S.F. Chron., Nov. 4, 1996, at E1. 7 See Gary Belsky, Living by the Rules, Money, May 1996, at 100; Kathleen Murray, Odd Couples and Their Odder Divorce Settlements, Cosmopolitan, May 1996, at 222. 8 However, prenuptials that regulate the marriage itself are usually unenforceable in court. See text accompanying notes 101-103 infra. 9 See Belsky, supra note 7, at 100; Charles Laurence, Couple Find Fame in Fine Print, Chi. Sun-Times, Feb. 18, 1996, at 32. 10 See Belsky, supra note 7, at 101 (listing highlights of the LeGalleys’ prenuptial agreement). 11 Laurence, supra note 9, at 32. Rex LeGalley has divorced twice and Teresa was “briefly and disastrously” married in her early 20’s. See id. 12 Id. 13 Id. (quoting New York matrimonial lawyer Raoul Felder). 14 See id. 15 See Judith T. Younger, Perspectives on Antenuptial Agreements: An Update, 8 J. Am. Acad. Matrimonial Law. 1, 8 (1992) (discussing the subjects of prenuptial agreements). 16 See Charles Cahn II, Estate Planning to Avoid Complications of Remarriage, 19 Est. Plan. 268 (1992) (discussing survivorship rights vested by the state and how prenuptial agreements can alter those rights); Albert B. Crenshaw, To Love, Honor and Protect Your Assets: Older Couples Embrace Prenuptial Agreements, Wash. Post, Apr. 27, 1993, (Health), at 12-13 (noting that prenuptials can allow widows to “get around” state inheritance laws). 17 See Bart A. Basi & Ed Bodnam, Premarital Agreements: Retirement Plan Rules Supersede Premarital Contract, 24 Tax’n for Law. 226 (1996) (“[A]n enforceable premarital agreement can be an important element in estate planning, especially for parties that have children from a prior marriage.”); Money Talks Aid 2nd Marriages: Discussing Plans on Insurance, Wills and Housing Can Make for a Happier Household, Orlando Sentinel, Sept. 10, 1995, at H2 (“Many financial planners recommend a prenuptial agreement and separate consultations with estate-planning experts for couples who remarry.”). 18 See Recent Developments, Family Law--Prenuptial Agreements-- Pennsylvania Supreme Court Rejects Substantive Review of Prenuptial Agreements: Stone v. Simeone, 104 Harv. L. Rev. 1399, 1399 n.3 (1991) (discussing the various purposes of different types of prenuptial agreements) [hereinafter Recent Developments]; Andrew Leckey, Married or Divorced: Watch Finances, St. Louis Post-Dispatch, May 17, 1996, at 5C (quoting attorney Barry Schatz as saying, “Defining what constitutes marital and nonmarital property is one of the most important benefits of a prenuptial agreement.”). 19 See Karen S. Peterson, Money Sense From Start Is Important in Marriage, Chi. Sun-Times, Feb. 23, 1995, § 2, at 39 (stating that prenuptials “help you figure out the way you will go”). 20 See Crenshaw, supra note 16, at 13. 21 See Pam Slater, Prelude to Partnership, Sacramento Bee, June 13, 1996, at C1. 22 See Belsky, supra note 7, at 102 (describing the rise in the use of prenuptial agreements from less than 1% two decades ago). 23 See Emy Sigler, Case Comment, Elgar v. Probate Appeal: The Probate Court’s Implied Powers to Construe and to Enforce Pre-Nuptial Agreements, 9 Conn. Prob. L.J. 145, 145 (1994). 24 Cecile C. Weich, Love on the Dotted Line: Craft a Prenuptial Agreement Carefully to Withstand Any Future Challenges, A.B.A. J., Oct. 1994, at 50. 25 See Crenshaw, supra note 16 (noting that increasing divorce rates have led couples to plan for this possibility); Allison A. Page, Note, Premarital Consent to Waiver of Spousal Pension Benefits: A Proposal to Equalize Prenuptial “I Do” and Postnuptial “I Do,” 47 Wash. U. J. Urb. & Contemp. L. 157, 162 (1995) (noting that the increasing frequency of second marriages has spurred couples to write prenuptials). 26 See Arthur J. Norton & Louisa F. Miller, U.S. Dep’t. of Commerce, Marriage, Divorce, and Remarriage in the 1990’s, at 5 (1992) (citing U.S. Nat’l Center for Health Stat., Pub. Health Service, DHHS Pub. No. (PHS) 91-1120, Advance Report of Final Marriage Statistics, 1988 (1991)). 27 See Ilyce R. Glink, Nuptial Saga: ‘48 Hours’ of Marriage, ‘For Better, For Worse,’ Chi. Trib., May 19, 1991, § 6 (Womanews), at 2. 28 Norton & Miller, supra note 26, at 12. 29 Mary Ann Glendon, The New Marriage and the New Property, in Marriage and Cohabitation in Contemporary Societies: Areas of Legal, Social and Ethical Change 59, 63 (John M. Eekelaar & Sanford N. Fetz eds., 1980). 30 See Younger, supra note 15, at 12. 31 See Norton & Miller, supranote 26, at 3 (“The distribution of the percentage of women who had ever married ... clearly shows an aggregate movement away from early age at first marriage.”). 32 See text accompanying notes 81-94 infra. 33 Gitta Morris, Taking a Legal Approach to Marriage, N.Y. Times, Feb. 10, 1991, § 12 (Conn. Wkly.), at 3 (interviewing lawyer Louis I. Parley, co-author of Alexander Lindey & Louis I. Parley, Lindey on Separation Agreements and Antenuptial Contracts (1990)). 34 See Belsky, supra note 7, at 102 (describing how and when to draw up an “airtight prenup”). 35 See Weich, supra note 24, at 50 (describing the use of prenuptials as an attempt to avoid antagonistic divorce proceedings). 36 See Pamela E. George, Can a Woman of the 90’s Have It All? Or, Is She Once Again Faced with That Age Old Question--“What’s a Girl to Do?,” 8 J. Am. Acad. Matrimonial Law. 73, 75-76 (1992) (“Some perceive that a premarital agreement will quell any possibility of a bitter divorce because there will be nothing over which to fight.”). 37 See Judith Rehak, Prenuptial Accords: Walking Down the Aisle and Reading Fine Print, Int’l Herald Trib., Feb. 25, 1995, at 14 (noting that parents of an heir or heiress often press for a prenuptial agreement); Anita Sharpe, Prenuptial Pacts Shield Businesses from an Heir’s Ex, Wall St. J., June 19, 1996, at B1 (reporting that “ ‘it’s the rare exception’ when wealthy business owners don’t require prenups from their sons and daughters”) (quoting New York attorney Raoul Felder). 38 See In Praise of Prenuptial Contracts, Inv. Daily, June 7, 1991, at 8 (defining “people of wealth” as those with assets over $500,000) [hereinafter In Praise]; Peterson, supra note 19, at 39 (encouraging prenuptial agreements for couples with “substantial assets”). 39 See Gail Koff, Love and the Law 85 (1989) (stating that with the “rise in two-income families, ... there is an interest for some to protect each spouse’s individual property”). 40 See Joe Catalano, Sharing Home Buying Deeds: Spell Things Out Clearly When Purchasing with Friends, Newsday, May 19, 1995, at D7 (“[P]artners purchasing property together should ... draw up a formal agreement, spelling out such things as how much interest each has in the property, who pays what expenses connected with the house and what happens if one partner is unable to pay their share.”). 41 See Belsky, supra note 7, at 102. 42 See Making Cents, When Your Fiancé Has Lots of Debt, L.A. Times, Mar. 17, 1996, at D2 (“Financial analysts say you would be wise to draw up a prenuptial agreement keeping your financial lives separate, at least until you decide you want to pay off your fiancé’s past debts or they become uncollectible.”). 43 See Kirk Johnson, Gay Divorce: Few Markers in This Realm, N.Y. Times, Aug. 12, 1994, at A20. 44 See Belsky, supra note 7, at 102; In Praise, supra note 38, at 8. 45 See In Praise, supra note 38, at 8. 46 Andrew J. Kyreakakis, Antenuptial Law in New Jersey, 24 Seton Hall L. Rev. 254, 254 (1993). 47 Franklin I. Miroff & Andrew C. Mallor, When a Simple ‘I Do’ Won’t Do: How to Draft a Premarital Agreement--And Survive, 13 Fam. Advoc., Spring 1991, at 10, 14. 48 Edward L. Winer, Introduction to Premarital and Marital Contracts: A Lawyer’s Guide to Drafting and Negotiating Enforceable Marital and Cohabitation Agreements at xiii, xiii (Edward L. Winer & Lewis Becker eds., 1993) [[[hereinafter Premarital and Marital Contracts]. 49 See Ralph Underwager & Hollida Wakefield, Psychological Considerations in Negotiating Premarital Contracts, in Premarital and Marital Contracts, supra note 48, at 217, 218 (noting that prenuptial agreements undermine the “trust, hope, and faith the parties have in each other”). 50 See Mary Rowland, Linking Love and Money, N.Y. Times, Feb. 25, 1990, § 3, at 17 (“The biggest challenge in creating a sound financial arrangement is not whether it will stand up in court .... Rather, it is mixing money and love without dousing the romance.”). 51 See Lenore J. Weitzman, The Marriage Contract: Spouses, Lovers, and the Law 243 (1981) (“[A]pproaching marriage as a bargained-for relationship undermines the cooperative goals of marriage.”). 52 See Underwager & Wakefield, supra note 49, at 218 (“A marriage contract may glorify independence and self interest. This will undermine the sense of partnership and equality that is necessary in a successful marriage.”). 53 Jonathan P. Decker, Wedding Checklist: Couples Add Premarital Counseling, Christian Sci. Monitor, May 2, 1996, at 12. 54 Id. (quoting Rev. James Terrell of Washington’s Second Baptist Church). 55 See Slater, supra note 21, at C1. 56 See text accompanying notes 172-187 infra. 57 See Charles W. Gamble, The Antenuptial Contract, 26 U. Miami L. Rev. 692, 724 (1972) (noting that “cases in which the husband contests the antenuptial contract are practically nonexistent”). But see, e.g., Gould v. Rafaeli, 822 S.W.2d 494 (Mo. Ct. App. 1991) (husband contesting validity of a prenuptial). 58 Weitzman, supra note 51, at 241. 59 See text accompanying notes 204-213 infra. 60 Underwager & Wakefield, supra note 49, at 219 (quoting New York attorney Jacalyn Barnett). 61 Rehak, supra note 37, at 14 (quoting family law lawyer William Zabel). 62 See Judith Schoolman, Advice for Newlyweds: Keep Some Finances Single, Reuter’s Bus. Rep., Feb. 25, 1994, available in LEXIS, News Library, Curnws File (noting that “57 percent of divorced couples cited disputes over money as contributing to their breakup”). 63 Bill Rumbler, Money to Have and to Hold: Pair Should Sort Out Financial Situation Before the Wedding, Chi. SunTimes, Sep. 11, 1994, at 13. 64 See Morris, supra note 33, at 3. 65 Premarital Agreement Basic Form: Anticipating the Needs of the Monied Spouse, 18 Fam. Advoc., Summer 1995, at 8, 9. 66 See Underwager & Wakefield, supra note 49, at 219. 67 Id. 68 Crenshaw, supra note 16, at 12 (quoting attorney Glenda A. Fowler) (alterations in original). 69 See Lynn A. Baker & Robert E. Emery, When Every Relationship Is Above Average: Perceptions and Expectations of Divorce at the Time of Marriage, 17 Law & Hum. Behav. 439, 443 (1993). 70 Weich, supra note 24, at 50. 71 See, e.g., Brooks v. Brooks, 733 P.2d 1044, 1050 (Alaska 1987) (upholding a prenuptial agreement and asserting that “people with previous ‘bad luck’ with domestic life may not be willing to risk marriage again without the ability to safeguard their financial interests”); Gant v. Gant, 329 S.E.2d 106, 113 (W. Va. 1985) (upholding a prenuptial agreement and asserting that a prenuptial may “encourage rather than discourage marriage”). 72 See Kaylah Campos Zelig, Comment, Putting Responsibility Back into Marriage: Making a Case for Mandatory Prenuptials, 64 U. Colo. L. Rev. 1223, 1244 (1993) (“Mandatory contracts will allow divorce law to move forward, recognizing the plurality of marriages that exists today and better providing for partners at dissolution.”). 73 Id. 74 See text accompanying notes 44-47 supra. 75 Judy Glass, Prenuptial Pacts Increasing, N.Y. Times, Mar. 4, 1990, § 12 (Long Island Wkly.), at 4 (quoting Huntington, New York, matrimonial lawyer Peter Rubinton). 76 Younger, supra note 15, at 1-2. 77 See Brod, supra note 5, at 255. 78 See Gamble, supra note 57, at 704-05 (examining the courts’ assertions for invoking the public policy rule when voiding prenuptial agreements). 79 Brooks v. Brooks, 733 P.2d 1044, 1048 (Alaska 1987) (footnotes and citations omitted). 80 Stilley v. Folger, 14 Ohio 610, 613 (1846). 81 233 So. 2d 381 (Fla. 1970). 82 Id. at 385. 83 See Brod, supra note 5, at 253 (noting that “lawmakers in many states began making premarital agreements more readily enforceable ... while retaining the previously established common law principles that were used to protect women from unfair premarital agreements”). 84 Potter v. Collin, 321 So. 2d 128, 132 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 1975) (quoting Gamble, supra note 57, at 719). 85 See Brod, supra note 5, at 256-59. 86 Id. at 256. 87 See Phillip Gainsley & Susan C. Rhode, The Role of Substantive Fairness in Premarital Agreements, in Premarital and Marital Contracts, supra note 48, at 51, 55 (describing factors considered by the courts). 88 Sigler, supra note 23, at 148 (footnotes omitted). 89 See Younger, supra note 15, at 6. 90 See Brod, supra note 5, at 255 (noting that “states have an overriding interest in protecting the welfare of children”). 91 See id. (noting that “states currently implement the policy of protecting marriage by refusing to enforce premarital agreements that promote divorce”); see also Davis v. Davis, No. FA 9501448075, 1996 WL 456335 (Conn. Super. Ct. July 29, 1996) (finding agreement unenforceable because it gave husband incentive to divorce because his wife would receive $25,000 for each year the couple lived together). 92 See Younger, supra note 15, at 28 & n.138 (citing cases in Florida, New Jersey, Ohio, Washington, and Wisconsin). 93 See George, supra note 36, at 79 & n.26 (citing cases in Illinois, North Carolina, and Texas). 94 See Gamble, supra note 57, at 729 (describing this aspect as courts’ “chief concern” when reviewing prenuptial agreements). 95 9B U.L.A. 69 (1996). 96 See id. (listing twenty-eight states which have adopted the UPAA as of July 1, 1996). 97 See Barbara Ann Atwood, Ten Years Later: Lingering Concerns About the Uniform Premarital Agreement Act, 19 J. Legis. 127, 146 (1993) (“[T]he drafters of the UPAA seem to have so constrained the available challenges to antenuptial agreements that such agreements would survive in circumstances that the ordinary commercial contract would not.”); Brod, supra note 5, at 275-276 (“The greatest failure of the UPAA is Section 6” which treats enforceability.). 98 See Atwood, supra note 97, at 145-46 (contrasting the UPAA’s mandatory linkage of nondisclosure and unconscionability to the common law’s acceptance of either as an independent basis for voiding prenuptial agreements). 99 Id. at 135. 100 See Ralph Warner & Toni Ihara, California Marriage and Divorce Law 36-39 (7th ed. 1985) (listing issues which should be considered when drawing up a personal marriage contract). 101 Younger, supra note 15, at 15. 102 These examples come from actual prenuptial agreements. See Rehak, supra note 37, at 14 (describing some of the “wackier” terms of prenuptial agreements). 103 Laura P. Graham, Comment, The Uniform Premarital Agreement Act and Modern Social Policy: The Enforceability of Premarital Agreements Regulating the Ongoing Marriage, 28 Wake Forest L. Rev. 1037, 1045 (1993) (discussing the holding in Koch v. Koch, 232 A.2d 157 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. 1967)). 104 Baker & Emery, supra note 69, at 443. 105 See id. at 448. 106 Id. at 449. 107 The classic work on this topic is Weitzman, supra note 51. 108 Id. at xv. 109 Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190, 213 (1888) (quoting Noel v. Ewing, 9 Ind. 37, 50 (1857)). 110 Cal. Civ. Code § 4100 (Deering 1996). 111 American Bar Association, Your Legal Guide to Marriage and Other Relationships 15-16 (1989). 112 Id. at 9. 113 Atwood, supra note 97, at 131-32. 114 See Brod, supra note 5, at 236 (noting that “every common law state has enacted an ‘equitable distribution’ statute governing the distribution of property at divorce” that recognizes marriage as an economic partnership). 115 See text accompanying notes 104-106 supra. 116 See Baker & Emery, supra note 69, at 441 (describing the accuracy of survey responses to questions concerning custody, alimony, child support, and property settlement). 117 Warner & Ihara, supra note 100, at 35. 118 Roger A. Arnold, Marriage, Divorce, and Property Rights: A Natural Rights Framework, in The American Family and the State 195, 204 (Joseph R. Peden & Fred R. Glahe eds., 1986). 119 See Weitzman, supra note 51, at 153-54 (arguing that prenuptial agreements are necessary “because the traditional marriage contract completely ignores so many real needs by assuming that all marriages are first marriages”). 120 See id. 121 See generally Jana B. Singer, The Privatization of Family Law, 1992 Wis. L. Rev. 1443 (1992) (discussing the transformation in family law from public to private ordering of behavior). 122 Cf. Matthew P. Bergman, Status, Contract, and History: A Dialectical View, 13 Cardozo L. Rev. 171, 172 (1991) (“During periods of social change, status ... will give way to contract.”). 123 Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 453 (1972). 124 Singer, supra note 121, at 1511-12. Singer attributes this evolution to the rising influence of the law and economics movement, which characterizes people as rational maximizers: “[S]everal influential social science theories challenged the notion that people ... behave differently in family relationship than they do in more overtly economic settings.” Id. at 1523. 125 See Weitzman, supra note 51, at 227 (describing prenuptial agreements as according better with contemporary social reality than the sex-based legacy of traditional marriage law). 126 Recent Developments, supra note 18, at 1402 n.31. 127 See, e.g., Warner & Ihara, supra note 100, at 19 (discussing the history of the community property system). 128 Although this section focuses on the impact of English history on American family law, many other marriage systems have obviously influenced the concept of marriage in American culture. See, e.g., William A. Reppy, Jr. & Cynthia A. Samuel, Community Property in the United States at iii (3d ed. 1991) (discussing community property regimes derived from Spanish-Mexican and Spanish-French colonial law). However, a complete exploration of these influences is beyond the scope of this note. 129 See Lloyd Bonfield, Property Settlements on Marriage in England from the Anglo-Saxons to the Mid-Eighteenth Century, in Marriage, Property, and Succession 287, 292-93 (Lloyd Bonfield ed., 1992). 130 See id. at 293. 131 Lawrence Stone, The Family, Sex and Marriage in England 1500-1800, at 30-31 (1977). 132 See Bonfield, supra note 129, at 305-08. Bonfield notes that fathers who wished to protect their daughters prospectively would “insist upon an agreement regarding the widow’s maintenance prior to marriage.” Id. at 305. 133 See Younger, supra note 15, at 2 (noting that “[b]oth chancery and common law courts were then passing on their validity”). 134 See Stone, supra note 131, at 87. 135 Because this discussion focuses on property concerns, it does not examine the historical customs of the “common people.” Although there are few historical records, the common people presumably chose a mate based on love rather than on financial situations. See Alan Macfarlane, Marriage and Love in England: Modes of Reproduction 1300-1840, at 133 (1986). 136 See Stone, supra note 131, at 31 (describing the steps of sixteenth-century marriage). 137 See id. at 88. 138 Bonfield, supra note 129, at 288. 139 Stone, supra note 131, at 88. 140 See Macfarlane, supra note 135, at 125 (citing George Elliot Howard, 1 A History of Matrimonial Institutions 339 (1904)). 141 See id. at 294. 142 Charles Donahue, Jr., English and French Marriage Cases in the Later Middle Ages: Might the Differences Be Explained by Differences in the Property Systems?, in Marriage, Property, and Succession, supra note 129, at 339, 362. 143 See Macfarlane, supra note 135, at 125-26. 144 Id. at 198. 145 Stone, supra note 131, at 86. Stone later argues, however, that “romantic and sexual love ... played little or no part in the daily lives of men and women of the late seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.” Id. at 272. 146 Macfarlane, supra note 135, at 165. 147 Nathaniel Branden, The Psychology of Romantic Love: What Love Is, Why Love Is Born, Why It Sometimes Grows, Why It Sometimes Dies 131 (1980). 148 Weitzman, supra note 51, at 239. 149 See Patricia Noller, Judith A. Feeney, Denise Bonnell & Victor J. Callan, A Longitudinal Study of Conflict in Early Marriage, 11 J. Soc. & Pers. Relationships 233, 249-50 (1994) (reporting findings that “[s]pouses high in relationship satisfaction ... let their partner know about their grievances, were involved in mutual discussion of issues and were consistent in their use of positive conflict resolution strategies”). 150 Koff, supra note 39, at 89. 151 See id. 152 See Branden, supra note 147, at 172 (“There is the sense of an alliance: Whoever harms my partner harms me.... [T]he protection and preservation of the relationship exists on my highest level of priorities ....”). 153 See Edward L. Winer, Practical Considerations for Premarital Agreements, in Premarital and Marital Contracts, supra note 48, at 67, 71 (suggesting that equal protection will result if neither spouse is allowed “to share in premarital assets of the other in the event of divorce”). 154 Robert E. Burger, The Love Contract: Handbook for a Liberated Marriage at viii (1973). 155 See Underwager & Wakefield, supra note 49, at 217. 156 See Gwen J. Broude, Marriage, Family, and Relationships: A Cross-Cultural Encyclopedia 189 (1994). 157 Id. at 40. 158 Patricia Uberoi, Introduction to Family, Kinship and Marriage in India 1, 2 (Patricia Uberoi ed., 1993). The idea that marriage is based on the personal feelings or inclination of those marrying may strike us as self-evident. Yet the majority of societies would take the view that marriage is far too important a matter to be left to the individuals concerned and that ‘feeling’, ‘emotion’, ‘love’, between the prospective partners are largely irrelevant. Mcfarlane, supra note 135, at 119. 159 See Broude, supra note 156, at 214-18 (describing criteria for choosing marriage partners). 160 Ernest W. Burgess & Harvey J. Locke, The Family: From Institution to Companionship 319 (1953)); see also Macfarlane, supra note 135, at 120 (“[F] ew people are so given to romantic love as are Americans. In our individualistic sentimentalism we exalt the ideal of marriage based on love-- that mysterious psychophysiological reaction.”) (quoting E. Adamson Hoebel, Man in the Primitive World 214 (1949)). 161 See Stone, supra note 131, at 273. 162 Id. at 284. 163 See G. Robina Quale, A History of Marriage Systems 286 (1988). 164 Frederick Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State 144 (Alec West trans., 1990); see also Paul Horton & Lawrence Alexander, Freedom of Contract and the Family: A Skeptical Appraisal, in The American Family and the State, supra note 118, at 229, 250 (“The ‘romantic love’ concept of Marriage ... became an ideal sometime in the western civilization’s nineteenth century and has stuck around ever since.”). 165 Stone, supra note 131, at 680. 166 See Shoshana Grossbard-Shechtman, On the Economics of Marriage: A Theory of Marriage, Labor and Divorce 1-2 (1993). 167 Branden, supra note 147, at 49. 168 Brod, supra note 5, at 232. 169 See text accompanying notes 85-87 supra. 170 See In re Marriage of Spiegel 553 N.W.2d 309, 314-15 (Iowa 1996) (upholding a prenuptial while admitting the difficulty inherent in evaluating the agreements for substantive fairness). 171 Randolph v. Randolph, No. 03S-01-9510-CV-00119, 1996 WL 506715, at *3 (Tenn. Sept. 9, 1996) (holding a prenuptial invalid because wife did not enter agreement knowledgeably). 172 See Robert H. Mnookin & Lewis Kornhauser, Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: The Case of Divorce, 88 Yale L.J. 950 (1979). 173 See id. at 968-69. 174 See id. at 956-57 (describing the advantages of private solutions to divorce disputes). 175 See id. at 978-79 (“[I]f there is substantial variance among the possible court-imposed outcomes, the relatively more risk-averse party is comparatively disadvantaged” because that party “will accept less in order to avoid the gamble.”). Mnookin and Lewis also argue that uncertainty about the legal outcome increases transaction costs, which in turn advantages the party better able to bear them. See id. at 979. 176 In re Marriage of Spiegel, 553 N.W.2d 309, 315 (Iowa 1996). 177 Greenwald v. Greenwald, 454 N.W.2d 34, 41 (Wis. Ct. App. 1990). 178 See Atwood, supra note 97, at 138 (“[F]air and full disclosure of financial holdings is an absolute prerequisite to enforcement of a premarital agreement.”). 179 See, e.g., Newman v. Newman, 653 P.2d 728, 733 (Colo. 1982) (en banc) (“Once the stringent tests of full disclosure and lack of fraud or overreaching are met, the parties are free to agree to any arrangement for division of their property, including a waiver of any claim to the property of the other.”); Cary v. Cary, No. 02-S-01-9505-CV-00035, 1996 WL 291095, at *5 (Tenn. June 3, 1996) (“So long as the antenuptial agreement was entered into freely and knowledgeably, with adequate disclosure, and without undue influence or overreaching, the provision limiting alimony will be enforced” unless the spouse would become a public charge.). 180 Gant v. Gant, 329 S.E.2d 106, 114 (W. Va. 1985) (upholding a prenuptial agreement and emphasizing that using vague judicial standards of fairness to measure prenuptials invites “the very wealth redistribution that these agreements are designed to prevent”). 181 See Atwood, supra note 97, at 133 (noting that the wife typically petitions the court for “a more favorable economic settlement ... than what she would receive under the terms of the agreement”). 182 Brod, supra note 5, at 243. 183 See Deborah M. Kolb & Gloria G. Coolidge, Her Place at the Table: A Consideration of Gender Issues in Negotiation 6-7 (Program on Negotiation, Working Paper Series No. 88-5, 1988) (discussing women’s ability to negotiate economic issues such as salary and divorce settlement). 184 Carol M. Rose, Women and Property: Gaining and Losing Ground, 78 Va. L. Rev. 421, 423 (1992) (exploring reasons women “systematically do worse than men” with respect to obtaining and owning property). 185 See id. at 445. 186 Glass, supra note 75, at 4 (quoting Leon Friedman, Professor, Hofstra School of Law). For a sustained attack on prenuptial agreements on this ground, see Brod, supra note 5, at 240-252. Brod argues that “the prospective wife is more likely to be harmed by a premarital agreement than the prospective husband.” Id. at 243. 187 See, e.g., In re Marriage of Spiegel, 553 N.W.2d 309, 317 (Iowa 1996) (upholding a prenuptial signed five days before the wedding after the man threatened to cancel the wedding unless his fiancé signed the agreement; the court reasoned that “[p]ressure ... and its timing, may be criticized as unkind, but cannot be deemed illegal”); Rathjen v. Rathjen, No. 05-93-00846-CV, 1995 WL 379322, at *4 (Tex. App. May 30, 1995) (upholding a prenuptial signed the day of the wedding despite the wife’s assertion that she had not entered the agreement freely because “canceling the wedding was not a reasonable alternative ... [and] would have caused her great embarrassment in front of her family and friends”);. 188 See In re Estate of Garbade, 633 N.Y.S.2d 878, 879-80 (App. Div. 1995) (holding that the wife’s failure to obtain independent counsel did not establish the fraud necessary to invalidate the prenuptial agreement). 189 Id. at 880. 190 Id. at 879. 191 Some judges have noted this dynamic. See Simeone v. Simeone, 581 A.2d 162, 168 (Pa. 1990) (“I view prenuptial agreements as being in the nature of contracts of adhesion with one party generally having greater authority than the other who deals in a subservient role. I believe the law protects the subservient party, regardless of that party’s sex, to insure equal protection and treatment under the law.”) (Papadakos, J., concurring in result). 192 See Rowland v. Rowland, 599 N.E.2d 315, 316-317 (Ohio Ct. App. 1991). 193 See id. at 317. 194 Id. at 320. 195 See id. at 320-21 (explaining that the facts of the case did not comprise good faith and fair dealing). 196 See Randolph v. Randolph, No. 03S-01-9510-CV-00119, 1996 WL 506715, at *7 (Tenn. Sept. 9, 1996). 197 See, e.g., Fletcher v. Fletcher, 628 N.E.2d 1343, 1348 (Ohio 1994) (stating that “when an antenuptial agreement provides disproportionately less than the party would have received under equitable distribution, the party financially disadvantaged must have a meaningful opportunity to consult with counsel,” and finding plaintiff did have such an opportunity) (emphasis added). 198 See, e.g., Randolph, 1996 WL 506715, at *7; Gant v. Gant, 329 S.E.2d 106, 116 (W. Va. 1985). 199 Chaudhary v. Ali, No. 0956-94-4, 1995 WL 40079, at *1 (Va. Ct. App. Jan. 31, 1995) (holding a prenuptial invalid because it was not negotiable, did not require the disclosure of assets, and “[t]here was no evidence wife received independent advice prior to signing the agreement”). 200 James v. James, No. CN93-09971, 1995 WL 788187, at *13 (Del. Fam. Ct. May 18, 1995) (upholding a prenuptial entered into by parties of disparate economic means because both had made fair and reasonable disclosures, had entered into the agreement voluntarily, and had retained independent counsel). 201 Id. 202 Estate of Thies v. Lowe, 903 P.2d 186, 192 (Mont. 1995) (Leaphart, J., dissenting). 203 Id. 204 This rule is based on that proposed by Justice Resnick in the dissent in Fletcher v. Fletcher, 628 N.E.2d 1343, 1350 (Ohio 1994) (Resnick, J., dissenting). The requirement of counsel would not apply, however, in cases where neither party wishes to use a lawyer. 205 This procedure is illustrated in Lebeck v. Lebeck, 881 P.2d 727 (N.M. Ct. App. 1994), where the husband asked his wife to review the prenuptial with independent counsel and to have the attorney verify that they had reviewed the agreement and that his wife understood it. See id. at 730. This rule is unlikely to exert too great a financial burden since most couples enter prenuptial agreements to protect substantial interests in financial or property investments. As one court noted, “these rules are unlikely to have any untoward consequences among those marrying for the first time ... because ... it is a rare, starey-eyed [sic] couple in their early twenties who enter into an elaborate prenuptial agreement; after all, among the young, marriage is an exercise in optimism.” Gant v. Gant, 329 S.E.2d 106, 115 (W. Va. 1985). 206 This rule does not foreclose courts’ ability to apply the two most stringent tests for evaluating prenuptials: unconscionability and the “public charge” test. An agreement is unconscionable if the “inequality [is] so strong, gross, and manifest that it must be impossible to state it to one with common sense without producing an exclamation at the inequality of it.” Peirick v. Peirick, 641 S.W.2d 195, 197 (Mo. Ct. App. 1982). Alternatively, the court can refuse to enforce an agreement “if enforcement deprives one spouse of support that he or she cannot obtain otherwise and results in that spouse becoming a public charge.” Cary v. Cary, No. 02-S-01-9505-CV-00035, 1996 WL 291095, at *6 (Tenn. June 13, 1996). Due to the stringency of these tests, they would be unlikely to affect parties’ negotiations. 207 See Randolph v. Randolph, No. 03S-01-9510-CV-00119, 1996 WL 506715, at *7 (Tenn. Sept. 9, 1996) (speculating that “representation by independent counsel may be the best evidence that a party has entered into an antenuptial agreement voluntarily and knowledgeably”). 208 See, e.g., Gant, 329 S.E.2d at 112 (asserting that “nowhere in the law of contracts is it required that a party be advised by independent counsel before an agreement to which he or she sets his or her hand is enforceable”). 209 Carpenter v. Carpenter, 449 S.E.2d 502, 504 (Va. Ct. App. 1994) (holding a prenuptial invalid because the husband failed to disclose his assets, and because the wife signed the agreement without full knowledge of her legal rights). 210 Simeone v. Simeone, 581 A.2d 162, 166 (Pa. 1990). 211 See J. Thomas Oldham, Divorce, Separation, and the Distribution of Property 4-18.1 (1996) (“[R]equiring independent counsel is unwise.... American lawyers are not known for their ability to harmonize ongoing relationships between parties.... [I]t would not be surprising if a substantial number of marriages that would have resulted will not occur when lawyers are inserted into premarital negotiations.”). 212 Mnookin & Kornhauser, supra note 172, at 986. 213 Lebeck v. Lebeck, 881 P.2d 727, 733 (N.M. Ct. App. 1994) (quoting 5 Samuel Williston, A Treatise on the Law of Contracts § 11:8, at 478 (Richard A. Lord ed., 4th ed. 1993)). 214 Burger, supra note 154, at 77. End of Document © 2012 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.
© Copyright 2024