Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Discrete mathematics I - Logic Theories Emil Vatai May 5, 2015 Outline Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic 1 Basics First-order logic Theories 2 Zeroth-order logic 3 First-order logic 4 Theories Logic: The science of correct reasoning Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Definition Logic (from the Ancient Greek: logike) is the use and study of valid reasoning. Independently of the object of discussion. Logic discusses statements which have a unique truth value. Truth values Truth values can be either true (↑, 1, >) or false (↓, 0, ⊥). L = {>, ⊥}. Propositional variables are variables which range over truth values, (they must be either true or false, but never both). Zeroth-order logic Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Definition In mathematical logic, a propositional calculus or logic (also called sentential calculus or sentential logic) is a formal system in which formulas of a formal language may be interpreted to represent propositions. It is formal, i.e. it uses (well-formed) formulas to approximate reality. It deals only with statements which are either true or false (not both). Mathematical logic does not address the contents of the statement, only it’s truth-value. Propositional logic discusses the properties and rules of logical operations. Domain of discourse Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Definition The domain of discourse, also called the universe of discourse (or simply universe), is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. It is the set of "things we are discussing". Usually it is denoted by U Examples U = the students in this class U=N Terms Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Definition Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic 1 2 Theories 3 If t ∈ U then t is a term. If f is an n-ary function symbol, and t1 , t2 , . . . , tn are terms, then f (t1 , t2 , . . . , tn ) is a term. Every term can be obtained by the finite application of the previous two rules. Examples f (t) = the nearest student to t f (n, m) = n + m (note we can think of + as a +(·, ·) binary function Predicates Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Definition Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories A predicate takes an entity or entities in the domain of discourse as input and outputs either True or False. P is an n-ary predicate if P : U n → L. Predicates are statements about the entities of the domain of discourse. Examples F (t): t is female D(m, n): m divides n Logical operators Discrete mathematics I Logic Definition Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Logical operators are map of the form Ln → L (for some positive integer n). They come from well-known everyday logical operations, e.g. and, or, if. . . then, if and only if, not They connect predicated i.e. statements to form larger statements Examples Binary logical operators: ∧ (and, conjunction), ∨ (/inclusive or, disjunction), ⇒ (if..then, implication), ⇔ (if and only if, iff, equivalence). Unary logical operator: ¬ (not, negation) Truth-tables Discrete mathematics I Logic Conjunction and disjunction Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories A > > ⊥ ⊥ B > ⊥ > ⊥ A∧B > ⊥ ⊥ ⊥ A > > ⊥ ⊥ B > ⊥ > ⊥ A∨B > > > ⊥ A > > ⊥ ⊥ B > ⊥ > ⊥ A⇔B > ⊥ ⊥ > Implication and equivalence A > > ⊥ ⊥ B > ⊥ > ⊥ A⇒B > ⊥ > > Truth-tables Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Negation Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories A > ⊥ ¬A ⊥ > Number of unary and binary operators What is the number of unary operators? What is the number of binary operators? Different OR’s Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic Inclusive, exclusive, conflicting1 OR 1 First-order logic Theories 2 3 Inclusive or ∨: Those who had good weapons or good reflexes were victorious. Inclusive or ⊕: We have to go left or right. "Conflicting" or: Drink or A > > ⊥ ⊥ 1 In lack of better translation drive! B 1 > > ⊥ > > > ⊥ ⊥ 2 ⊥ > > ⊥ 3 ⊥ > > > Remarks and Questions Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Remarks The variables A and B in the truth-tables above are propositional variables, i.e. A ∈ L (and not ∈ U). These propositional variables denote some predicates, i.e. A = P(t) or B = D(m, n). Note the distinction between the entities in the domain of discourse and the operations on them, versus the predicates (i.e. statements) and the logical operations connection them. Questions Is the following a valid statement, and is it true? "If 1 = 2 then I am the Pope!" Remarks and Questions Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Remarks The variables A and B in the truth-tables above are propositional variables, i.e. A ∈ L (and not ∈ U). These propositional variables denote some predicates, i.e. A = P(t) or B = D(m, n). Note the distinction between the entities in the domain of discourse and the operations on them, versus the predicates (i.e. statements) and the logical operations connection them. Questions Is the following a valid statement, and is it true? "If 1 = 2 then I am the Pope!" Yes, it is a valid statement. It is also true, because "false implies everything". (Check the truth-tables) Well-formed formulas Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Definition 1 Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories 2 3 If P is a n-ary predicate, and t1 , t2 , . . . , tn are terms, then P(t1 , t2 , . . . , tn ) is called an atomic formula and it is a well-formed formula. If A and B are well-formed formulas then A ∧ B, A ∨ B, A ⇒ B, A ⇔ B and ¬A are also well-formed formulas. Every well-formed formula can be obtained by the finite application of the previous two rules. Example Both F (x ) and F (y ) are well-formed formulas, Then F (x ) ∨ F (y ) and (F (x ) ∧ F (y )) ⇒ F (y ). Interpretation, Satisfiability, Validity Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Definitions Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories An interpretation of a formula is an assignment of meaning to the variables in the formula, i.e. substituting the variables with concrete values from U. A formula is satisfiable if it is possible to find an interpretation which makes the formula true. A formula is valid if all interpretations of the formula make it true. Valid formulas are also called tautologies or rules. The opposite concepts are unsatisfiable (always false) and invalid (some interpretations make it false). Interpretation, Satisfiability, Validity Discrete mathematics I Logic Examples Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Let M(t) mean that t is male (over the students of ELTE) and let A = M(x ) ∧ M(y ) be a formula. Possible interpretations of A are: The interpretation A(x /Attila, y /Istvan) yields M(Attila) ∧ M(Istvan) which is true. The interpretation A(x /Attila, y /Anna) yields M(Attila) ∧ M(Anna) which is false. A is satisfiable, because of the first interpretation. A is invalid, because the second interpretation makes it false (i.e. it is not always true). B = M(x ) ∧ M(y ) ⇒ M(x ) is a valid formula, because it is always true. It is a tautology. ¬B is an unsatisfiable fromula. Questions Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Questions For each of the bellow points determine if the statement or "vice versa" is true, or both or neither are true: All satisfiable statements are valid formulas. All satisfiable formulas are invalid. Some satisfiable formulas are invalid. All valid formulas are not unsatisfiable. Some rules of propositional logic Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Rules Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories A ∧ B ⇔ B ∧ A, A ∨ B ⇔ B ∨ A (A ∧ B) ∧ C ⇔ A ∧ (B ∧ C) (A ∨ B) ∨ C ⇔ A ∨ (B ∨ C) A ∧ (B ∨ C) ⇔ (A ∧ B) ∨ (A ∧ C), A ∨ (B ∧ C) ⇔ (A ∨ B) ∧ (A ∨ C) A ∧ (A ∨ B) ⇔ A, A ∨ (A ∧ B) ⇔ A A ∧ A ⇔ A, A ∨ A ⇔ A A ∨ ¬A ¬(A ∧ ¬A) ¬(¬(A)) ⇔ A commutativity associativity associativity distributivity distributivity absorption idempotency Some rules of propositional logic Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Rules Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories A∧>⇔A A∧ ⊥⇔⊥ A∨>⇔> A∨ ⊥⇔ A ¬(A ∧ B) ⇔ ¬A ∨ ¬B ¬(A ∨ B) ⇔ ¬A ∧ ¬B A ⇒ B ⇔ ¬B ⇒ ¬A (A ⇒ B) ∧ A ⇒ B (A ⇒ B) ∧ ¬B ⇒ ¬A (A ⇒ B) ∧ (B ⇒ C) ⇒ (A ⇒ C) ((A ⇒ B) ∧ (B ⇒ A)) ⇔ (A ⇔ B) DeMorgan DeMorgan Proof Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Proof of A ∧ (A ∨ B) ⇔ A Let F = A ∧ (A ∨ B) ⇔ A and lhs = A ∧ (A ∨ B) (left hand side), rhs = A (right hand side). If A =⊥ then lhs is false because of the definition of conjunction. If A = > then A ∨ B is true because of the definition of disjunction, so lhs is A ∧ > which is >. In both cases the rhs equals lhs, so by the definition of equivalence the formula is always true, i.e. valid. Proof using truth-tables is done by filling out the first two columns of the table as given bellow, and then the rest using the definitions of the logical operations: A > > ⊥ ⊥ B > ⊥ > ⊥ A∨B > > > ⊥ lhs > > ⊥ ⊥ rhs > > ⊥ ⊥ F > > > > Well-formed formulas Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Definition Basics Zeroth-order logic 1 First-order logic Theories 2 3 4 If P is a n-ary predicate, and t1 , t2 , . . . , tn are terms, then P(t1 , t2 , . . . , tn ) is called an atomic formula and it is a well-formed formula. If A and B are well-formed formulas then A ∧ B, A ∨ B, A ⇒ B, A ⇔ B and ¬A are also well-formed formulas. If A is a well-formed, x a variable of the domain of discourse, then ∀x A and ∃x A are also well-formed formulas (these are universally and existentially quantified formulas) Every well-formed formula can be obtained by the finite application of the previous two rules. Examples Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Example Continuing with the example from propositional logic: ∃xF (x ) and ∃x ¬F (y ) are well-formed formulas. ∀x ∃y (F (x ) ∧ ¬F (y )). Quantifiers Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Universal quantifier Symbol: ∀ Read: for all, for each ∀xP(x , y ) ⇔ P(x1 , y ) ∧ P(x2 , y ) ∧ · · · (if U = {x1 , x2 , . . .}) Existential quantifier Symbol: ∃ Read: exists, there is ∃xP(x , y ) ⇔ P(x1 , y ) ∨ P(x2 , y ) ∨ · · · (if U = {x1 , x2 , . . .}) ∃!x denotes "there exists a unique x " or "there is exactly one x " Scope, Free and bound occurrences Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Definition If Q is a quantifier (∀ or ∃) and x is a variable then the scope of Q is the narrowest sub-formula after Qx . All the occurrences of x in the scope of Q are quantified by Q. Let A be a formula and x a variable, then An occurrence of x is a free occurrence if it is not quantified. An occurrence of x is a bound occurrence if it is quantified. Free and bound variables, closed and open formulas Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Definitions The variable x is a bound variable in A, if its every occurrence is bound. The variable x is a free variable in A, if its every occurrence is free. The variable x has mixed occurrence if it has both free and bound occurrences. The formula A is a closed formula (or a sentence) if all of its variables are bound. The formula A is an open formula if it has at least one The formula A is quantifierless if all of its variables are free. Examples Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Examples A = ∀x (P(x ) ∧ Q(x , y )) ⇒ ∃x ∀zR(x , y , z) The scope of the first universal quantifier is (P(x ) ∧ Q(x , y ), the scope of the existential quantifier is ∀zR(x , y , z), the scope of the second universal quantifier is R(x , y , z). The free variable is y Rules of first order logic Discrete mathematics I Logic Rules Emil Vatai 1 ¬∀xP(x ) ⇔ ∃x ¬P(x ) 2 ¬∃xP(x ) ⇔ ∀x ¬P(x ) 3 ∀x ∀yP(x , y ) ⇔ ∀y ∀xP(x , y ) 4 ∃x ∃yP(x , y ) ⇔ ∃y ∃xP(x , y ) 5 ∃x ∀yP(x , y ) ⇒ ∀y ∃xP(x , y ) Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Example to remember the last rule If U = {1, 2} then consider the following two formulas: ∃x ∀y (x = y ) is false because it is: ∃x (x = 1 ∧ x = 2) which is (1 = 1 ∧ 1 = 2) ∨ (2 = 1 ∧ 2 = 2) ∀y ∃x (x = y ) is true because it is: ∀y (1 = y ∨ 2 = y ) which is (1 = 1 ∨ 2 = 1) ∧ (1 = 2 ∨ 2 = 2) And by the definition of implication > ⇒⊥ is false and ⊥⇒ > is true. Axioms, theorems Discrete mathematics I Logic Emil Vatai Basics Zeroth-order logic First-order logic Theories Definition Axioms (or postulates) are formulas in a theory which we consider trivially true. Theorems are formulas derived from axioms using the rules of logic. Example In euclidean geometry one of the postulates (axioms) is: A straight line segment can be drawn joining any two points. A theorem is that the sum of angles in a triangle is π radians (or 180°)
© Copyright 2024