REAL POSSIBILITIES, INDETERMINISM AND FREE WILL Konstanz (Germany), 18-21 March 2015 Programme and Abstracts tagxedo.com Programme Wednesday, 18 March 2015 16:00 Registration (Level A7) 17:00-18:30 Keynote Lecture (Room A701) Ruth Groff: Powers, Agency and the Free Will Problematic Chair: Thomas M¨ uller 18:30 Reception (Level A7) Thursday, 19 March 2015 (Room A701) 09:00-10:30 Thomas M¨ uller and group: Introduction 10:45-11:45 Peter Øhrstrøm: A.N. Prior’s Philosophical and Tense-Logical Analysis of the Problem of Human Freedom Chair: Daan Evers 12:00-13:00 Helen Steward: What is Determinism?—Why we should Ditch the Entailment Definition Chair: Daan Evers 13:00-14:30 Lunch (Mensa, K6 + K7) 14:30-15:30 Rani Lill Anjum & Stephen Mumford: Causation is Not Your Enemy Chair: Markus Schrenk 15:45-16:45 John Pemberton: Possibilities from Powers Chair: Markus Schrenk 17:00-18:00 Barbara Vetter: Dispositions, Necessary Masks, and Counterpossibles Chair: Markus Schrenk 19:00 Conference Dinner: Wessenberg, Wessenbergstraße 41 Friday, 20 March 2015 09:00-10:00 Plenary Talk (Room A 701) Geert Keil: What Is Wrong with the Luck Objection? Chair: Katarzyna Paprzycka Parallel Session 1 (Room A704) Parallel Session 2 (Room A701) G. Torrengo & S. Iaquinto: The Invisible Thin Red Line Verena Wagner: Reconciling Projects Chair: Niko Strobach Chair: Katarzyna Paprzycka Jesse Mulder: Two Perspectives on Time Anne-Sophie Spann: Indeterministic Compatibilism: A Third Way between Compatibilism and Incompatibilism? Chair: Niko Strobach Chair: Roland P¨ollinger Tibor F¨ oldes: Double-indexing, Propositional Identity and Obtainment Jacob Rosenthal: Libertarianism and the Problem of Clear Cases Chair: Niko Strobach Chair: Roland P¨ollinger 13:00-14:30 Lunch (Mensa, K6 + K7) Lunch (Mensa, K6 + K7) 14:30-15:30 Jan Broersen: A Spatial Stit-logic Approach to Real Possibilities Gottfried Seebaß: Can Quantum Physics Ground Indeterminism? Philosophical Remarks on a Controversial Problem Chair: Hans Rott Chair: David Widerker Simon Kittle: Abilities, Circumstances and Possibilities Federica Della Grotta: What is the Future that Sets us Free? Chair: Hans Rott Chair: David Widerker Florian Fischer: Localized Dispositions and Global Laws Anna Drozdzewska: Free Will, Indeterminism and the Missing Context Chair: Hans Rott Chair: David Widerker 10:15-11:00 11:15-12:00 12:15-13:00 15:45-16:30 16:45-17:30 21:00-21:00 Drinks: Barbarossa, “Stauferkeller”, Obermarkt 8-12 Saturday, 21 March 2015 09:00-10:00 10:15-11:00 11:00-11:45 12:00-13:30 Parallel Session 1 (Room A704) Parallel Session 2 (Room A701) Tomasz Placek: In Praise of Forks Erasmus Mayr: The Relevance of Alternatives Chair: Alberto Zanardo Chair: Jacob Rosenthal J. Wawer & L. Wro´ nski: A New Theory of Historical Counterfactuals Georg Gasser: Human Agents as Rational Powerful Particulars Chair: Alberto Zanardo Chair: Jacob Rosenthal Frederik Van De Putte: Possibilities, Abilities, and Obligations Katarzyna Paprzycka: Two-Way Two-Gear Powers Chair: Alberto Zanardo Chair: Jacob Rosenthal Keynote Lecture (Room A701) Tim O’Connor: The Dead Hand of the Past Chair: Hans Briegel 13:30 Closing of conference and departure: snacks will be provided Abstracts Rani Lill Anjum (Norwegian University of Life Sciences) Stephen Mumford (University of Nottingham) Causation is Not Your Enemy Causation plays a vital role in the free will debate so it is among the top priorities that it be understood right. There is a view that merely being subject to causal laws is already enough to compromise our freedom. Watson (1982, p. 2), for example, speaks as if we might be robbed of free will simply in virtue of our actions having prior causes. This trades on an alleged link between causation and determinism. There might then be a temptation to look for free will in an ability to step outside the regular causal nexus. That would be a big mistake, effectively attributing supernatural powers to agency. Rather, we should understand causation as something that is on our side: on the side of freedom. It is through the exercise of causal powers that we are agents and through which we have gained free will. The last thing we need is to be liberated from causation, then, for that would thereby enslave us to pure chance. It is clear, however, that causation has been misunderstood in terms of determining, necessitating and controlling. We argue for a different understanding of causation as something that we use to get what we want. Causes acting upon us can certainly influence us but we also make a causal contribution to what is brought about. The correct account can thus give us both freedom and responsibility. Jan Broersen (Utrecht University) A Spatial Stit-logic Approach to Real Possibilities We extend stit logic by adding a spatial dimension. This enables us to distinguish between abilities and opportunities of agents. Abilities are independent of locations, but depend on agents. Opportunities do depend on locations, but are independent of agents. The possibility to see to the truth of a condition in space and time is defined as the combination of the ability and the opportunity to do so. We explain the relation with Belnap’s branching space-time theory. We argue that in Belnap’s theory the agent has been lost in the physics-oriented analysis. The focus on agent-relative abilities, as we define them in our theory, brings the autonomous choice making agent back into the space-time picture. We show how our semantics naturally distinguishes between different kinds of histories; histories that reflect real (factual) possibilities and histories that reflect counterfactual possibilities (of a particular hypothetical kind). Furthermore, we discuss how the spatial picture sheds a clear light on the conceptual problems surrounding the central stit property of “independence of agency”. We provide a clarification of the concept and will argue that the phrase is a misnomer; the better term would be exactly its opposite, that is, “dependence of agency”. Federica Della Grotta (University of Cambridge) What is the Future that Sets us Free? I argue that a metaphysical open future is not a necessary element to understand the distinctive kind of agency human agents attribute to themselves. Instead, I argue that the requirement is considerably lower: all that is needed is only an epistemic open future. By further exploring the possibilities offered by epistemic openness, I aim to offer a convincing story about the attribution of autonomous human agency. As a starting point, I distinguish between two claims typically made by incompatibilists. The first claim says that the absence of an open future entails that no one can choose otherwise, thereby ruling out free will. The second says that in the absence of an open future we are not the real ‘source’ of our actions. I endorse the first claim while I argue against the second. To this end, I offer an original understanding of the role of deliberation as a first-person, normative space in which we attribute an active role to ourselves, and in which we recognize ourselves as free agents. Anna Drozdzewska (Universit´e Catholique de Louvain) Free Will, Indeterminism and the Missing Context With the recent advancement in neuroscience, the debate of free will gained new life. Most of the neuroscientific experiments investigating free will, starting from Libet’s along with his successors, are based on specific assumptions, which will be analyzed in detail, as a starting point of this presentation. I will examine the potential issues with those premises, influencing not only the conclusions of those experiments but also our understanding of the problem, determining thus further experiments. I will present a new approach to free will, which hypothesizes that, instead of a momentary occurrence, as its usually conceived, it is exercised as a process. In the second part of the talk, I will show how my proposal could be realized on a neuronal level, based on the argument by P.U. Tse, and I will argue the informational patterns Tse recognizes as paramount in his criterial causation are similar to what, for Habermas, would be an objective brain: the world of shared symbols transferred through language. I will conclude the presentation by discussing the additional advantages of the approach, focusing on its solution to the problem of randomness in the indeterministic account of free will. Florian Fischer (University of Bonn, University of Cologne) Localized Dispositions and Global Laws One important problem for dispositional theories of laws of nature is the tension between the locality of dispositions and the globality of laws. Already within the debate about dispositions a similar question arises: the so-called generality problem. How do dispositions synchronise the behaviour they produce if each disposition is only a local property? Dispositional theories of laws of nature claim to be the best candidates to explain natural necessity. Their opponents allegedly either just posit necessity out of the blue (ADT theories) or abandon natural necessity altogether (Neo-Humean theories). But also the laws’ natural necessity seems endangered by the locality of the dispositions. I propose a theory of dispositions as natural kinds which come with inbuilt combination principles for other natural kinds. These ensure the global and modal behavioural stability and thus are good candidates to ground universal and necessary laws. Tibor F¨ oldes (ELTE Budapest) Double-indexing, Propositional Identity and Obtainment My paper focuses on the connections between our indeterminist intuitions about the future and the various semantic treatments of the double indexing phenomenon in intensional languages with indexicals. The two paradigmatic theories of the analysis will be John MacFarlane’s relativist assessment-sensitive theory of future tense and Nathan Salmon’s theory of complex semantic content with four different strata based on his classic eternalist understanding of propositions. I’ll argue that absolutism isn’t incompatible with indeterminism at all, if we don’t leave the Stalnakerian concept of propositional functions and their structures out of account. My paper discusses the different ontological intuitions about truth-making that can be found in the background of the different handling of double-indexing. These divergent ontologies are mirrored in the different predictions about the behavior of the meta-language truth predicates. While the truth predicate concerning the truth-bearers representing future facts is context-sensitive in a simple way from a relativist stance, the eternalist indeterminism treats the truth-predicate itself doubleindexed. I’ll argue that these two intuitions about the future presuppose different relations between time and obtainment of truth-makers. Georg Gasser (University of Innsbruck) Human Agents as Rational Powerful Particulars This paper contributes to the current debate on agent-causal power by proceeding in four steps: First, I briefly outline Tim O’Connor’s account which claims that there is genuine agent-causal power, that is, the agent herself being a cause of her action. Second, I present an objection against this account. It claims that the agent does not dispose of any particular agent-causal power because the real powers are the powerful properties of an agent. Third, in the bulk of my paper I propose a way how this line of reasoning can be rejected. I argue that the distinction between powerful properties (of a substance) on the one hand and the substance itself (bearing these properties) on the other hand rests on a problematic metaphysical understanding of the relationship between substance and (its) properties. I propose a more accurate understanding of this relationship. Finally, in the light of these reflections I conclude with some remarks about how I think that agent-causation should be spelled out. Ruth Groff (Saint Louis University) Powers, Agency and the Free Will Problematic Realism about causal powers has begun to make its way into contemporary debates over free will. Most powers theorists will say that agents, like other substances, have real powers to engage in activity, in doing of various kinds. It is a natural thought to add that agents, having the remarkable power of consciousness, are able to exercise or to decline to exercise at least some of our other powers as we see fit, i.e., freely. A common rejoinder is that agents would be no freer in a powers-based environment than in a non-powers-based one, because (it is said) the exercise of agential powers is deterministically triggered by the prior display of the powers of other things. Against this backdrop, I want to try to clarify just how and why a non-Humean commitment to the existence of real causal powers might make a difference for the theorizing of agency. My working assumption is that there is significant confusion about what the commitment in question actually involves, what it amounts to at the most basic level. Moreover, I think that there are interesting philosophical reasons for the lack of clarity. I will begin, therefore, by talking about why it might be hard for someone who doesn’t believe in the phenomenon in question to understand what the term “power” is meant to pick out. Then, in the central part of the talk, I will offer a sketch of how a properly conceived powers-based ontology reconfigures (or, technically speaking, sublates) the existing free will problematic in analytic philosophy—a problematic that, in its present form, presupposes a nomological and/or regularity-based metaphysics. Finally, I will talk just a little bit about whether or not every genuinely powers-based metaphysics shows the “powers-based determinism” objection to be ill-conceived. It may be that one needs a position that is more like Aristotle’s than not, in order to do the job. Geert Keil (Humboldt University, Berlin) What Is Wrong with the Luck Objection? The luck objection is commonly regarded as the most serious challenge to event-causal libertarian accounts of free will. The objection says that (1) if there exist no deterministic causal links between mental processes and decisions, then it is a matter of sheer luck whether the decision occurs. It further assumes that (2) luck precludes the kind of control that is required both for moral responsibility and for any kind of free will worth wanting. The phrase “being a matter of luck” has a number of readings. The only reading that libertarians qua indeterminists are committed to is “not being deterministically caused”. The paper argues that the dialectical situation in which the luck objection is put forward is underexplored in the literature. It argues further that agnostic compatibilism is in no better position to answer the challenge than libertarianism, while deterministic compatibilism cannot explain how the existence of deterministic links between pro-attitudes, decisions and bodily actions should enhance the agent’s control. Pereboom argues as follows: “On an event-causal libertarian picture, the relevant causal conditions antecedent to the decision, i.e., the occurrence of certain agent-involving events, do not settle whether the decision will occur”, since they do not render the decision 100% probable. Therefore, the agent “will lack the control required for basic desert moral responsibility” (Pereboom 2014, 32). The second step of the argument from luck—i.e., the assumption that in order to be morally responsible, an agent must be able to guarantee that the decision takes place—seems misguided in the first place. Human agents have no such abilities, not even in a deterministic world. Hence both compatibilist and incompatibilist accounts of free will are ill-advised to require such abilities. Simon Kittle (University of Sheffield) Abilities, Circumstances and Possibilities In this paper I propose a way of individuating ability properties which requires the complete definition of an ability to include, in addition to the stimulus and manifestation, a set of circumstances against which the manifestation is to be expected and a parameter which concerns what Barbara Vetter has called “modal force”. Using this view it is possible to make sense of a distinction in the free will literature that is often made, but not often made clearly: that between general abilities on the one hand and specific, particular, or local abilities on the other. I use the account of ability individuation presented to articulate two ways that an ability might be general. And with the two senses of generality clearly separated, I then present a number of principles which aim to summarise which abilities are most relevant to the agent’s control. This then promises an account of which possibilities are genuine or real for an agent. Erasmus Mayr (Oxford University, Humboldt University, Berlin) The Relevance of Alternatives Most arguments for incompatibilism are based on the idea that moral responsibility presupposes that the agent could have acted otherwise. With regard to responsibility for blameworthy actions, this requirement is often motivated by the claim that it would be unfair to blame or punish someone who could not avoid doing what he did. For praiseworthy actions, however, the issue is more complicated, and the requirement of alternative possibilities has been rejected by several philosophers. I will examine both the plausibility of fairness-based arguments for the requirement in the case of non-blameworthy actions and will discuss the consequences of a powers- or disposition-based account of free will for the question whether responsibility in these cases requires alternative possibilities. Jesse Mulder (Utrecht University) Two Perspectives on Time Frege taught us how to understand one form of predication: an atemporal one. There is also a different, temporal form of predication. Accordingly, there are two fundamentally different approaches to time: a reductive one, aiming to account for time in terms of Frege’s atemporal predication, and a non-reductive one, insisting that the temporal form of predication is irreducible. I argue that three of the main debates in contemporary philosophy of time (endurantism–perdurantism, A-theory–B-theory, and presentism–eternalism) largely boil down to mere quarrels amongst reductive approaches, and thus fail to hit the level of fundamentality they aim for. The real issue, I suggest, is whether we should reduce or not. Once we recognise this, we can start considering truly anti-reductionist versions of endurantism, A-theory, and presentism. Tim O’Connor (Indiana University) The Dead Hand of the Past The problem of free will is in large measure the problem of understanding how causally conditioned agents can be loci of ultimate control: how can human actions originate, and not merely conduct, causal influence upon the world? That our acts be causal undetermined is necessary for us to exert such ultimate control, but it is not enough. Also necessary is that our activity be fundamental in the causal order, in the way we might suppose is true of elementary particles. But how might this be? How might causally conditioned and composed entities (as we are) be fundamental, non-derivative causes? I will attempt to make progress towards an answer to this question. Peter Øhrstrøm (Aalborg University) A.N. Prior’s Philosophical and Tense-logical Analysis of the Problem of Human Freedom Arthur Norman Prior was born in 1914 in Masterton, New Zealand. In 1932 he went to Otago University at Dunedin. He set out to study medicine, but after a short time he instead went into philosophy. During his first year as a Philosophy student, he joined the Presbyterian denomination. He became a very active member of the Presbyterian community. As such he felt that a Christian had to be a determinist, since he would have to believe in a perfect divine foreknowledge. On the other hand, even a determinist will have to be able to give an account of the human feeling of free choice. Prior became a specialist in the debates regarding the logical tension between the doctrine of divine foreknowledge and the doctrine of human freedom. He found inspiration in the works of Aristotle, Diodorus, St. Thomas, Ockham, Peirce, Lukasiewicz and several others. Based on the study of these famous contributions he formulated his tense-logic and demonstrated how the problem can be analyzed in terms of this formalism. In fact, he argued that in the discussion concerning divine foreknowledge and human freedom there are only a few possible positions. Gradually, it became more and more difficult for Prior to accept determinism and to reject human freedom of choice. Finally, he left the Presbyterian denomination, and he claimed that human freedom should in fact be maintained as an important philosophical tenet. In terms of his tense-logic this means that there are future contingents. When Prior died in 1969 he left a number of unpublished papers and notes. This material is now being edited and published. Based on recent studies in Prior’s Nachlass we can in fact obtain a much better understanding of Prior’s analysis of the future contingency problem as well as his own personal way from a defence of determinism to a strong belief in human freedom. Katarzyna Paprzycka (University of Warsaw) Two-Way Two-Gear Powers It is natural to think that the following biconditional holds for any agent with two-way powers: (A) It is in α’s power to φ iff it is in α’s power not to φ. I distinguish between two grades of an ability to φ: the first grade ability (roughly, reliability in φing) and the second grade ability (merely occasional success in φing). I define three two-way power concepts: control, doability and power∗ . φing is in α’s control [is doable for α] iff α has the first [second] grade ability to φ and the first [second] grade ability not to φ. It is within α’s power∗ to φ iff α has the first grade ability to φ and at least the second grade ability not to φ. (A) does hold for control and doability but not for power∗ (cases of an addict and a person with Parkinson’s disease serve as illustrations). I argue that power∗ seems to do much work frequently thought to be required of the notion of ability in philosophical discussions. I focus on: the Butler problem, the normative theory of omission (which requires the ability to do otherwise), the ought-implies-can principle. John Pemberton (London School of Economics) Possibilities from Powers Powers are producers of change, we should suppose—and hence powers give rise to possibilities. This view contrasts with others which take possibilities as central: e.g. the various possible world accounts and now-popular counterfactual approaches, such as the interventionist approach of Woodward, where offering an account of how possibilities come about is not in focus. Powers exercise, in general, when they are in suitable contact with other correlate powers. Thus configurations of powers and the features in which they inhere can give rise to the exercising of powers, and hence the changing of that configuration—over time such changing is then what may be called a process of change. The processes of change to which a configuration (or type of configuration) can give rise are possibilities associated with that configuration, as are the configurations which result from such changes. By reference to Aristotle’s ontology of powers and change, I outline this this-world account of possibilities. Powers are often empirically available entities within the world associated with features which we can recognise and perhaps control—they thus license use of analytic and experimental methods, and hence make sense of many of the practices of contemporary science. Many of our most well-established empirical methods thus make use of possibilities which may be taken to arise from powers. Tomasz Placek (Jagiellonian University, Krak´ow) In Praise of Forks Although general relativistic spacetimes with non-isometric extensions satisfy the standard definition of indeterminism (due to J. Butterfield), they are rarely taken as evidence for indeterminism of general relativity. A peculiar feature of these extensions is that their union does not contain forks (bifurcating timelike curves). It looks as if the spacetime had more than one extension, but no object faced alternative possible evolutions. Clearly, this sounds like a statement of determinism. I thus suggest that forks be made a criterion of indeterminism. Forks are almost everywhere in our thinking about indeterminism: in our intuitive approach to alternative possibilities, in Prior’s (1967) branching time analysis, in Belnap’s (1992) branching space-times analysis, and even in my (2014) GR-friendly branching, devised to handle closed timelike curves. Moreover, a fork can be extracted from a Lewis-style divergent pair of worlds that witnesses indeterminism in Lewisian sense. And, forks would occur in a union of non-isometric multiple maximally global extensions of an appropriate initial data set, provided such non-isometric multiple extensions existed (they are prohibited by the Bruchat-Geroch theorem). In contrast, forks are absent in a controversial case of non-isometric multiple extensions of a maximally global spacetime. Oddly, a union of such extensions is non-Hausdorff (signaling alternative spacetimes), but forks are absent. I would illustrate this phenomenon on extensions of Misner’s spacetime, and contrast it with fork-like patterns introduced before. Jacob Rosenthal (University of Konstanz) Libertarianism and the Problem of Clear Cases Recent years have seen the development of new arguments in favour of and new varieties of libertarianism. It has gained many adherents and can no longer be called a minority view. I would like to highlight what seems to be a lacuna in all libertarian accounts, which concerns the specific role indeterminism is supposed to play in our practical deliberations, decisions and actions. The embarrassment is brought out most clearly by the various cases of decisions in which there are strong and quite obvious reasons for one of the options and only relatively weak ones in favour of the disjunction of the alternatives. What is the proper role of indeterminism in such cases? The problem with all answers given so far is that they either abandon libertarianism to a conspicuously high degree, leaving indeterminism no essential role to play, or that they link indeterminism to some serious defect in the person’s rationality, making implausible assumptions about what is genuinely possible and conferring a purely negative role upon indeterminism. I spell this out dealing with the accounts of Helen Steward and Geert Keil, respectively. Furthermore, I argue that some versions of compatibilism face a similar dilemma. Gottfried Seebaß (University of Konstanz) Can Quantum Physics Ground Indeterminism? Philosophical Remarks on a Controversial Problem From the diagnosis that the denial of determinism represents a necessary (though not sufficient) condition for human freedom, this talk enquires into the question of whether quantum physics as a fundamental theory of matter is in a position to justify the claim that the physical world is (significantly, if only partially) undetermined. Indeed, many physicists and philosophers of science make just this assertion. However, upon closer examination the claim is highly dubitable. In neither a theoretical nor even an ontological respect can quantum physics count as unrestrictedly “indeterministic”. When such inferences are drawn, this is (in addition to extra-physical reasons) the result of a substantial overestimation of the significance that the features relevantly distinguishing quantum from classical physics (quantization, probabilism, indeterminacy of measurement, doubtful applicability of basic ontological terms, etc.) have for indeterminism. Thus, as I will show, we cannot speak of a proof for the time being, but must content ourselves with a sustained assault on the na¨ıve faith in determinism and its unlimited applicability that developed in the wake of the classical mechanics of the Modern period. Anne Sophie Spann (University of Exeter) Indeterministic Compatibilism: Incompatibilism? A Third way between Compatibilism and John Dupr´e has recently proposed a third way between compatibilism and incompatibilism: indeterministic compatibilism. Indeterministic compatibilism rests on the metaphysical assumption that agency is a genuinely biological phenomenon, involving a special kind of indeterminism. On this basis, then, it is argued that agency can be made comprehensible as being free in a sense that does neither reduce freedom to the absence of external pressure and obstacles nor turns it into a matter of mere chance. In my talk, I want to present and critically discuss this position. I will also reflect on the general prospects of a biological approach to the problem of free will. Helen Steward (University of Leeds) What is Determinism?—Why we should Ditch the Entailment Definition J.L. Austin once famously claimed that determinism was “a name of nothing clear” (‘Ifs and Cans’, Philosophical Papers, p.231). But today many philosophers working on the free will problem operate happily with a definition of determinism that is pretty well accepted on all hands. I call it the ‘entailment definition’ and it states, roughly, that determinism is the thesis that for any given time, a complete statement of the nonrelational facts about that time, together with a complete statement of the laws of nature, entails every truth as to what happens after that time. In this paper, I argue that acceptance of the entailment definition has been a mistake—and make some suggestions about what ought to be put in its place. Giuliano Torrengo (University of Milan) Samuele Iaquinto (University of Milan) The Invisible Thin Red Line Our aim is to argue that the adoption of an unrestricted principle of bivalence is compatible with a metaphysics that (i) denies that the future is real, (ii) adopts nomological indeterminism, and (iii) exploits a branching structure to provide a semantics for future contingent claims. To this end, within a non-standard tense realist framework, we elaborate—after Kit Fine’s terminology—a fragmentalist presentism, according to which reality is divided up into maximally coherent collections of tensed facts. In this way, we show how to reconcile a genuinely A-theoretic branching-time model with the idea that there is a branch corresponding to the thin red line, that is, the branch that will turn out to be the actual future history of the world. Barbara Vetter (Humboldt University, Berlin) Dispositions, Necessary Masks, and Counterpossibles A disposition is masked when, for some reason, its manifestation would be prevented even if the right kind of conditions for it were to obtain. A glass’s fragility, for instance, may be masked by the glass being safely packed in styrofoam. In standard cases, masks are such that they could in principle be removed. But might there be necessary masks? In other words, might objects have dispositions that they are necessarily prevented from manifesting? This paper will explore the question whether there might be necessary masks before the background of dispositionalism about modality, the view that metaphysical modality is a matter of which dispositions are possessed by actually existing individual objects. The question about necessary masks will be shown to pose a prima facie dilemma for dispositionalists: if there are necessary masks, then the existence of a disposition is not sufficient for metaphysical possibility; but if there are no necessary masks, then dispositionalists have trouble accounting for counterpossibles, i.e., counterfactuals with metaphysically impossible antecedents. I will sketch ways of dealing with the dilemma and saving the dispositional account of metaphysical modality from the threat of necessary masks. Frederik Van De Putte (Ghent University) Possibilities, Abilities, and Obligations My talk will consist of two parts. In the first, I will show that a currently dominant approach to agency and ability in the logical literature (i.e., STIT logic and its many variants) cannot adequately cope with normative claims that concern the abilities of agents. More precisely, “ought to be able” and “is able” are simply equivalent, if we use the most common deontic extension of STIT logic. In the second part of the talk, I will propose and investigate three variants of STIT logic which fill this lacuna, comparing their inferential strength and philosophical underpinnings. If time permits, I will also consider an older proposal by Richmond Thomason from the viewpoint of abilities. Verena Wagner (University of Konstanz) Reconciling Projects Compatibilism is the thesis that free agency is possible in a deterministic world. In order to spell out a theory of free agency, the compatibilist, so it seems, only has to take into account the possible truth of determinism. The question as to whether and how indeterminism may be reconciled with free agency seems to be none of the compatibilist’s business. But this view is mistaken. Being a convinced compatibilist myself, I aim at showing that compatibilists have to care more about reconciling indeterminism with free agency if they do not want to commit themselves to the determinist position, but rather stay neutral with regard to this question. In this talk, I will show that proponents of the most prevalent compatibilist line of thought, the so-called “neutral compatibilists”, are committed to affirming the compatibility of freedom and indeterminism when they claim that there are actually free agents in our world. I will point out that neutral compatibilists not only have to allow for some random occurrences that are irrelevant for our agency, but have to side with the libertarian in her aim to refute the luck objection. I will explain how the neutral compatibilist can defend both compatibility claims (free agency is compatible with determinism and indeterminism) by the same arguments. Jacek Wawer (Jagiellonian University, Krak´ow) Leszek Wro´ nski (Jagiellonian University, Krak´ow) A New Theory of Historical Counterfactuals In the paper we investigate the semantics of historical counterfactuals in indeterministic contexts. We claim that “plain” and “necessitated” counterfactuals differ in meaning. To substantiate this claim, we propose a new semantic treatment of historical counterfactuals in Branching Time. We supplement our semantics with supervaluationist postsemantics, thanks to which we can explain away the intuitions which seem to talk in favor of the identification of “would” with “would necessarily”.
© Copyright 2024