SEMIKOLON Artefakter Artifacts T i d s s k r i f t f o r I d é h i s t o r i e , S e m i o t i k o g F i l o s o f i ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 Semikolon har som semikolon i skriftsproget funktion af at være et både-og tegn; både afhængigt af historien, der gik forud, men samtidigt (og vigtigst) peger det frem og vil noget mere. Et ; indstiller således opmærksomheden på det, der kommer efter. Og følgelig giver tegnet ikke mening i sig selv men kræver en sammenhæng at blive set i. Som sådan er tegnet kun den halve sandhed, idet sandheden og semantikken først udfoldes i interpretationen. Tidsskriftets intention er derfor ikke at være dogmatisk og monologisk sandhedspostulerende, men i stedet dialogisk, ”it takes two to do research”, hvilket igen vil sige at tilvejebringe et åbent forum. Dette forum skabte en flok studerende ved idéhistorie, semiotik og filosofi – alle ved Århus Universitet, da de i sommeren 2000 grundlagde tidsskriftet Semikolon. Målet er – i form af artikler, oversættelser, interviews, faglig kritik, polemik og boganmeldelser – indenfor emnerne idéhistorie, semiotik og filosofi at skabe og udbrede en kritisk tværvidenskabelig dialog mellem studerende og forskere på højere læreanstalter i Danmark og Norden. At Semikolon er tværvidenskabeligt betyder, at vi ikke ønsker at præsentere verden vha. en bestemt metodisk tilgang eller vidensstrategi. Vi ønsker at præsentere verden gennem så mange forskellige tilgange som muligt, for at afdække verden og tilgangene, og for at skabe dialog. Det eneste krav i en sådan dialog er, at der tales ud fra et minimum af fælles forståelse. Semikolon nr. 28 Artefakter ”[…] but now that i had finished, the beauty of the dream had vanished, and breathless disgust and horror filled my heart. Unable to endure the aspect of the being i had created […]” (Frankenstein - Mary Shelley 1818) S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 3 - 5 Vi er omgivet af dem, bruger dem hver dag og bær dem på vores krop. Men hvor ofte stopper vi op og overvejer, hvad de betyder for os, ikke enkeltvis men som overordnet kategori, af - ja af hvad? Kan man bare nøjes med at kalde det ting og sager? Livløse genstande? Mærkværdigt at vi har et ord som klassificerer disse både brugbare men til tider også upåfaldende ting. Vi nærer et så tæt forhold til disse genstande at vi sjældent overvejer deres betydning og langt fra deres filosofiske betydning. Nogle fag beskæftiger sig dog med det historiske aspekt af disse genstande. Teknologiske spring som for alvor rykker i vores verdensopfattelse. Stanley Kubrick bruger i hans film ”2001: A Space Odyssey” den visuelle metafor med en stor sort monolith til at beskrive disse teknologiske spring. I en af de første scener i filmen møder en gruppe aber denne monolith. I dette møde sker der noget uforklaret med disse aber, men man ser senere en af aberne passere forbi resterne af et nu afdødt dyr. Inden længe studser vores hovedperson over dyrets lårbensknogle, der ligger blandt de afdøde rester. Efter lidt prøven sig frem, bliver der gjort en erkendelse. Lårbensknoglen viser sig at være en genstand med stor drabelig effekt! Aben begynder i lyset af denne erfaring til Richard Strauss’ monumentale ”Also sprach Zarathustra” - i en blodrus, med voldsomme sving af lårbensknoglen at tilintetgøre resterne af det afdøde dyr. Denne scene er forvarslende for, hvad teknologisk udvikling potentielt kan gøre ved subjekter. Kubrick illustrerer her en interessant pointe for vores forhold til ”brugstøj”. Før erkendelsen af lårbensknoglens nytte som våben, havde knoglerne ingen værdi for aben, dets eksistens var ligegyldig og kunne mest af alt betragtes som værende i vejen. På et eller andet tidspunkt i sin forbipassage bliver abens relation til denne genstand drastisk forandret, og dermed også abens psykologiske tilstand - til skræk og rædsel for aberne af den rivaliserende flok. Side 4 Redaktionen Knoglens fysiske realitet er ikke at benægte. Den lå der inden aben tog fat i den og ændrede ikke sin fysiske form. På trods af det ændrede den sig drastisk i mødet med aben. Den blev til noget mere - til en anden type genstand. Den blev ”genopdaget” på ny, som noget andet end det, det var forinden. Denne genstand gik altså fra en udefineret epistemisk status til at være det vi (i aristotelisk forstand) kalder et ”artefakt”. En brugs-genstand som er blevet lavet til et bestemt formål, noget som har en ”forfatter” eller skaber, selvom skabelsen blot bestod i at aben realiserede dens destruktive potentiale. På samme måde nærer mennesker relation til genstande omkring dem, nogle genstande opstår slet ikke i vores ”erkendelsesfelt”, andre træder konstant frem, mens en helt tredje kategori er en forlængelse af os selv og hermed bliver en del af os. Artefakter er en klasse af genstande, som optræder for os i dagligdagen; ”hvor er min bærbar”, ”det er koldt jeg bør tage en jakke på”, men samtidigt er det genstande vi sjældent påtaler og deres epistemologiske og ontologiske status i verdenen er alt for sjældent gransket. En simpel udredning af artefaktens fysiske karakteristika dækker på ingen måde dens betydning og indflydelse på subjektet. Min relation til min lommeregner kan på den ene side forstås som relationen til en brugsgenstand, men er også en udvikling i den måde jeg forholder mig til matematik og det at regne. ”Unge mennesker læser og regner dårligere end nogensinde”, nogle mener at et sådant udtryk misforstår relationen unge har til lommeregnere, computere og lignende. Vi lever i en tid, hvor artefakterne indlejret i den teknologi vi omgives med påvirker os på mange måder. Nogle teoretikere vil endda gå så langt som til at hævde, at de ikke blot påvirker men er med til at skabe og forme os til de mennesker vi er i dag. Det at vi blev i stand til at skrive noget ned, formede menneskeheden og de mennesker, der var involveret. På samme måde står vi i dag med internettet og de sociale medier som en formende genstand. Den er med til at forme den måde vi er sociale på, den måde vi forholder os til andre mennesker på og hvordan vi fremtræder. Men dette er naturligvis kun én bestanddel af det menneskelige virke i det enogtyvende århundrede. Robot-teknologien buldrer derudaf og flere og flere arbejdsopgaver bliver udskiftet med maskiner. Artefakterne indtager vores arbejdsopgaver, ja selv krigsførelse, som nu bliver udført med ubemandede droner. Snart måske også varetagelsen af de syge, og måske også socialt samvær, når vi er ensomme? Hvordan bliver vores forhold til det kropslige påvirket af denne udvikling? En distancering mellem det fysiske og det sociale hvis yderste konsekvens måske er en afvikling af fysisk nærvær eller en kompensation i form af mekaniske venner og kærester? Hvis det er rigtigt at den teknologi, der omgiver os og som vi gør brug af og som er en så stor del af vores liv vitterligt er med til at forme os som mennesker, hvad siger det så om os som mennesker? De genstande og ting, som vi tager for givet og som gør vores liv så nemt. Er de ”unaturlige” og dermed også forkerte? Eller er denne påvirkning blot noget vi skal være opmærksomme på, uden at der behøves at drages drastiske normative slutninger på denne baggrund? Denne udgave af Semikolon har som tema Artefakter i bred forstand, vi inviterer hermed læseren til eftertanke i vores selvskab om de genstande i vores liv som ikke umiddelbart lader til at have filosofisk gods, men som ved nærmere granskning viser sig at have stor betydning. Leder tionerne forbundet med brugen af disse sindsudvidende artefakter. Vi er subjekter i den senmoderne tid. Grundet dette hævder Nis Primdahl i nummerets fjerde artikel, at vi er indlejret i dennes strukturelle tidslighed. Dette udmøntes i samfundet som en konstant samfundsmæssig acceleration ikke mindst påvirket af de artefakter, vi omgives af. I denne artikel undersøger forfatteren hvilken indflydelse disse artefakter har på vores kontrol over vores tid og hvorvidt vi er i stand til at øge eller sænke den. Kan vi på nogen måde undgå denne acceleration eller er denne tanke også blot afledt af en ideologisk modvægt til den senmodernes tidslighed? I nummerets næstsidste artikel bearbejdes det besynderlige danske overgangsritual for børn, hvor sutten hænges på et træ for at markere en overskridelse af barnets behov for sutten. Som udvekslingsstuderende studser Natalia Hoffmann over denne noget egenartede praksis og giver i denne artikel sin beskrivelse af den som den rituelle handling det er udtryk for. Hendes fokus er på artefakterne, både sutten men også træets symbolske dimensioner. Hvad er musik og hvorfor har vi den? ”genstanden” musik tjener ingen nytte evolutionært set, så hvorfor har den så stor betydning for mennesker og hvor kommer den fra? Allesandro Miani undersøger i nummerets sidste artikel de evolutionære faktorer relevante for menneskets erhvervelse af musikken som artefakt og dens betydning for os. Prænatale indflydelser fra forældrenes stemmer gang og lignende viser sig at have stor indflydelse på udviklingen af den musikalske sans og at musik har langt større fordele på neurovidenskabens præmisser end evolutionsteorien umiddelbart vil tyde på. God fornøjelse med Semikolon nr. 28! Side 5 Artiklerne i dette nummer af Semikolon Temaets første artikel tager René Descartes i forsvar imod et af de mest hyppige anfægtelser gjort imod ham. Her tales om antagelsen om, at kroppen blot er en mekanisk, afskåret ”klump” som ikke har noget med ”os” at gøre. Det der naturligvis menes med ”os” er ”sjælen”, som så er placeret i koglekirtlen i hjernen. Christoffer Basse Eriksen gennemgår denne påståede position hos Descartes og viser os at det måske ikke er helt så sort/hvidt, som det ofte foregives af hans kritikere. Juan Olvido undersøger i temaets anden artikel, hvordan vi skal forstå vores forhold til brugen af ulovlig cannabis og dens plads i vores samfund. I undersøgelsen ser han på de relevante sociale og kulturelle faktorer og overvejer deres indflydelse på vores brug af de korresponderende artefakter. De sociokulturelle-artefaktskabende elementer ved brugen af disse ulovlige midler viser sig at transcendere nationale grænser og støtter en form for subkultur centreret omkring cannabis. Men samtidigt forekommer der også et normaliserende effekt af cannabis brug via en bredere eksponering i de kulturelle produkter. Vores brug af verdslige genstande kan hurtigt blive til forlængelse af os selv. Vores hukommelse sidder i telefonen: telefon numre, datoer på fødselsdage eller hvornår vi skal aflevere næste opgave. Det at vi uddelegerer kognitive egenskaber ud i verdenen er blevet teoretiseret omkring af Chalmers og Clark som ”Extended mind”. Dette emne tager Kevin Crowley op i nummerets tredje artikel. Her kigger han kritisk og oplysende på, hvordan omverdenens artefakter fungerer som en forlængelse af vores kognitive kapaciteter. Med interessante eksempler fra historiefortællinger som Homer fortæller forfatteren om implika- C A L L F O R PA P E R S S E M I KO LO N N R. 2 9 Kærlighed Forestil dig, at man kunne kureres for kærlighed. Slippe for hjertesorg og længsel efter den som ikke vil have en. Hos de fleste opstår straks en stærk modvilje mod denne tanke. Men hvorfor egentlig? Der er nemlig et lommefilosofisk aksiom, at kærlighed er årsagen til vores eksistens. Så denne modvilje kan måske have mere på sig end som så? Kierkegaard mente, at kærlighed var en egenskab givet af Gud; trangen til at elske og blive elsket. At kaste sin kærlighed på en anden er en frihedshandling, som hverken er forudbestemt eller nødvending, ja nærmest tilfældig; forelskelsen sker bare. Men for de elskende er det bestemt ikke tilfældigt, det er et ganske bestemt andet menneske, man elsker. Kærligheden kan både skabe relationer af en ganske særlig slags og en voldsom intensitet og glæde. Men også stor smerte, hvis man ikke ved, om den anden gengælder følelserne, og mere smerteligt forekommer det, da forelskelsen kan være lunefuld og kan forsvinde så hurtigt, som den opstod. Kærlighed deles ofte op i to dele: Eros og agape. Eros kender vi som den kødlige lyst og forelskelsen, modsat agape som handler om en næstekærlighed der i bibelske termer ’ikke søger sit eget’. Denne næstekærlighed er af en dobbelt natur. For den kræver ikke blot, at man er en gud hengiven, men den kræver en selvhengivenhed overfor vores næste. Den næste dækker dog over alle mennesker også ens fjender og de syndige. Denne relation er i stærk kontrast til den ’bestemte anden’ og fordrer nogle helt andre ting af en; fx tilgivelse i stedet for hengivenhed. Men kærlighed kan også være rettet mod andet end mennesker, det kan nemlig være rettet mod ens profession. En sådan lidenskab for ens værk kan vi kalde passion. Mere klassisk kan sådan en passion relateres til en kærlighed for viden eller philo(kærlighed)sophia(viden). Der hvor drivkraften i ens bestræbelser ikke grunder i et håb om lønforhøjelse eller et håb om salg af produkter, men i stedet et mere grundlæggende hengivenhed for et højere gode, om det så er kærligheden for viden, kunsten eller noget helt tredje. En sådan kærlighed kan nemt ses som en besættelse. Hvorfor bliver mennesker på denne måde besat af andre mennesker eller af projekter som kunst og videnskab? Er det blot hjernens kemi, der driver denne galskab, eller er der noget andet? Semikolon efterspørger derfor i dette nummer artikler, som kan belyse denne af livets gåder. Under fanen kærlighed søger vi artikler, som gransker menneskers passion, til hinanden, Gud, deres værk mm. Hvad forklarer vores ofte så irrationelle handlinger? Bør det overhovedet forklares? Måske er det bedste, vi kan gøre, blot at beskrive og fortolke det i håb om, at andre kan fange intuitionen. For er det overhovedet muligt at forstå, hvad kærlighed er, hvis man aldrig selv har elsket? Er det et qualia? Eller er det blot neurologiske/kemiske input fra vores hjerne, der sørger for, at vi reproducerer? Deadline er 14 maj 2015 Skrivevejledning og afleveringsformalia findes bagerst i dette nummer samt på www.semikolon.au.dk C A L L F O R PA P E R S S E M I KO LO N N R. 2 9 Love Imagine that you could be cured of love. Get rid of heartache and longing for the one that does not love you back. Most people immediately have a strong aversion for this thought. But why? It’s sort of a commonsense axiom that love is the answer to our existential problems. Maybe this aversion has root much deeper than a simple commonsense idea. Kierkegaard believed that love is a faculty given by God: The need to love and be loved. To cast your love upon another person is an act of freedom that is neither predestined nor necessary; it’s almost random – it just happens. But for the people in love, it certainly isn’t random; it’s a certain person that your love is directed against. Does that mean that love is a special kind of relation? And why is it so intense – both in positive and negative terms? If a great love turns sour, the intense feelings of joy and euphoria can turn to equally intense feelings of hate and resentment in an instance. Love is traditionally divided into two categories: eros and agape. Eros is lust, and agape is about selfless neighborly love and charity. In biblical terms, this charity has a dual nature. Not only does it dictate that you are devoted to your friends, it also demands that you are nice to, or even love, your enemy and the sinful. This relation is in stark contrast to love of “a certain other”, and demands different things, such as forgiveness instead of devotion. But love can also be directed against activities like a hobby or profession. Love directed towards creation, we call passion. In a classical sense, this passion could be directed towards knowledge: philo- (love) sophia (wisdom). This sort of passion is not fuelled by ambitions of pay raise or profit, but by a more basic devotion to a higher good, may it be wisdom, art or other self-contained goods. Passion can also be understood as an obsession or madness. Why does humans get obsessed by things and projects like art or science? What is the purpose of the brain chemistry driving this madness? Is there a semiotics of love? Or more than one? Semikolon is looking for articles that can solve these kind of riddles. Under the umbrella “love” we want to discuss people’s love for each other, God, their work etc. Is it even possible to explain the (often irrational?) behavior of people under the spell of love? Is it possible to understand, what love is, if you have never experienced it yourself? Is it a “qualia”? Or a basic instinct for reproduction and advance? Deadline is 14th of May 2015 Find Semikolons Article Submission Guidelines at www.semikolon.au.dk C A L L F O R PA P E R S S E M I KO LO N N R. 3 0 Tillid I Danmark tager vi ofte tillidsrelationer for givet. Vi mistænker generelt ikke vore omgivelser for at have bagtanker med deres handlinger. Vi antager, at de taler sandt og ikke er ude på at gøre os fortræd. Dette er dog ikke en selvfølge. I samfund, der ikke er velfungerende, opstår der en frygt blandt mennesker, hvilket er ødelæggende for tilliden. Vi tænker sjældent over, hvad der faktisk kræves for at opretholde et velfungerende samspil mennesker imellem. Ifølge K. E. Løgstrup er tillid et af de grundlæggende kriterier for dette. Han hævder, at vi ikke kan undgå i enhver social akt at udlevere os selv til ’den anden’. Denne udlevering er en tillidserklæring, hvor vi giver andre magt over os. Tillidsrelationen brydes, når denne udlevering bliver udnyttet, hvilket resulterer i, at man bliver bange for at udlevere sig igen. Mistillid nedbryder det, man på samfundsplan kalder social kapital – samhørighed mellem individer – hvilket hævdes at være årsagen til, at Danmark er verdens lykkeligste land. Men kan man sætte lighedstegn mellem tillid og social kapital, eller er der andre ting, der spiller ind? Robert Putnam mener, at jo større den samlede sociale kapital er i et samfund, jo mere sammenhængskraft er der. Men ikke alle personer/sociale grupper nyder lige stor social kapital. Er tillid nødvendigvis noget, man gør sig fortjent til, eller kan det være et udtryk for symbolsk magt? Stoler man automatisk mere på folk fra bestemte samfundslag, etniske baggrunde eller med gode netværk? I dette nummer af Semikolon efterspørger vi artikler, som belyser dette interpersonlige forhold. Hvordan opstår tillid mellem mennesker? Kan man måle og dermed forøge det? Gør vi noget aktivt, når vi stoler på nogen? Eller er det kognitivt set en ”default mode”? Hvordan ser tillidens semiotik ud, og hvordan bruger brands denne forskning til deres fordel? Tilliden eksisterer i en form for spænding, hvor den kun kan forekomme, når den ikke er garanteret. Men en sådan uvished kan nemt medføre en frygt for, hvorvidt den overholdes. Hvordan skal man forholde sig til en sådan nødvendighed af usikkerhed? Fordrer det ikke magtesløshed? Er det bedre at have tillid end at have kontrol? Deadline er 9. oktober 2015 Skrivevejledning og afleveringsformalia findes bagerst i dette nummer samt på www.semikolon.au.dk C A L L F O R PA P E R S S E M I KO LO N N R. 3 0 Trust In Denmark we often take trustful relations for granted. In general, we don’t expect other people to have ulterior motives. We assume that they speak the truth, and that they won’t purposely hurt us. However, this is not a given. In societies that don’t function well, fear and distrust can arise between citizens. We rarely think about, what is actually needed to keep a well-functioning interplay in a society. According to K.E. Løgstrup, trust is a basic criterion in this matter. He claims that we can’t avoid to surrender ourselves to ‘the other’ in any social action. This surrendering is a declaration of trust, where we grant the other person power over us. The relation of trust is broken, if it is taken advantage of, which leads to difficulty in surrendering yourself in the future. Distrust breaks down, what we in sociological terms call ‘social capital’ – cohesion between individuals – which is claimed to be, what makes Danes the happiest people in the world. But does trust equal social capital, or are there other things at play? Robert Putnam believes that the larger the total amount of social capital there is in a society, the more solidarity there is. But not all people/social groups enjoy the same amount of social capital. Is trust necessarily something you earn, or can it rather be a question of symbolic power? Do we automatically trust people from certain layers of society, ethnical backgrounds, with better networks more than others? In this issue of Semikolon, we are looking for articles that shed some light on this interpersonal relation; a relation we often take for granted. How does trust arise between people? Can we measure it and thereby increase it? Is trusting an active act? Or is it cognitively the “default mode”? What is the semiotic of trust, and how does brands exploit this research? The concept of trust exists in a field of tension, where it can only exist, if it is not guaranteed. But this uncertainty can easily create a fear that it will not be fulfilled. How should one relate to this built-in uncertainty? Does it entail helplessness? Is it better to trust than to control? Deadline is 9th of October 2015 Find Semikolons Article Submission Guidelines at www.semikolon.au.dk ANNONCÉR Synes du også de andre læsere skal kende den forening eller virksomhed du er en del af? – Kontakt os og find ud af hvor let det er at reklamere: [email protected] Selv en lille annonce bliver læst i Semikolon! Christoffer Basse Eriksen Er kroppen blot en maskine? – Minutiøs materialitet hos René Descartes René Descartes beskriver flere steder i sin filosofi kroppen som en maskine, men hvor bogstaveligt skal dette udsagn tages? Er den levende krop at sidestille med et artefakt? Gennem en læsning af Descartes’ værker og breve argumenterer jeg for, at Descartes reserverede en plads til den levende krop i sit mekaniske system og at han kvalificerede denne plads ved at pege på, hvad jeg her kalder en minutiøs materialitet. Jeg viser, at Descartes sammenkoblede det levende og det minutiøse og at han på den måde skaber en epistemologisk åbning for 1600-tallets mikrobiologiske program. Descartes udraderede ikke den levende krop, men bekymrede sig om den. kunne skelnes fra hinanden. Dette skulle have hylet en skibskaptajn så meget ud, da han en nat på en overfart over det Hollandske hav opdagede dukken i Descartes‘ kiste (han var åbenbart en nysgerrig kaptajn), at han smed den overbord. Descartes har selvfølgelig aldrig haft en mekanisk pigedukke, der hed Francine. Historien blev fortalt for første gang i det tidlige 18. århundrede, halvtreds år efter Descartes‘ død og i et intellektuelt Frankrig, som provokeret specielt af udgivelsen af La Mettries L‘Homme Machine i 1747 var travlt beskæftiget med at bringe mekanisk-materialistisk fysiologi og antropologi i miskredit. De incestuøstseksuelle undertoner i historien må siges at være et smart træk fra propagandisterne. S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 1 1 - 2 0 Som indledning til sin intellektuelle biografi om den franske filosof René Descartes (1596-1650), en biografi der blot bærer titlen Descartes, fortæller idéhistorikeren Stephen Gaukroger en røverhistorie. Den går sådan her: Siden 1700-tallet har der floreret en historie om Descartes, der gik på at han altid, når han var ude at rejse medbragte en dragkiste, hvori han havde en life-size mekanisk pigedukke af egen konstruktion. Angiveligt skulle han have konstrueret dukken for at bevise, at ’dyr kun er maskiner og at de ingen sjæl har’. Dukken hed Francine, opkaldt efter Descartes‘ uægte datter og i nogle versioner af historien hedder det endda, at dukken var skabt i datterens billede, at de to ikke Christoffer Basse Eriksen Side 12 Den bærende stemning i historien er en frygt for det mekaniske. Francine er uncanny, unheimlich, uhyggelig. Hvorfor kastede kaptajnen Francine-dukken overbord, hvorfor blev han forfærdet? Fordi den var obskøn, pervers, klam. Jeg forestiller mig, at tankerækken i hans hoved, da han efter at have sneget sig ind i den sovende filosofs kahyt, åbnet dragkisten lige så stille fandt den lille Francine liggende der, også sovende (eller måske uhyggeligt smilende med åbne øjne?), må have været nogenlunde denne: Tror denne filosof, at han er Gud? Eller tror han, at Gud blot er en snild håndværker? Tror han, at denne dukke er levende? Eller tror han, at vi alle sammen blot er mekaniske dukker? Det var nok det sidste spørgsmål, der fik kaptajnen til at kaste dukken fra sig med en klam smag i munden. Det var da han begyndte at spejle sig i dukken, at det blev for meget for ham, det var da han så sig selv: mennesket, en maskine. Men mens historien om Francine nok er propaganda, som bruger overdrivelsen som litterært våben, er der stadig noget over denne tale om kroppen som en maskine. Hør blot følgende citater fra Descartes‘ værker: I sit modne værk Principles of Philosophy (1644) sidestiller han den naturlige krop med artefaktet: “For I do not recognize any difference between artefacts and natural bodies” (CSM I: 288), i den tidlige, posthumt udgivne Treatise on Man beskriver han mennesket som “the statue or machine made of earth” (CSM I: 99), mens han i et brev til sin ven Marin Mersenne fra 30. august 1640 skriver: Speaking as a metaphysician, one might well build a machine that supports itself in the air like a bird, because birds, at least according to me, are such machines. (AT III: 163-164) På trods af disse meget klare formuleringer vil jeg i det følgende lade forholdet stå som et åbent spørgsmål: Er kroppen blot en maskine? Først vil jeg vise, hvordan ny Descartes-forskning har beskrevet, hvordan Descartes faktisk giver en privilegeret plads til den menneskelige krop, når han taler om medicin og menneskets helbred. Et fokus, der stiller store spørgsmål ved den mekaniske filosofis grad af universalitet, idet Descartes i disse diskussioner nærmer sig teleologiske formuleringer. Derefter undersøger jeg ikke den menneskelige krop, men den levende krop generelt og ikke for at lede efter fejl i Descartes‘ mekaniske system, men for at se, om der, de bastante formuleringer om kropmaskine-ligheden til trods, skulle være en anden slags materialitet, en minutiøs materialitet, på spil i Descartes‘ forståelse af den levende krop. Slutteligt argumenterer jeg for, at Descartes med sin sammenkædning af liv og det minutiøse leverer en epistemologisk åbning for det mikrobiologiske program, der udvikledes i løbet af det 17. århundrede. To ambitioner ligger latente under denne undersøgelse af forholdet mellem den levende krop og maskinen i Descartes‘ tænkning. For det første vil jeg gerne præsentere en anden Descartes end den, vi normalt bliver præsenteret for, nemlig rationalisten, erkendelsesteoretikeren og tvivleren Descartes, der primært var optaget af at garantere verdens og sin egen eksistens. Vi skal selvfølgelig ikke blot kaste Meditationerne over bord, men vi er nødt til at tage den indledende kommentar om, at den metodiske tvivl er en engangsforestilling seriøst. Det store fokus på Descartes‘ epistemologi har mere at gøre med en filosofihistorisk tradition, som har været beskæftiget med at klargøre, hvad rationalisme overhovedet er og så forresten modstille denne med empirismen for at en fin dynamisk historie kunne opstå, Er kroppen blot en maskine? end den har været interesseret i Descartes‘ eget projekt. Et projekt, som der er masser af tekstuelt bevis for i hovedsagen var naturfilosofisk, dvs. et projekt som beskæftigede sig med hvad vi i dag i Descartes‘ tilfælde vil kalde astronomi, optik, matematik, fysik, fysiologi og psykologi. For det andet vil jeg gerne give et historisk eksempel på, at der ikke er nogen nødvendig modsætning mellem et mekanisk verdensbillede og et blik for det levende. Disse to fænomener, nemlig et mekanisk system og hævdelsen af det levendes særegenhed bliver ofte omtalt som gensidigt udelukkende. Det er selvfølgelig rigtig nok, hvis man med det levendes særegenhed mener en hård vitalisme, der hævder at mekaniske forklaringsmodeller må give fuldstændig op, når det vil beskrive det levende (en organisme, den levende natur), men dette er, historisk set, sjældent tilfældet. Et eksempel kunne være Kants heuristiske model for sameksistensen af mekanisme og organicisme fra anden del af Kritik af dømmekraften, et andet kunne være Leibniz‘ beskrivelse af de “guddommelige maskiner” fra Monadologien og andre steder i hans forfatterskab og breve. Pointen er den, at mekanisme ofte bliver beskrevet som død, fattig eller i andre nedgørende termer. Ved at vise, at også Descartes, den mekaniske filosofis fader, havde et blik for det levende mener jeg at kunne vise, at disse beskrivelser er overfladiske og affektive domme lignende historien om Francine, der har alt andet som deres projekt end at forsøge at forstå, hvad mekanisk filosofi var og er. First of all, I would have wished to explain what philosophy is, beginning with the most commonplace points. For example, the word ‚philosophy‘ means the study of wisdom, and by ‚wisdom‘ is meant not only prudence in our everyday affairs but also a perfect knowledge of all things that mankind is capable of knowing, both for the conduct of life and for the preservation of health and the discovery of all manner of skills. (CSM I: 179, min kursivering) Ligeledes er medicinen en del af det meget berømte videnstræ, som Descartes beskriver i samme forord: Thus the whole of philosophy is like a tree. The roots are metaphysics, the trunk is physics, and the branches emerging from the trunk are all the other sciences, which may be reduced to three principal ones, namely medicine, mechanics and morals (CSM I: 186) Læst i samklang med Descartes‘ breve ville en fortolkning kunne lyde, at metafysikken eksisterer for fysikkens skyld og at fysikken eksisterer for mekanikkens, medicinens og moralens skyld. Side 13 Helbred som formål: Den menneskelige krops privilegerede status I et brev til markisen af Newcastle fra oktober 1645 skriver Descartes ”the preservation of health has always been the principal end of my studies” (CSMK: 275). Den samme ambition afslører Descartes i sin korrespondance med prinsesse Elisabeth fra samme periode for hvem Descartes fungerer som assisterende livlæge pr. brev. Nu skal man selvfølgelig altid passe på med at tage filosoffers udtalelser om deres egne ambitioner for gode varer (især når de korresponderer med magtfulde og meget rige prinsesser og mæcener!), men Descartes‘ diskussioner af medicinens betydning synes ikke at være en overfladisk interesse. I forordet til hovedværket Principles of Philosophy skriver han fx: Christoffer Basse Eriksen Side 14 De seneste 15 år har en række forskere betonet Descartes‘ fokus på fysiologien og medicinen. Dennis Des Chene viser i sine arbejder om Descartes, specielt Spirits and Clocks (2001), hvordan Descartes, når han forklarer organernes funktioner falder tilbage til et aristotelisk sprogbrug, som når han taler om “the office of the liver” og når han bruger begreberne actio, functio og usus. Disse begreber er aristoteliske og de holder simpelthen op med at give mening, hvis de ikke forstås teleologisk. Når Descartes taler om leverens embede (officium) må det forstås sådan, at leveren udfører sit arbejde med et formål, nemlig det formål at opretholde en harmoni eller stabilitet i kroppen – at opretholde kroppens helbred. Dette skurrer dog i forhold til Descartes‘ andre bemærkninger om, hvordan kroppen fungerer. I sine beskrivelser af den menneskelige krop (mest udtalt i Treatise on Man) er Descartes meget opmærksom på at beskrive alle kropslige funktioner kun ud fra, hvad de gør og ikke ud fra hvad formålet er med deres handling. Dette skal forstås i forlængelse af Descartes‘ angreb på den aristoteliske idé om den tredelte sjæl og den hippokratisk-galeniske idé om de fire kropsvæsker (som igen svarer til de fire elementer). For Descartes findes kun én slags stof ligesom der kun findes én sjæl, en sjæl der dog intet har at gøre med kroppens opretholdelse af sig selv. Her fra Discourse on Method: I supposed, too, that in the beginning God did not place in this body any rational soul or any other thing to serve as a vegetative or sensitive soul, but rather that he kindled in its heart one of those fires without light which I have already explained, and whose nature I understood to be no different from that of the fire which heats hay when it has been stored before it is dry, or which causes new wine to seethe when it is left to ferment from the crushed grape. (CSM I: 134) Bemærk, at Descartes ikke går fra afvisningen af de aristoteliske sjæle til res cogitans, men i stedet til at pege på et rent fysisk fænomen, nemlig “the fire without light”, der igen er et problematisk begreb, fordi Descartes aldrig ekspliciterer, hvad det præcis dækker over. Her forstås, at kroppen ikke er noget specielt, som skal beskrives med specielle love, men at de mekaniske principper virker lige så godt her som i beskrivelsen af resten af den naturlige verden. Og fordi kroppen ikke er noget specielt er det ikke muligt ud fra en rent mekanisk betragtning at vurdere kroppens helbred, for kroppen adlyder naturlovene i lige så høj grad, når den er syg, som når den er rask. I den sjette Meditation formulerer Descartes dette præcist i en diskussion af urets ’helbred‘: A clock constructed with wheels and weights observes all the laws of its nature just as closely when it is badly made and tells the wrong time as when it completely fulfills the wishes of the clockmaker. In the same way, I might consider the body of a man as a kind of machine equipped with and made up of bones, nerves, muscles, veins, blood and skin in such a way that, even if there were no mind in it, it would still perform all the same movements as it now does in those cases where the movement is not under the control of the will or, consequently, of the mind. (CSM II: 58) Vurderet rent mekanisk er uret altså lige så velfungerende, når det ikke viser tiden korrekt, som når det gør. Det er først, når vi Er kroppen blot en maskine? vurderer uret i forhold til et formål og anviser, at dets formål er at vise tiden korrekt, at det kan fejle. Ligesådan med kroppen; det er kun, når vi sætter et eksternt formål op for kroppen, nemlig at den skal være rask, at den kan opfylde dette formål. Men på trods af dette taler Descartes altså om den menneskelige krops (men ikke dyrets) helbred. I sin artikel ”The Health of the BodyMachine?” fra 2003 sætter Lisa Shapiro dette op som et generelt problem: Helbred er et inhærent normativt begreb og kan ikke forstås uden henvisning til formål og formulerer problemstillingen som følgende: The problem stems from the conflict of two principles: first, the natural world is to be conceived non-teleologically; and second, the norms that constitute our concept of health are essentially teleological. (Shapiro 2003: 424) Selvbevægende og levende maskiner Vi bevæger nu undersøgelsen væk fra den menneskelige krop og hen mod den levende krop i det hele taget idet vi spørger: Er der noget specielt ved den levende krop? Et godt bud ligger i det adjektiv, der her har sneget sig ind: nemlig levende. Hvis målet er at finde den forskel i Descartes‘ system, der adskiller den levende krop fra maskinen, kunne en løsning være at den levende krop er speciel netop fordi den er levende. Men denne løsning er ikke så ligetil som den måske synes, for liv er også et meget problematisk begreb i Descartes‘ filosofi. Descartes bruger begrebet flittigt, idet han taler om et “principle of life”, et princip som vi uden alt for mange problemer kan henføre til tilstedeværelsen af hjertevarme (cardiac heat) samt en gruppe af livsfunktioner som fx fordøjelse, ernæring, lokomotion (bevægelse) samt forplantning. Descartes‘ livs-begreb er dog ikke et stærkt ontologisk begreb, men snarere et begreb, som han bruger ad hoc, intuitivt og lettere pragmatisk. I et brev til Henricus Regius fra juni 1642 kommenterer Descartes meget direkte på forholdet mellem liv og mekanik. Her skriver han: On page 66 you seem to make a greater difference between living and lifeless things than there is between a clock or other automaton on the one hand, and a key or sword or other non-self-moving appliance on the Side 15 Der synes ikke at være en umiddelbar løsning i Descartes‘ system, der på den ene side kan tillade ham at tale om menneskets helbred som et mål, men samtidig ikke giver køb på det universelle, ikke-teleologiske mekaniske system. Shapiro peger på én mulighed, nemlig at menneskets specielle status som dualistisk væsen, hvor krop og sjæl er forenede, ville kunne forklare, at mennesket indtager denne specielle plads, hvor formål findes. Men det er ikke en overbevisende løsning, for det ville implicere en stor del aristotelianisme, da forbindelsen mellem krop og sjæl kommer til at virke som en form for hylomorfisme, hvor sjælen til en vis grad informerer kroppen, noget, som Descartes, som vi har set, tager så stor afstand fra. Modsat Kant, der løser antinomien mellem det mekaniske og det ekstra-mekaniske heuristisk, så diskuterer Descartes ikke problemet. Den menneskelige krop får lov at stå som noget mere end en maskine, men på en måde, der stiller flere spørgsmål til Descartes‘ naturfilosofiske system end det giver svar. Derfor er henvisningen til den menneskelige krops særegenhed et utilfredsstillende, omend interessant, svar på vores ledende spørgsmål, nemlig om kroppen blot er en maskine. Christoffer Basse Eriksen Side 16 other. I do not agree. Since ‘self-moving’ is a category with respect to all machines that move of their own accord, which excludes others that are not self-moving, so ‘life’ may be taken as a category which includes the forms of all living things (CSMK: 214) Citatet her er sjovt, fordi Descartes‘ selvsikkerhed overstiger hans præcision med mange længder. Én ting står dog fast: Spørgsmålet om liv er ikke af lige så fundamental ontologisk betydning som spørgsmålet om de selv-bevægende apparater (automater). Descartes skriver, at distinktionen mellem apparater, der har et internt bevægelsesprincip og de, der har et eksternt bevægelsesprincip inkluderer alle maskiner (inklusiv de levende maskiner), mens liv er en kategori, der inkluderer alle levende ting. Gruppen ’levende maskiner‘ er altså nødvendigvis inkluderet i gruppen ’automater‘, mens det omvendte ikke nødvendigvis er tilfældet (omend det kan være). At være levende er underordnet at være selvbevægende – det er altså spørgsmålet om det mekaniske forhold, der er det centrale for Descartes. Dette er det primære indhold i brevet til Regius og det er her, Descartes‘ primære interesse ligger. Men der er også et sekundært indhold. Uden at specificere det yderligere får Descartes nemlig nævnt, at der findes en anden gruppe, nemlig gruppen af ‚levende ting‘, omend han ikke definerer præcist hvilke ting, der er inkluderede i denne gruppe. Lad os nu se, om vi ikke kan specificere denne gruppe af levende ting yderligere ved at læse nogle flere af Descartes‘ sekundære betragtninger frem. Disse betragtninger må nødvendigvis være sekundære, for, som vi lige har set, er det primære projekt altid for Descartes den mekaniske beskrivelse af naturens fænomener. Og for at være præcis: Jeg hævder ikke, at Descartes forpligter sig strengt på kategorien ’levende kroppe‘ - jeg hævder ikke, at Descartes er en form for skabs-vitalist. Mit mål er i stedet at betone, at den levende krop eksisterer i Descartes‘ mekaniske system. Den er ikke fast defineret og det er ikke en central kategori, men den levende krop er ikke a priori ekskluderet fra det mekaniske verdensbillede. Livsånder, artefakter og naturlige kroppe Jeg vil nu udvikle denne idé om at Descartes levner en plads til den levende krop, en plads der bliver beskrevet af en materialitet, som jeg vil kalde minutiøs materialitet. Med begrebet minutiøs materialitet peger jeg på det forhold, at der synes at være en korrelation mellem tilstedeværelsen af minutiøse dele (minute parts) og liv i Descartes‘ beskrivelse af de levende, naturlige kroppe. Svagheden af dette argument forstærkes af det faktum, at Descartes ikke opererer med forskellige slags stof eller materie. I stedet er al stof det samme for Descartes, idet det har den minimale definition at være udstrakt i “length, breadth and depth” (CSM I: 210). Stof differentieres altså kun i kraft af sin specifikke udstrækning, dvs. størrelse og figur, omend Descartes inddeler stof i tre grupper, nemlig stof af det første, andet og tredje element i grader af størrelse og agitation, hvoraf det første er mindst, mens det tredje er størst. Forskellige fænomener udgøres da af de tre forskellige typer af stof: The sun and fixed stars are composed of the first element, the heavens from the second, and the earth with the planets and comets from the third. (CSM I: 258) Er kroppen blot en maskine? Det er netop stof af det første element, det mest minutiøse, hurtige og varmeste (idet varme er defineret som agitation), der korrelerer med de naturlige kroppe. Et eksempel på denne korrelation findes i de specielle korpuskler, som Descartes i forlængelse af en lang skolastisk tradition kalder livsånder (esprits animaux, animal spirits). Navnet er her misledende, for der er intet spirituelt i betydningen immaterielt ved disse livsånder, hvad Descartes også bemærker i et brev til Adolph Vorster fra juni 1643, hvor han skriver, at han er very surprised that anyone denies the existence of spirits in animals, unless he is questioning the name, and objects to the term ‘spirits’ being applied to particles of terrestrial matter that are separated from each other and driven about at great speed. (CSMK: 226) I Principles fremføres den samme pointe: For what I am calling ‚spirits‘ here are merely bodies: they have no property other than that of being extremely small bodies which move very quickly, like the jets of a flame that come from a torch. (CSM I: 331-332) In order to explain these functions, then, it is not necessary to conceive of this machine as having any vegetative or sensitive soul or other principle of movement and life, apart from its blood and its spirits, which are agitated by the heat of the fire burning continuously in its heart – a fire which has the same nature as all the fires that occur in inanimate bodies. (CSM I: 108) Typisk for den måde, Descartes behandler emnet på indleder han her med at afvise eksistensen af de aristoteliske sjæle, hvorefter han peger på den levende krops specificitet som værende “its blood and its spirits”, der er varme og agiterede, men alligevel ikke substantielt anderledes end andre former for ild. Descartes‘ frem-og-tilbage-argumentation er et perfekt eksempel på, hvad jeg mener med, at han har et svagt ontologisk begreb om den levende krops specificitet: Han udpeger den som værende speciel, men afviser, at der gælder specielle love for den. Samme argumentationsform og samme udpegning af den minutiøse materialitet finder vi i konklusionen til Principles of Philosophy, hvor Descartes diskuterer, hvordan vi kan dømme klart og distinkt, dvs. med sikkerhed, om ting, der er så små, at de ikke kan ses. Efter at have konkluderet, at der ingen forskel er mellem artefakter og naturlige kroppe, giver han en interessant undtagelse: For I do not recognize any difference between artefacts and natural bodies except that the operations of artefacts are for the Side 17 Begge steder betones livsåndernes specifikationer som ild-lignende, dvs. at de består af meget minutiøst materiale, nemlig stof af det første element. Livsåndernes funktion i Descartes‘ fysiologi er meget kompleks, idet de både er ansvarlige for kroppens rent fysiologiske opretholdelse, ligesom de har stor betydning for den udveksling, der finder sted mellem kroppen og sjælen overalt i kroppen, men mest i koglekirtlen. Descartes beskriver specielt dette i det sene værk The Passions of the Soul, men her skal blot bemærkes tilstedeværelsen af disse livsånder samt det faktum, at de er korrelerer med den levende krop. Dette kommer eksemplarisk til udtryk i de sidste linjer af Treatise of Man: Christoffer Basse Eriksen Side 18 most part performed by mechanisms which are large enough to be easily perceivable by the senses – as indeed must be the case if they are to be capable of being manufactured by human beings. The effects produced in nature, by contrast, almost always depend on structures which are so minute that they completely elude our senses. (CSM I: 288) To forskelle mellem artefaktet og den naturlige krop bliver her klare. For det første er artefaktet skabt af mennesket, mens den naturlige krop er skabt af “the supreme craftsman” (CSM I: 289), nemlig Gud. Og i forlængelse af denne forskel betoner Descartes, at artefaktet altid har virkende dele, der er store nok til at blive erkendt af mennesket, mens de naturlige kroppe, derimod, har dele, der er så små, at de ikke kan erkendes af det menneskelige sanseapparat. Som vi så tidligere er også den levende, eller naturlige, krop mekanisk og i sidste ende en maskine, idet den virker ved at forskellige dele yder indflydelse på hinanden og kan beskrives rent mekanisk. Men samtidig er den naturlige krop en maskine, der har en mikrostruktur, dvs. at de dele, der indvirker på hinanden er så minutiøse, at de ikke kan erkendes af mennesket og derfor heller ikke skabes af mennesket. Vi skal huske, at også artefaktet selvfølgelig har minutiøse dele, dvs. at også artefaktet består af korpuskler (som alt gør), men at det er på et funktionelt plan, at forskellen opstår. Artefaktets funktionerende dele er nødvendigvis store nok til at blive ‚grebet‘ af mennesket, mens den naturlige krop har minutiøse funktionerende dele, som fx livsånderne. Denne svage distinktion er også tydelig i det brev til Mersenne fra 30. august 1640, som jeg citerede i indledningen. Her skriver Descartes: Speaking as a metaphysician, one might well build a machine that supports itself in the air like a bird, because birds, at least according to me, are such machines; but not speaking as a physicist or a moral philosopher, because that would require springs that are so intricate [subtils], and jointly so strong, that humans wouldn’t know how to make them. (AT III: 163-164) Metafysisk anskuet er dyr altså maskiner, men fysisk anskuet kan vi ikke behandle dem under ét, idet dyret er langt mere sofistikeret, eller minutiøst, end maskinen. Guddommelige maskiner og det mikrobiologiske program Afslutningsvis vil jeg gerne fremhæve endnu et brev, som Descartes sender til Henri Regnier (1593-1639), men hvis rette modtager er Alphonse Pollot (16021638). I brevet fra april eller maj 1638 har Descartes en fabelagtig passage over et par sider, hvori han gennem en fiktiv historie argumenterer for at dyr ingen sjæle har. Men ligesom det er tilfældet i de andre teksteksempler, jeg har bragt, så sker der langt mere i passagen end hvad Descartes primært har for øje. I brevet fortæller Descartes en fiktiv historie om en mand, der aldrig har set et dyr, men som er optaget af maskiner og bygger automater, der forestiller både dyr og mennesker. Descartes beder nu Pollot forestille sig, hvad der ville ske, når denne mand så de dyr, vi har, og om han ville gå ud fra, at de havde sjæle. Det interessante fra vores synspunkt er, at Descartes gør meget ud af at differentiere mellem automaterne, som manden laver og naturlige dyr, som Gud har skabt. De naturlige dyr er automater, som er “incomparably more accomplished than any of those he had Er kroppen blot en maskine? previously made himself” (CSMK: 100), og denne perfektion beskriver Descartes i en diskussion af planter således: Nature has packed plants with an infinity of tiny invisible ducts through which certain juices gradually ascend to the ends of the branches, where they intermingle and combine and dry out in such a way as to form leaves and flowers and fruits. (CSMK: 99, min kursivering) Notes 1 Jeg parafraserer her fra Gaukroger (1995: 1-3.) 2 For diskussioner af de her berørte temaer i Kants ‚biologi‘, se Robert Richards: The Romantic Conception of Life (2002) og Timothy Lenoir: The Strategy of Life (1989). For en diskussion af Leibniz‘ mikrobiologiske filosofi, se Justin E. H. Smith: Divine Machines (2011). 3 I Descartes-forskningen er der lige nu stor diskussion om livs-begrebet i Descartes‘ fysiologi. Se specielt Ablondi (1998), Des Chene (2001), Shapiro (2003), Distelzweig (forthcoming). En stærk sammenfattende diskussion af emnet findes i Hutchins (forthcoming), der argumenterer for at Descartes ikke har et fast begreb om liv, men at han i stedet bruger begrebet pragmatisk. 4 I sjette Meditation skriver Descartes: “I am not merely present in my body as a sailor is present in a ship” (CSM II: 56) og argumenterer derved for, at sjælen føler hvad kroppen føler og ikke kun i koglekirtlen, men over hele kroppen. Side 19 Her ser vi igen, hvordan Descartes peger på tilstedeværelsen af en mikrostruktur, når han skal kvalificere, hvad der adskiller artefaktet fra den naturlige krop, her planten. I en avanceret dobbeltfiktion beder Descartes Pollot forestille sig, at manden ved, at hvis der fandtes “automatons made by God or nature” (ibid.) ville de være mere perfekte end menneskeskabte automater. Selv i denne dobbeltfiktion opretholder Descartes sin skelnen mellem dyr og automater, sådan at den underlige skabning en guddommelig automat kan opstå. Den guddommelige automat fungerer som forklaring af, hvad dyret er, men den gør det analogisk, dvs. at Descartes ikke siger at dyret er en guddommelig automat, men i stedet at hvis vi vil forestille os, hvad et dyr er i strikt mekaniske termer, så gør vi det bedst ved at forestille os en automat lavet af Gud eller naturen. Gennem denne sammenkædning af begreberne liv, det minutiøse samt idéen om guddommelige maskiner gennemfører Descartes en epistemologisk åbning for det mikrobiologiske program, som intensiveres i løbet af det 17. århundrede i takt med at mikroskopet perfektioneres. Den bærende idé i det mikrobiologiske program, som det gennemføres af mikroskopisterne Marcello Malpighi, Antoni van Leeuwenhoek, Jan Swammerdam og Nicolaas Hartsoeker er, at det kendetegnende for livet skal findes i den mikroskopiske struktur. Derfor findes så mange teoretiske objekter, der har en diminutiv form som fx Pierre Gassendis idé om flammulen, den flammelignende, materielle sjæl, teorien om vermiculen, den grundlæggende biologiske entitet, der har ormens form, Leeuwenhoeks opdagelse af animalculet i mikroskopet, sædcellen, som Leibniz udvikler en hel mikrobiologisk filosofi om, samt selvfølgelig molekylet, som senere i Georges Buffons hænder bliver til det organiske molekyle, et vitalistisk-materialistisk grundelement. Hvis vi vil have en ordentlig idéhistorisk forståelse af dette videnskabelige program, der var så essentielt i udviklingen af biologien som videnskab, er vi nødt til at forstå den mekaniske filosofi, som blev udviklet af René Descartes og huske på, at Descartes ikke udraderede den levende krop, men at han bekymrede sig om den. Christoffer Basse Eriksen 5 Peter Gallison diskuterer analogien og sammenligningens funktion i Descartes‘ perceptionsteori i sin artikel “Descartes‘s Comparisons: From the Invisible to the Visible”. Gallison fastslår også, at det er vigtigt at huske at sammenligningerne (fx menneskemaskinen i Treatise on Man) er værktøjer for erkendelsen og ikke virkelige entiteter. Kort sagt: Gallison minder os om, at Descartes anvender litterære strategier i sine tekster, en simpel, men meget vigtig pointe. Litteratur Side 20 Ablondi, Fred (1998): “Automata, living and nonliving: Descartes‘ mechanical biology and his criteria for life”, Biology and Philosophy 13, pp. 179-186 Des Chene, Dennis (2001): Spirits & Clocks: Machine & Organism in Descartes, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY (CSM) Descartes, René (1984, 1985): The philosophical writings of Descartes, red. og oversat af John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch, 2 bind, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (CSMK) Descartes, René (1991): The philosophical writings of Descartes: The correspondence, red. og oversat af John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch and Antony Kenny, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (AT) Descartes, René (1996): Oeuvres de Descartes, red. af C. Adam, P. Tannery, 11 bind, J Vrin, Paris Distelzweig, Peter (forthcoming): ‘The Uses of Usus and the Function of Functio: Teleology and its Limits in Descartes’ Physiology’, Journal of the History of Philosophy Gallison, Peter (1984): “Descartes‘s Comparisons: From the Invisible to the Visible” i Isis, pp. 311-326 Gaukroger, Stephen (1995): Descartes - An Intellectual Biography, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Hutchins, Barnaby (forthcoming): “Descartes and the dissolution of life” Lenoir, Timothy (1989): The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanism in Nineteenth-Century Biology, University of Chicago Press, Chicago Richards, Robert (2002): The Romantic Conception of Life, University of Chicago Press, Chicago Shapiro, Lisa (2003): “The Health of the BodyMachine? or Seventeenth Century Mechanism and the Concept of Health” i Perspectives on Science, pp. 421-442 Smith, Justin E. H. (2011): Divine Machines - Leibniz and the Sciences of Life, Princeton University Press, Princeton Juan Olvido Sociogenesis and stability of artifacts in cultural practices of illegal cannabis use Introduction This article will use the cognitive semiotics approach to characterize the emergence and stability of artifacts as a particular kind of cultural form (following Saxe & Esmonde, 2005). To do this, I will look into a set of cultural practices that has been profiled in the criminological literature as “illegal cannabis use” (“ICU” from now on). I will draw from Tylén et al.’s (2013) dynamical account of linguistic meaning making that identifies four main sources of stability in linguistic forms. I will argue that the same model can be used to account for the emergence and stability of artifacts. The reasons behind the choice of artifacts in ICU are the following: a) the legal status of cannabis makes the social dynamics operating behind ICU strongly resemble those dynamics on which Tylén et al. build their assumptions (i.e., local interaction scale, cf. Tylén et al., 2013); b) the core aspects of the sub-cultural practices revolving ICU are well-documented (Zimmerman & Wieder, 1977); c) I believe that a full-fledged analysis of this kind can contribute significantly to the ongoing criminological discussion between normalization theory and subculture theory. As I will discuss below, the sketch I present in this article already points at the importance of ecological factors in the stability of cultural forms revolving ICU. S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 2 1 - 2 8 In this article I will suggest that recent developments in subculture theory facilitate a cognitive semiotic analysis of the study of cultural practices of illegal cannabis use. I will sketch one such analysis, focusing on the role that artifacts have in structuring interactions according to a cultural script. Specifically, I will adapt Tylén et al.’s (2013) account of the emergence and stability of linguistic forms to understand the emergence and stability of recurrent types of artifacts such as “joints” or “pipes” in the specific context of illegal cannabis use. I will conclude that the stability of cultural forms in illegal cannabis use (reported by supporters of subculture theory to ground their claims) can be partially explained by looking at key socioeconomic factors that have remained largely the same since the introduction of cannabis in Western societies, contributing to the stability of cultural forms (and, in turn, the values that these represent). Side 22 Juan Olvido I already mentioned that I will consider artifacts as a kind of cultural form, as defined by Saxe & Esmonde (2005). Thus, by cultural forms I refer to any intentful physical manipulations of personal or environmental matter, the outcome of which will approximate the intention of one or more agents. These forms are cultural because their occurrence can be more or less circumscribed to cultural populations (in fact defining them, as I will expand on below). In this very broad conception of “cultural forms” we can find then the results of verbal behavior (words), nonverbal bodily behavior (gestures, facial expressions, full blown rituals, etc.), or intentful manipulations of matter (artifacts). In this view, the main difference between artifacts and other cultural forms is the amount of time that these are publicly accessible. Words, gestures, rituals, etc., tend to “fade” more rapidly (cf., “rapid fading” in Hacket, 1960) than those entities we tend to categorize as “artifacts”. The precise metaphysics or ontological status of these “cultural forms” are not the focus of the present paper, so I encourage the reader to overlook particularities and try to do with the present description. Furthermore, my definition could be characterized as cybernetic because I will place an important emphasis not on the physical affordances of artifacts involved in ICU but, rather, in how they provide a common perceptual ground that help interactants constrain their interaction. Additionally, I will focus on how constraints (Bateson’s “restraints” in Bateson, 1967) allow for the emergence of distinctive forms, instead of pointing at causal forces that directly force them into being. As such, artifacts involved in ICU (typically joints, or pipes) become nodes around which ritualized behavior revolves. Therefore, crucial to my approach, will be the assumption that there is nothing in the shape, color, weight, or any combination of perceived properties of a joint or pipe that conveys the norms around its usage, according to the rites consistently observed in ICU in naturalistic settings, or as inferable by indirect means (i.e. interviews). So, whereas one could possibly infer after long consideration that one extreme of the pipe is intended to burn marihuana, and another to suck the air into the lungs, the chances that one would conclude that the pipe has to be passed around (as is customary in ICU, cf. Zimmerman & Wieder, 1977) are insignificant if one were to base this conclusion on the formal properties of the artifact alone. As it happens, the norms around the consumption of cannabis in ICU are passed on mainly through local interaction (because legal constraints and subsequent stigma have hindered its public access), even though an increasing public discussion must also be acknowledged and considered in any comprehensive analysis of ICU as it is today. Sandberg’s take on subculture theory facilitates a cognitive semiotic analysis Illegal cannabis use in the criminological literature has been subject to a certain conceptual controversy regarding its current significance in contemporary Western culture. On the one hand, subculture theory understands illegal use of cannabis as a cultural act of resistance performed by people who see themselves as oppressed, or who do not share values with their perceived majority. On the other hand, the thesis of normalization maintains that the approach of subculture theory is inadequate because it fails to capture the greater heterogeneity in the population that, today, use cannabis Sociogenesis and stability of artifacts... illegally, as well as failing to account for its greater social acceptance. Traditionally, subculture theory has maintained that marginalized groups in a broader social context have formulated an alternative set of values from that held by the dominant culture they are embedded in. In this view, the illegal consumption of cannabis is in itself constitutive of a wider set of values that set apart smokers (subculture) in an act of cultural resistance against the non-smoking majority. More recently, and mainly on the basis of statistical data showing an increase in the consumption of illegal drugs during the 1990s (and of cannabis in particular), some authors put forward the thesis of normalization. Supporters of the thesis of normalization claim that the subculture revolving ICU is rapidly losing its relevance, and ground this claim on the observation of five points that, on their view, point towards the normalization of illegal drug use: increased availability and access; increased drug trying rates; increased drug-usage rates; accommodating attitudes towards ‘sensible’ recreational drug use (especially by non-users); and a degree of cultural accommodation to illegal drug use” (Parker et al., 2002 in Sandberg, 2013) [...] a collection of rituals, stories and symbols [that] revolve around certain perceptions of the world and are often linked to general cultural currents in society. To a greater or lesser extent, people and groups internalize and embody parts of the subculture. They also exploit the subculture in creative portrayals of themselves. By doing this, Sandberg takes cultural practices (enacted in actual interactions) as the minimal unit to be analyzed, which allows for an in-between groups coverage of practices of ICU. This shift from groups of people to culturally modulated interactions as the object of study facilitates the application of semiotic analyses such as the one Tylén et al. (2013) developed in order to account for the dynamic emergence and stability of linguistic forms. In what follows, I will briefly introduce Tylén et al.’s dynamic account of the emergence and stability of linguistic forms, and explain why I think it is suitable for the study of artifacts. Then, I will sketch an analysis of typical artifacts in ICU as material nodes structuring cultural interaction, pointing at how ecological factors play an important role in their structural stability. A dynamic account of the emergence and stability of artifacts in ICU By referring to a series of studies in experimental pragmatics and semiotics, Tylén Side 23 The pivotal criticism of normalization theory against subculture theory can be understood as a methodological one - subculture theory attempts to delineate groups of people that oppose mainstream values by enacting ICU. But if we intended to group all cannabis users under a single social group, the label for that group would serve no practical or theoretical purpose beyond the tautological category of “illegal users of cannabis”, which would hardly constitute a marginalized minority today (as pointed out by normalization theory), much less a distinctive social group. In his paper (2013), Sandberg makes an ingenious move in order to save subculture theory from this criticism. Instead of focusing on groups of people in his study, he uses the term “subculture” to refer to Juan Olvido Side 24 et al. (2013) identify four sources of stability that motivate the emergence of shared meaning in linguistic structures. These are characterized as follows (adapted from Tylén et al., 2013, emphasis added): ••1st Source of stability: “our biological makeup constrains our sensorimotor engagements with the world. Though subject to great plasticity, there are limits to our perceptual sensitivity (e.g., the range and resolution of our perception, etc.) and our motor engagements with the environment that naturally constrain the way we can conceive of the world”. ••2nd Source of stability: “our physical/ material world has stable structure affording (but not determining) certain categorical and conceptual distinctions rather than others. This physical world encompasses both “natural” and “enculturated” properties and objects since a long history of human intervention has profoundly shaped our material world into a hybrid of natural objects and artifacts”. ••3rd Source of stability: “our immersion in specific socio-cultural and linguistic practices puts profound normative pressure on the way we perceptually attend to and realize the multiple structural affordances of the material environment. This gives local lingual-cultural variations to the structural affordances realized in different languages”. ••4th Source of stability: “the local history of successful communicative interactions constitutes another set of social affordances that, through processes of reciprocal alignment of perspectives and profilings, scaffold the stabilization of linguistic meaning”. The four sources of stability identified by Tylén et al. are also relevant to understand artifacts. In fact, according to their own terms, the only difference between artifacts and linguistic forms are the constraints of the different materials in which they’re respectively instantiated (2nd source of stability). Interestingly, the fact that artifacts such as pipes, joints, and other variations of cannabis cigarettes are intended for consumption gives a new dimension to the 1st source of stability (our biological makeup) in that it is precisely by virtue of the chemical effects that cannabis has in our bodies that the substance acquires its relevance as a drug. If these four sources of stability were actually involved in the outcome of artifacts as cultural forms, we should see variation in said cultural forms there were there was variation in the sources of stability. I am convinced that this is the case, and will briefly illustrate this point with some actual examples by referring to Tylén et al.’s sources of stability. Whereas a full-fledged analysis of ICU should, in my view, include a comprehensive account of the chemical effects of the drug in interactants (which would entail the interaction between the 1st and 2nd sources of stability), this will be omitted for the purposes of the present paper. 1st, our biological makeup One of the most interesting aspects in this respect would be studying the effects of cannabis in ongoing interactions to see how they contribute (or hinder) the transmission of subcultural values represented by the enactment of cultural practices of ICU. Joints, spliffs, pipes, bongs, etc., administer different quantities of cannabis, in different intervals and are sometimes mixed in different concentrations with other substances Sociogenesis and stability of artifacts... (ie., tobacco). It would therefore be interesting to further explore the precise effect of these changes in the way people experience the enactment of these practices. For the moment being, however, I will just work under the assumption that our biological makeup (and therefore the “general” effect of cannabis on humans) is by and large the same as it was when certain subcultures introduce the drug in Western communities (Sandberg, 2013), so this source of stability has remained nearly identical. 3rd, our immersion in specific socio-cultural and artifact-manufacturing practices This point must be crucially extended if we want to account for the nature not only of artifacts involved in ICU, but also if we want to understand the set of practices that so consistently accompany it. A clearly determinative factor to take into account Side 25 2nd, our physical world Regarding aspects relative to the material world in which cultural practices of ICU are embedded (2nd source of stability), I could venture that the general availability of cannabis (as a function of ease of access and price) is today higher than it was during the 60s and 70s. Sadly, I cannot refer to specific data supporting this claim. I can, however, make reference to synchronic changes in current ICU in as typified in different geographical regions to claim that the material properties of the world around us are a source of stability for the cultural forms that inhabit practices of ICU. In Southern Spain specially (and Europe in general), the consumption of hash is much higher relative to that of America, where dried marijuana is the most widespread form of cannabis (Gamella & Jiménez, 2008). Given the physical properties of these two substances (a thick, sticky paste in the case of hash, and a somewhat crackly and dry herb covered in fine, sticky dust in the case of marijuana), it would follow that different forms would arise in order to incorporate them in cultural practices of ICU. That is indeed the case - whereas pipes, bongs and spliffs (cigarettes containing only marijuana) seem to be most common in America, joints (cannabis with tobacco) seem to be the preferred method of consumption in most of Europe, a more accentuated trend the closer we get to the countries where hash is imported to. In fact, hash can only be smoked by itself in long, thin pipes such as those used in the Rif mountains. Furthermore, within European boundaries, hand-rolled filters also vary in shape and nature according to the most available forms of cannabis. That is, some widely available materials and shapes seem to be favored over others when manufacturing filters depending on the form of cannabis that is being smoked. Another comparison could illustrate this last point - whereas it is common in Southern Spain to find “moras” (filters with tobacco in them, that prevent the passing of small particles such as tobacco or small pieces of hash), this form of filter is hardly found in other European regions where marijuana is more common - many users would see the finer granularity of “mora” filters as a waste because much of the smoke would remain in the filter. Most filters for “joints” with marijuana (and not hash) are thus elaborated by rolling a piece of cardboard into an empty cylinder that lets through all of the smoke, while providing structural support for the joint to be held between the lips, and indicating that the joint is “finished”. Side 26 Juan Olvido is the legal status of cannabis. I will extend on this issue in the section below, as I hold the opinion that this aspect is essential if we want to understand the social dynamics of cultural practices revolving ICU. Within illegal users of cannabis, different sets of assumptions in their respective subcultures give rise to various local cultural forms. This, again, is reflected in artifacts. Cultural groups that share a dislike for tobacco will recur to “spliffs” or “pipes” rather than “joints”. These dynamics will surely interact with those elicited by other sources of stability, giving rise to more stable forms over time. As interactions involving ICU become typified, interactants will enact them according to their own intentions and goals - as such ICU might be a more conversational experience in communities where the quantity, concentration, and frequency of use are lower, whereas it might lead to other interpersonal dynamics in other communities (i.e., where it is smoked in high quantities). It is very important to note that there seems to be a core set of practices common to all western illegal users of cannabis, and it seems to me that this is the adequate section to discuss them in more detail. This core set of practices is manifested with parametric variations in different social, aesthetic, or linguistic communities, but its principles still respond to the description by Zimmerman & Wieder (1977) that a) everyone who has cannabis is expected to share, b) the joint or pipe is passed round to all those present, and c) smoking cannabis together obliges one to further social interaction (adapted from Sandberg, 2013). This is the “stable” culture that supporters of subculture theory refer to, as it can still be observed in illegal users of cannabis today. The assumption of sub-culture theorists is that this set of practices survives as an expression of values (ie., sharing) that were shared by the communities that first brought ICU to Western cultures “en masse”. However, it is also clear that aspects such as the legal status of cannabis must have a big impact in these practices. For example, principles a) and b) (Zimmerman & Wieder, 1977) described above could - and in my view, do - respond to an expression of generosity or collective property while, at the same time, maximizing its pervasiveness in cultural communities by involving everyone present in the cultural practice. Thus, not only is there a general sense of belonging and in-group (hypothesized by some social scientists to underlie much of what goes on in human social dynamics, cf. Alford & Hibbing, 2004) but, on top of that, no one in the group would be liable to accuse others of doing something illegal without risk of putting herself in danger because she would have also taken part in ICU. 4th, the local history of successful interactions Cultural practices of ICU are rich, varied and respond to minimal changes in the purposes for which it is enacted as well as the constraints imposed on them by the sources of stability at discussion. As extensively noted by researchers that affiliate with a subcultural approach (Sandberg 2013), it is not strange to find a richness of shared local terms, rituals, symbols, stories associated with ICU. These cultural forms, however, are heavily ostracized in that their public accessibility is much more reduced than those of collective cultural practices such as going to the cinema, cooking, bowling, drinking alcohol, etc. Normalization theory does well in pointing at a progressive shift towards acceptation, but it cannot overlook Sociogenesis and stability of artifacts... the fact that, as it happens, cannabis is still illegal in much of the Western world. If the public accessibility of these practices is so reduced (presumably because of the risk it would supposed to enact them openly), how, then, can we explain the existence of a “core set” of practices that extends well beyond national and continental boundaries, and manifests itself regardless of the language spoken by the interactants? It would appear as if the main means of transmission for this kind of practice is its enactment - that is, “the local history of successful interactions”. Thus, in the absence of public channels (public spaces, mass media) in which cultural practices of ICU could be enacted, these practices become conventionalized and acquire structural stability through reiterated enactment. In an online survey I published thanks to the generosity of the administrators of the erowid website, I had cannabis smokers of a varied background answer where they acquired their knowledge (expressed in lexical terms) about different forms of cannabis, marijuana cigarettes, etc. Out of 1085, 903 answered that they learned these things “while smoking”. This contrasts starkly with the 113 that answered that they acquired this knowledge from cultural material (comic books, films, tv-series, internet) and supports my claim. It is not hard to conclude that this dynamics is heavily influenced by the legal status of cannabis. Bibliography Alford, J. R., & Hibbing, J. R. (2004). The origin of politics: An evolutionary theory of political behavior. Perspectives on Politics, 2(04), 707-723. Bateson, G. (1967). Cybernetic explanation. American Behavioral Scientist,10(8), 29-29. Gamella, J. F., & Jiménez, M. L. (2008). Multinational export–import ventures: Moroccan hashish Side 27 Discussion The conclusions I extract from my brief analysis of artifacts as a subtype of cultural forms in cultural practices of ICU is that the stability of cultural forms depends not only on the need for individuals to define themselves against a majority of people by enacting “marginalized” practices - crucially, it is also ecological socioeconomic factors that have favored stability in the cultural forms. The stability of these cultural forms might have, in turn, reinforced the values they represent, which would support the claims of subculture theory. For normalization theory, the reasoning goes the other way: as long as the dynamics of ICU are modulated by the same set of constraints as they were in its origins in Western practitioners, its cultural forms (and therefore its expressive value) are likely to remain stable and unchanged. Biological, physical, but also human factors constrain cultural practices of ICU. Laws could be seen as a factor promoting the stability of denormalization today. However, we must not disregard the claims made by normalization theory - the amount of cultural references to ICU in mass media is increasingly bigger and less covert. This can be seen as trends by referring to tv-series such as South Park, The Simpsons, Futurama, How I Met Your Mother in which punctual references are more or less covert, or That 70’s Show, Smiley Face or the Spanish Malviviendo in which cannabis becomes a central leitmotif around which the narrative is structured. These are only some of the cultural products that I have consumed as an enculturated Westerner. They are part of an increasing body of publicly accessible (through the internet) mass cultural products, so their influence should not be underestimated. Juan Olvido Side 28 into Europe through Spain (). EMCDDA MONOGRAPHS, 263. Hackett, C. F. (1960). The origin of speech. Scientific American, 203, 88-96. Parker, H., Williams, L., & Aldridge, J. (2002). The Normalization of ‘Sensible’Recreational Drug Use Further Evidence from the North West England Longitudinal Study. Sociology, 36(4), 941964. Saxe, G. B., & Esmonde, I. (2005). ARTICLES: Studying Cognition in Flux: A Historical Treat- ment of Fu in the Shifting Structure of Oksapmin Mathematics.Mind, culture, and activity, 12(3-4), 171-225. Tylén, K., Fusaroli, R., Bundgaard, P. F., & Østergaard, S. (2013). Making sense together: A dynamical account of linguistic meaning-making. Semiotica,2013(194), 39-62. Zimmerman, D.H. & Wieder, D.L. (1977) You can’t help but get stoned: Notes on the social organization of marijuana smoking. Social Problems 25(2): 198–207. Kevin Crowley Extended Mind, Shrinking Memory Intro: Our symbiotic relationship with technology The mind is not bound by our brain, according to David J. Chalmers and Andy Clark. In their pivotal essay “The Extended Mind”, they cut at the heart of the meaning of cognition and thereby challenge our preconceived notions of the concept of “mind”. In the essay, they ask us first to consider three problem-solving cases. Each case is a simple task of fitting the right shape in the socket, the kind we have experience doing as kindergarteners, except on a computer. In one case, a person is asked to mentally rotate the objects to find the right fit. The second case, a person can change the orientation of the shapes by pressing a rotate button on the computer. The third case is a more hypothetical futuristic option, where a person is hooked to a neural implant and can actually rotate the shapes immediately by just thinking about it. They then ask, ”How much cognition is present in each of these cases?”. To Chalmers and Clark, each case is of a similar nature. The only difference is that the act of physically pressing the button to rotate the shape in case two is simply a physical manifestation of the same cognitive process. In such a case, we have effectively extended the operationalization S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 2 9 - 3 7 Our mind is not only in our heads. It is all around us. At least, that is the base presumption of the Extended Mind theory, developed by David J. Chalmers and Andy Clark (1998). They argue that humans are linked with external entities (i.e. tools and technology) in a coupled system that effectively extends our cognition beyond the borders of skin and skull. They claim, as humans rely on these external entities to help us with tasks, our mind is extended to those entities. But what are and has been the consequences of this extension? Socrates warned against one such mind extending technology—writing, insisting that “...this invention will produce forgetfulness in the minds of those who learn to use it” (Plato, Phaedrus 274c, translated by Fowler 1925). To what degree is Socrates right? In this critical essay, we will examine the main points of the extended mind thesis and consider how the theory, although clearly a boon in many ways, with unchecked technological development, can also turn into a bane for mankind and why we should be cautious. Side 30 Kevin Crowley to a part of the body. They further point to other common cases where this extension of a cognitive process occurs. Their examples include: solving a math problem with paper and pen, the physical rearrangements of letters in the game of Scrabble, and even the use of language, through any of its mediums, are seen as a mechanism of mind extension via environmental supporters. Certainly, the example of language seems to fit nicely with the theory of image schemas, in that babies and toddlers are suspected of deriving meaning through interaction with their environment which enables them to develop schematic associations that eventually become coupled with language (Mandler 1992). Further, it has been shown in adults as well through a matching task of sentence and image (i.e. subjects shown “the eagle is flying”, but showing an eagle with its wings folded), with mismatch sentenceto-image trials resulting in slower responses, suggesting perceptual symbols are activated in language comprehension (Zwaan et al. 2002). Thus, if this pre-linguistic structure aids the conceptual metaphor mapping that we establish when language is formed, then even the acquisition of language has its roots in the physical world. So then, what could the possible benefits of relegating mental tasks to physical mediums? In line with their hypothetical shaperotation cases, they refer to a study where it is calculated how long it takes to rotate shapes in the game of Tetris versus doing it mentally. It was found that it takes significantly longer to do it mentally than by the normal button-pressing method (300ms vs. 1000ms) (Chalmers & Clark, A. 1998). These kinds of actions are referred to as epistemic actions, which change the world in order to aid and augment cognitive practices, which are contrasted with what is called pragmatic actions, a physical change done for a desirable outcome (i.e. hedging the bushes for aesthetic appeal) (Chalmers and Clark 1998). Thus they claim that epistemic action is inherently a coupled system: the mind and physical environment both, being linked in an interactive two-way system. This process, they claim, is an active process involved in the here and now. They write: Because they [external features] are coupled with the human organism, they have a direct impact on the organism and on its behavior. In these cases, the relevant parts of the world are in the loop, not dangling at the other end of a long causal chain. (Chalmers & Clark 1998) And this, what they call active externalism, is what is behind the online execution of mental tasks, where if it were not involved, as the Tetris timed task example illustrates, our performance or competency of such tasks would diminish. Thus we use environmental resources as an epistemic action because it enhances the execution of those tasks. In other words, we get better and faster at them. Chalmers, in his TED Talk about the extended mind, uses the idea of an extended body as a comparable analogy, eliciting such examples as prosthetic limbs, canes for blind people, or even cars, bicycles, and musical instruments (Chalmers, D. 2011). In all of these examples, each tool or technology enhances a function that we would not be able to do as well otherwise (i.e. to see if you are blind; run as fast as a bicycle/ car). Similarly, he invokes a very presentday example of the iPhone and how it and other smartphones are mitigating the role of our brain in everyday mental activities. He outwardly admits: Extended Mind, Shrinking Memor y It’s basically started taking over a whole bunch of the functions of my brain. (Chalmers, D. 2011) Surely, anyone who has experience with a smart-phone probably has noticed this themselves. Remembering phone numbers, spatial navigation (GPS), schedule planning, and suggestions for consumer purchases are just some of the functions smartphones can do for us, and that we can become reliant upon. And most of us have probably experienced the “Let’s ask Google” panacea as either a debate breaker or to find some piece of information you might have at the tip of your tongue, but just cannot seem to wait for your memory to grasp it. Interestingly, while smart-phones, which most have experience with nowadays, provides the most relatable example of the extended mind thesis, it also provides the most poignant example of a technology which comes with some striking negative side effects. While Chalmers, in that TED Talk, mentions some of the downsides of the extended mind, he seems to only scrape the surface, insisting on speaking of it in a positive tone. With the iPhone-mind takeover he spoke about in mind, let us now look further into the negative consequences of a mind exponentially extending. Memory and cognition before writing The negative consequences of an extended mind where articulated well by Plato, in the book of Phaedrus, concerning the ramifications of one such extension technology – writing: The cynical words of Socrates, a person who had his pupil Plato scribe his speeches, against ’writing’ still ring true to this day. While some people see his warning as a failed prophecy about the bane of writing, the invention of writing actually did change a lot in memory and cognition. Of course, before the invention of writing, information was still passed down from generation to generation, but was done so orally. Even during the advent of writing and up until the mass production of books, (starting from the Gutenberg printing press), reading and writing was not a common practice. Instead it was the privileged upper class of society that were literate throughout much of civilized history. The majority of people had no skill to read or write, yet they maintained to pass their cultures down to the succeeding generations. How was this feat accomplished for so many millennia? How do oral societies pass down their knowledge and what effects do they have on our memory and cognition? The two epic stories which have been well studied are Homer’s two classics, The Illiad and The Odyssey. Before these stories were put into written form they are commonly thought to have been created by Side 31 For this invention will produce forgetfulness in the minds of those who learn to use it, because they will not practice their memory. Their trust in writing, produced by external characters which are no part of themselves, will discourage the use of their own memory within them. You have invented an elixir not of memory, but of reminding; and you offer your pupils the appearance of wisdom, not true wisdom, for they will read many things without instruction and will therefore seem to know many things, when they are for the most part ignorant and hard to get along with, since they are not wise, but only appear wise. (Plato, Phaedrus 274c, translated by Fowler 1925) Side 32 Kevin Crowley a bard named Homer, although they are uncertain whether this was one person or several. (Parry 1987; West 1999). But what is certain is that despite whoever its creator was, the stories could not have survived without many capable poet-bards that would retell the story over and over until it was written down. And so regardless of whoever the epic poem’s original maker was, if looked upon as a result of successive transmissions, it is without a doubt a product of numerous individuals. Interestingly, what made this successive transmission possible was the style in which Homer’s works were told, namely in a poetic, rhythmic, and prosodic style. The use of dactylic hexameter verse, a metrical line composed of six parts with each part consisting of one long syllable followed by two short syllables, helped guide the structure of its retelling and put the poem into chunks, thus making it easier to remember. Homer also uses epic-style similes, using vivid analogous description of an event, and also using relatable word-picture associations (Rambo 1932). Homer’s stories’ are also full of clichés and strong characters, and furthermore only uses concrete examples of abstract concepts such as heroism, wisdom, and justice, thus further utilizing mnemonic devices (Rubin 1997). One scholar of the transition from oral societies to writing societies, Walter J. Ong, agrees in that ”Colorless personalities cannot survive oral mnemonics” (2002). In the same vein, one common modern mnemonic device is to associate a target item with something that is unique, violent, unusual, absurd, or extraordinary (Lorayne 1985,p.17-20). This is also sometimes called “the slap in the face principle”, using the analogy that someone would not forget being slapped in the face. And it stands to reason that this technique would afford memorization better than a mundane action, as epic poetry’s utilization of this principle also illustrates. So, without writing, it appears that certain styles that afford memorization were necessary in order to be successfully passed down. Rather than ink, in oral tradition, mnemonic tools are the medium of choice. Those styles that were ill-adapted for memorization did not survive and were lost to the ages. To me, it seems to be a testament to the greatness not only of Homer’s epic poems, but of the styles that developed in the pre-writing ancient world that were necessary for the survival of the story; it can be viewed as a sort of Darwinian survival of the fittest of oral tale. Of course, this type of transmission is not without its faults. Much like the telephone game, where a group whispers along a sentence down a line, and by the end it is altered significantly (sometimes hilariously so), so too oral traditions cannot escape this error that is inherent in the system of oral transmission. Memory is a dynamic social process. Memory systems do not preserve or reproduce cultural knowledge without sometimes altering, shaping, or even inventing it, either consciously or unconsciously. (Goucher , LeGuin, & Walton 1998) However, due to the style that developed in oral tradition, which essentially embedded mnemonics into its structure, it has made transmission error free more than one would expect. Through oral tradition’s multiple constraints, it made it so that oral texts need not be remembered verbatim. Each time Homer’s stories were performed, the text was reconstructed, held together Extended Mind, Shrinking Memor y recitable and accessible to the audience by using common ’type scenes’ of the time. This aspect of a ’shared consciousness’ is suspected to be one of the effects of oral societies on the mind. Not only are formulae and type scenes aiding the storyteller’s memory, but also living through the character’s lives as the story unfolds, as a poet would animately sing the tale, creates an inescapable vicariousness for both reciter and audience. Listeners would be entrenched, as if in a trance, as the story comes alive in the present moment during the performance (Neel 1988). Story, poet, and listener would be bonded supposedly greater than what we can presently relate to in the world of print or computer text. Further touching upon the effects on cognition, Walter J. Ong, who was briefly mentioned before, was one of the leading scholars on the psychological effects of the transition from oral culture to writing culture. In his book Orality and Literacy (1982), he claims that writing fundamentally changed the way people think, feel, and interact with one another. Orality is fundamental to humanity in that it affords community in the immediate moment with another person. On the other hand, writing is what stemmed from that rich oral culture, and in the end corrupted it, losing its intersubjectivity in the process and becoming a pipeline of sender and receiver. Of course this is not limited to writing, rather Ong points the finger at all type of media that is uni-directional, from television to radio. From this one directional way of communicating, he claims our personal psychology has changed from holistic, shared-group thinking and communication, to an interiorized consciousness, withholding knowledge to the self and thus greater individuation (1982). Side 33 by the dactylic hexameter, rhyme patterns, and mnemonic-riddled structure. The main point of oral epic-poem storytelling was to transmit the main features of the story, while the way in which the poem is told the story was left up to the transmitter. This way of structuring oral stories is not only a characteristic of Homer or of other ancient epics, but also supported by research of more modern oral societies. Two famous scholars of this topic, Harvard University professors Milman Parry and his student, Albert Lord, visited the southern part of former Yugoslavia from the years 1933 to 1935, and studied a then-present-day oral tradition in the Serbian-Croatian language. They luckily found a master storyteller named Avdo Međedović who could perform a story in a very similar manner and length as the Illiad, as many as 12,000 lines (Nagy 2013). Through their research of a live oral tradition, they discovered that poets are able to store formulas, similar to the chunks we have learned in fairy-tales (ie. Once upon a time; In a galaxy far far away), but to a much greater degree and complexity. Thus, where in normal discourse people have stored words and some chunks of words (i.e. idioms, maxims, etc.) and a speaker has relative freedom to arrange their sentences, epic storytellers, on the other hand, have these chunks organized and structured on a higher level, which are known as theme or type scene (Foley 1966). Basically, these themes are stereotypes of scenes that are remembered not only in the mind of the story reciter, but also in the social conscious mind. This oral-formulaic theory shows how long epics can be memorized using such formulas that are not only in one mind or in the mind of previous story tellers, but the structure also makes it possible for storytellers to improvise in order to make it Kevin Crowley Side 34 In this way, it seems that there are some intriguing effects of the entities that our mind is extended to, and conversely, what minds are extended to us. But what further evidence is there for this effect? Let us now examine a few recent studies of technology affecting our mind. The mind stretched thin Going beyond how writing has affected human memory, it turns out recent technology has further impacted our memory capabilities. Aside from the numerous personal anecdotes we all likely have experience with our smart-phones or computers, such as no longer remembering phone numbers, being slower at mental math, and forgetting how to spell words (thanks to spell-check), what other effects on our memory and cognition might there be from high-technology societies? Since computers and the internet have made it possible to read text, humans have now made accessing another person’s mind even easier than its now-primitive ink and paper counterpart. And since the launch of Kindle, tablets, and other eReaders, whole books can now be consumed with relative ease. But can this easy access to the written word also affect our memory? It appears it can. In a recent study, 72 tenthgraders in Norway were split in two and one half asked to read a story in print; and the other half were asked to read the same story in PDF form. The students were given a comprehension test afterward about what they had read and the group who read the print version scored significantly higher (Mangen, et. al 2013). The experiment was done again a year later, this time using the Kindle, and similar results were found. While Mangen and company suspect a tactile feature which is at lost when holding a book and turning the pages that may be responsible for the poorer comprehension, she also says: Research shows that the amount of time spent reading long-form texts is in decline, and due in large part to increasing digitization, reading is becoming more intermittent and fragmented overall. (Mangen 2014) In concurrence with this opinion, I believe people who read on digital mediums can remember less partly because of those people’s fragmented reading habits, but I will go further in saying that the cause of those habits stems from the innate capability of E-readers which allow quick access to the text. The brain’s memory faculty has no need to hold onto whatever it knows it can access quickly. This is further supported by another recent study seeing how photographs can affect our memory retrieval. In this study, subjects were asked to tour through a museum, half of them taking photos of objects, the other half just looking. It was found that there was a photo-taking-impairment effect as participants who used the camera could remember fewer objects and details than those who did not use a camera. However, when certain details were zoomed in on by some subjects, there was not an effect, but interestingly their recall was just as good as the no-camera’s memory of the zoomed-in detail (Henkel 2014). Thus, similar to eReaders, the brain can more readily let go of information it knows it can retrieve in the physical world, thus creating an impairment of what our brain is actually capable of remembering. When our body is extended physically, as in a car to enhance our traveling capabili- Extended Mind, Shrinking Memor y ties, the cost of not using your legs as much would mean the muscles would atrophy to some degree and we would not be as strong or healthy as a person who walked all of the time. And so, too, when our mind is extended to a physical object, the cost is our mind not being to perform the task as well as it could as a person who can do the task without the tool. And this effect is shown even more so when the object is relied upon heavily or allows its use to be instantaneous. Forebodingly, it might serve us well to carefully consider the implications of augmented reality devices even more. The flexible mind and sociological effects What this investigation shows us is the incredible flexibility of the mind. Its ability to spread knowledge to other minds is an incredible phenomenon in of itself. Through this spread of human thought, first by voice, reaching those in your immediate circle, then by writing, touching the lives of any who have access, and now by computers, smart-phones, and the internet, we have been able to express and hold onto the thoughts of others. We have made it possible to share, collaborate, and work together. To some extent, this extension has been invaluable, continuously and exponentially enhancing human life. This extension of mind cannot only be held by other minds, but by the artifacts that surround us. Tools that we use to save information or do calculations can have a very positive effect on our way of life, and at the same time have a very negative effect on our own mind’s capability of doing it without aid. As men- Side 35 The socially extended mind As we live in a reading and writing culture, it may seem strange to us how the technology we all have grown up with and accustomed to could be hindering the potential of our memory’s capacity, and even perhaps even more bizarre of how it can affect our consciousness. After all, this technology has enabled us to spread information farther and to more people than ever before. However, it appears to be because of this extension that we are apt at letting go of memories we know can be retrieved by something, or even someone else. It is well known trope that senior citizens rely on each other for retrieval of information. Even Chalmers himself used the old couple stereotype as one of his examples of how another person can act as their memory, which he calls the socially extended mind. (2011). Two good friends or lovers finishing each other’s’ sentences, or social networking, and crowd-sourcing are all other good examples of this social mind. But as Chalmers also warns in his talk, as our mind is extended more, the more vulnerable to harm there is when that object that our mind is extended to is lost (i.e. when you lose your iPhone, your hard drive dies, or worse still, your friend or lover passes). Thus, while extension of mind is inevitable, to what, whom, and how we extend to makes a difference. As social creatures, humans cannot expect to give up this extension in the social realm, nor would it be healthy to. After all, as mentioned before, this social interconnectedness is the foundation of human culture. However, if due to social networking, for example, our mind is extended to too many people, there might be richness lost in our social interactions as our mind is stretched thin. Likewise, if the mind is extended to our GPS navigational system, for example, were one to be lost or the navigational system malfunctioned, one might not have the cognitive resources to find their way. Kevin Crowley tioned, there is probably no person without a story of how some technology has made it harder for them to do a task without its use. Not that this is always a bad thing. Relegating tasks to our tools can free up cognitive resources so that it can attend to other things. This is why those tools, such as calculators and writing, were invented in the first place. When we can focus less on how to solve a complicated formula, for instance, the more time we can spend doing other things like solving the issue at hand. And this is the true hallmark of progress: when technology makes certain tasks easier, we can move on and address novel problems, and advance technology. Yet there is still nagging feeling that I and others have. German author and poet, Hans Magnus Enzensberger, in his essay In Praise of Illiteracy, extols the virtues of an illiterate mind, writing: Side 36 I envy the illiterate his memory, his capacity for concentration, his cunning, his inventiveness, his tenacity, his sensitive ear. Please don’t imagine that I am speaking not about romantic phantoms but about people I have met. I am far from idealizing them. I also see their narrow horizons, their illusions, their obstinacy, their quaintness. (Enzensberger & Lipson 1986) Likewise, there seem to be something about the human condition that we have lost by becoming literate, forgoing communal storytelling, vivid vicarious experiences, and therefore a bond with human brethren that we might never again know. It is also possible by forgoing such experiences, there is a lack of spiritually internalizing knowledge, and instead we use knowledge in a utilitarian fashion, copying and pasting knowledge where it suits us best. Enzensberger (1986) also brings up another problem with literate society, or rather the literate society which developed since the 18th century. From the second half of that century, many of today’s first world nations underwent a systematic project of making the general populace literate. Many of those nations succeeded, achieving less than 1% illiteracy of the population. But simultaneously, according to Enzensberger, indoctrination and homogeneity accompanied this education. A byproduct of this education which we have all grown up in is what he calls a second-order illiterate, one who can read for practical matters, whose concentration lacks, yet considers himself well-informed. This is the perfect type of citizen who can be swayed easily to be a good consumer in a capitalist society. Furthermore, one other sociological phenomenon that is worthy of mention is the change of our value of intelligence. As one author poignantly points out: The externalization of memory not only changed how people think; it also led to a profound shift in the very notion of what it means to be intelligent. Internal memory became devalued. Erudition evolved from possessing information internally to knowing how and where to find it in the labyrinthe world of external memory. (Foer 2011) Of course to some degree people still cherish and admire those who can tell a good story or have the gift of gab. However, since writing, and more recently with the internet, internal knowledge has been evermore subverted and relegated to a needless skill. Now, with the world’s knowledge at our fingertips, it has been an equalizing force in a way, with knowledge being accessible to Extended Mind, Shrinking Memor y all. But as people consume more and more, it appears we end up remembering less and less. There may be a ceiling for constructive consumption in the human mind after all. It is very possible that modern erudition could be turning students into (using Socrates’ term) “empty vessels”. Conclusion While it is not my purpose to advocate illiteracy in this article, nor any Luddite-like halting of technological progress and mind extension technologies, it behooves us to be aware of the implications of an extended mind, especially in the domains of writing, high-tech gadgets, and social networking, and the pitfalls that may accompany them if left unchecked. Chalmers mentions that since the mind is flexible, we can be positive about the future, reassuring that mankind may make the right decision. But it is also very possible, as he admits, that this mind extension, just like technology itself, can be used for bad as well. Let us hope we do not, as Plato said, create an elixir of reminding, but rather strive toward wisdom as our minds extend and interconnect. References Side 37 Enzensberger, H.M & Lipson M, (1986). “In Praise of Illiteracy.” Grand Street 5, no. 4 (1986): 88. doi:10.2307/25006902. Foer, J. (2011). Moonwalking with Einstein, Penguin Press HC. ISBN 978-1-59420-229-2 Foley, J. M. (1966). Oral-Formulaic Theory and Research: An Introduction and Annotated Bibliography. New York: Garland Publishing, Inc. 1985. p. 42.; Foley cites ”The Literary Character of Anglo-Saxon Formulaic Poetry” Publications of the Modern Language Association 81, 334–41 Goucher, C. L., Le Guin,C.A, and Walton, L.A. (1998). In the Balance: A Thematic Global History, Vol. 1 and 2. Boston, Mass.: Mcgraw-Hill College. Henkel, L. A. (2014). “Point-and-Shoot Memories: The Influence of Taking Photos on Memory for a Museum Tour.” Psychological Science 25, no. 2. February 1: 396–402. doi:10.1177/0956797613504438. Lorayne, H. (1985). Harry Lorayne’s Page-a-Minute Memory Book. Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. Ong, W. J.(2002). Orality and Literacy: The Technologizing of the Word. Routledge. Mandler, J.M. (1992) On the Birth and Growth of Concepts. Philosophical Psychology Vol. 21, No. 2, April 2008, pp. 207–230 Mangen, A. et. al (2013). “Reading Linear Texts on Paper versus Computer Screen: Effects on Reading Comprehension.” International Journal of Educational Research 58: 61–68. doi:10.1016/j. ijer.2012.12.002. Mangen, A. et al. (2014). Mystery story reading in pocket print book and on Kindle: possible impact on chronological events memory. Conference paper presentation, IGEL (The International Society for the Empirical Study of Literature and Media), Turin, Italy July 21-25 Mangen, A. (2014). “COST IS1404 E-READ: Evolution of Reading in the Age of Digitisation.” . Accessed October 29. https://www.academia. edu/7664953/COST _IS1404_EREAD. Parry, A. (ed.) (1987)The Making of Homeric Verse: The Collected Papers of Milman Parry, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Nagy, G. (2013). The Ancient Greek Hero in 24 Hours. Harvard University Press. Neel, J.P. (1988). Plato, Derrida, and Writing. SIU Press. Plato, from the book of Phaedrus (1925). (from Plato in Twelve Volumes, Vol. 9, translated by Fowler, H.N. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd. http:// www.perseus.tufts.edu) Rambo, E.F. (1932).On Homer’s Similes.The Classical Journal, Vol. 28, No. 1., pp. 22-31. Rubin, D. C. (1997). Memory in Oral Traditions: The Cognitive Psychology of Epic, Ballads, and Counting-Out Rhymes. Oxford University Press. West, Martin (1999). ”The Invention of Homer”. Classical Quarterly49(364). Zwaan, R. A., Stanweld, R. A., & Yaxley, R. H. (2002). Language comprehenders mentally represent t he shapes of objects. Psychological Science, 13(2), 168–171. Nis Langer Primdahl A r t e f a k t, m o d e r n i t e t – social acceleration Artiklen diskuterer relationen mellem det tekniske artefakt og senmodernitetens strukturelle tidslighed. Er det muligt for det senmoderne subjekt løbende at veksle mellem henholdsvis langsom og hurtig tid ved at vælge ting fra eller til? Hvordan skal subjektets relation til det tekniske artefakt fortolkes i et samfund præget af social acceleration? S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 3 8 - 4 6 The logic of the cabin deserves to be globalized (Eriksen 2001: 157) Med dette diktum betoner den norske socialantropolog Thomas Hylland Eriksen, hvordan det afsondrede rum i fjeldet med plads til stille dvælen bør udbredes. I hytten hersker langsommelig tænkning; i hytten står selvet i et særligt forhold til tiden. Modsætningen til denne hyttens tidslighed er den hurtige tid, ’øjeblikkets tyranni’, der har indfundet sig i det senmoderne samfund. At samfundsudviklingen sker med forøget hastighed har været en integreret del af fortællingen om moderniteten, ligesom sondringen mellem det moderne og det senmoderne har impliceret en ændring i vores forhold til tiden. Spørgsmålet bliver da, hvorvidt diskrepansen mellem en hurtig og langsom tidslogik, som subjektet ifølge Hylland Eriksen veksler i mellem, kan anvendes som kritik af det senmoderne samfunds tidslighed? Som jeg vil vise, er dette tvivlsomt, fordi relationen mellem subjekt, social acceleration og det tekniske artefakt er af en sådan karakter, at ligevæg ten mellem det hurtige og langsomme udviskes – kun det hurtige gør sig gældende. Det interessante og problematiske ved begrebet om en specifik, langsommelig tidslig logik i hytten, er at en sådan logik implicerer, at subjektets forhold til tiden er betinget af både hytten som afsondret sted uden for højhastighedssamfundet, og af det fravær af tekniske artefakter, lokaliteten ligeledes indebærer. Implikationen af denne udlægning hos Hylland Eriksen er, at tingen og min relation til tiden er forbundet således, at et fravær af tingen bevirker en overgang fra hurtig til langsom tid; jeg kan slukke min telefon, tage mit armbåndsur af, koble e-mailpåmindelser fra og derved overgå til en stemning præget af langsommelig dvælen. Subjektets tidslighed er altså bundet til det tekniske artefakt, og et midlertidigt eller varigt brud på denne relation gør det samtidig muligt at springe fra et hverdagsliv i høj hastighed tilbage ind i langsommeligheden. A r t e f a k t, m o d e r n i t e t Modernitet og strukturel tidslighed Relationen mellem det tekniske artefakt, tiden og moderniteten tematiseres i det 20. århundredes filosofiske og socialvidenskabelige tradition på forskellig vis. I den klassiske sociologi er Max Weber, Émile Durkheim og Karl Marx kritiske over for den forøgelse af hastighed, som industrialiseringen, bureaukratiet og den moderne kapitalisme medfører, og de peger alle på en grundlæggende forøgelse ikke blot af hastigheden i samfundets funktionelle elementer, men på den tendens i det moderne, at selve tiden begynder at gå hurtigere (Elias 2007: 156).1 Hos Nicklas Luhmann findes en bemærkelsesværdig formulering, der mere aktuelt tematiserer forholdet mellem modernitet og strukturel tidslighed: Mit dem Aufkommen der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft [hat sich] die Struktur der Zeit drastisch in Richtung auf höhere temporale Komplexität verändert [..., deshalb] müssen wir davon ausgehen, dass diese Umstrukturierung auf jede soziale Struktur und jeden Begriff einwirkt. Nichts wird seinen früheren Sinn behalten. (Luhmann 1990: 122)2 Side 39 Der peges her på en række facetter af forholdet mellem modernitet og tid. For det første anfører Luhmann, at der ved det moderne borgerlige samfunds begyndelse finder en restrukturering af måden, hvorpå de tidslige strukturer indvirker på sociale strukturer, sted. Der er altså tale om, at den gensidige, strukturelle relation mellem tid og samfund træder ind en ny fase, implicerer en ny definition af begreberne og indstifter en ny tid. En fortolkning af modernitetens epoke må på den måde indeholde en udlægning af denne epokes tidslighed, altså måden hvorpå strukturerne er tidsligt betingede. For det andet knyttes udviklingen til en forøgelse af den samfundsmæssige kompleksitet, en udvikling der som nævnt allerede hos tidlige sociologiske tænkere som Marx, Durkheim og Weber er i spil. Endeligt påpeger Luhmann, at denne forandring har implikationer, der er mere vidtgående end den semantiske ændring af de anvendte begreber. Det bemærkelsesværdige viser sig altså i måden, hvorpå de forskellige dimensioner af relationen mellem tidslighed og modernitet på både et strukturelt, et udviklingsteoretisk og et begrebsligt niveau og gøres til genstand for en videre undersøgelse. Ovenstående tematik befinder sig inden for de seneste tre årtiers aktualisering af tidslighedsbegrebet som grundbegreb i en analyse og kritik af samfundet.3 Opkomsten af samfundsanalyser baseret på begreber som acceleration, hastighed og fart udtrykker, hvad man kunne betegne en temporal-diagnostisk tilgang, der tager kritisk afsæt i forskellige former for strukturel tidslighed. Spørgsmål om eksempelvis klasse, identitet, kultur og modernitet indeholder et tidsligt aspekt og derfor kan de kun besvares på baggrund af en afdækning af disse determinerende og underliggende tidsstrukturer. Endvidere betyder dette, at enhver kritisk tidsdiagnose kun kan gennemføres som en diagnose af en tids eller given epokes strukturelle tidslighed. Nyere sociologiske forsøg på en rekonceptualisering af det moderne enten som ’ufuldendt projekt’ (Habermas 1983) eller som sen modernitet, der løber løbsk (Giddens 1990), som individualisering præget af fleksibilitet (Sennett 1999), som flydende strukturer (Baumann 1994), øjeblikkets tyranni (Hylland-Eriksen 2001) eller bevægelse mod ikke-tid (Castells 2000) baserer Nis Langer Primdahl Side 40 sig i mere eller mindre udtalt grad på forskellige forestillinger om en moderne eller senmoderne tidslighed. Disse kan opdeles i to paradigmatiske perspektiver på modernitetsprocessen: modernitet som proces præget af kontinuitet (Habermas 1983), hvor den samme fundamentale dynamik, gør sig gældende eller modernitet som en proces af brud med radikale indbyrdes forskelle (Sennett 1999). Eksempelvis kan der i henhold til sidstnævnte perspektiv sondres mellem en klassisk og en sen modernitet – moderniteten forstås således i faser eller epoker, bestemt af en eller flere grunddynamikker. Med sit begreb om social acceleration forsøger den tyske socialfilosof Hartmut Rosa i en begrebsramme, der ligger i forlængelse af den kritiske teori, at problematisere det moderne begreb om acceleration ved at stille spørgsmålet om, hvordan accelerationen grundlæggende har ændret karakter i det senmoderne samfund; går tiden hurtigere i det senmoderne samfund og i så fald, hvilke konsekvenser har dette for det sociale subjekts måde at forstå sig selv og sin tid på? Tidslighed og acceleration I bred forstand defineres termen ’acceleration’ som en forøgelse af hastighed pr. tidsenhed. En båd kan siges at accelerere, hvis sejlhastigheden er højere nu, end den var før, og lavere end den vil være om lidt. I en sociologisk kontekst kan nævnes arbejdslivsstudier, hvor der anvendes en operationalisering af tidsbegrebet i ’hurtig tid’, hvor små arbejdsopgaver løses, og ’langsom tid’, hvor større projekter skabes (Holt et al. 2013: 35). Her bliver acceleration et parameter for forøgelsen af antallet af momenter i en given tidsperiode; antallet af små arbejdsopgaver kan således være accelererende. Social acceleration udlæg- ges her som en betegnelse for en bestemt form for dynamik, der på den ene side gør sig gældende som konstitutivt træk ved alle modernitetens faser, men som på den anden side samtidig ændrer tempo i bølger og derved gør en epokal opdeling mulig, eksempelvis mellem præmodernitet, klassisk modernitet og senmodernitet. Der er altså forskel på accelerationens intensitet, hvilket gør det muligt at bruge begrebet instrumentelt i en analyse af det klassisk modernitet over for senmoderniteten. Også i nyere systematiske teorier omkring moderniteten spiller denne forøgelse af alle momenters hastighed en væsentlig rolle. Gleick (1999) betoner, hvordan det moderne samfund på alle områder ikke blot er præget af fart, men ligefrem på fetichistisk maner er optaget en effektivisering af enhver proces på både mikro- og makroplan (Gleick 1999: 55, Tomlinson 2007). Udlægninger baseret på, at modernitetsprocessen er knyttet til en form for grundlæggende acceleration, at samfundet udvikler sig hurtigere og hurtigere, har siden 1980’erne været en tendens i sociologiske teorier. Koselleck taler om, at acceleration udgør et væsenstræk ved moderniteten (Koselleck 2004: 11). Moderniteten indvarsler en ny måde at erfare tiden på. Denne forandring konstituerer en ny form for moderne tidslighed, hvilket har konsekvenser for andre samfundsmæssige strukturmomenter. Acceleration får dermed hos Koselleck status af en overskrift for skellet mellem modernitet og en præmodernitet. I den tidlige modernitet opstår ifølge Koselleck en ny form for tidslig bevidsthed for så vidt, at historien bliver tidslig, og det moderne sættes ind i en tidslig ramme med en fortid, nutid og fremtid (Koselleck 2004: 11). Hvis vi skal bestemme, hvordan moderniteten kan A r t e f a k t, m o d e r n i t e t siges at accelerere, danner denne tidslige bevidsthed en forudsætning for en sådan bestemmelse, ved at acceleration som strukturel dynamik kun er meningsfuld, hvis historiens varierende faser kan sammenlignes med fortidige eller fremtidige tilstande eller i en sociologisk kontekst, samfundsmæssige konfigurationer.4 Paul Virilios teori og problematisering af senmoderne samfundsstrukturer med afsæt i fartbegrebet og den teknologiske acceleration har ligesom Kosellecks teori haft stor indflydelse for senmoderne samfundsteorier og teknologikritik, der tager afsæt i tidslighed. Termen ’dromologi’, der betegner hastighedens logik, og forestillingen om dromologiske revolutioner, hvor produktionsprocesserne indtræder i en ny fase5, har desuden indvirket på kritiske perspektiver på teknologisk udvikling (Virilio 1986). Virilio forsøger i en teknologikritisk retning at problematisere den moderne fartsyge, og jeg vil derfor ikke bevæge mig nærmere ind i denne problematik. Det teoretiske greb, der er til stede her, er ligeledes baseret på accelerationens konsekvenser for samfundets forskellige strukturelle niveauer og er relevant i nærærende sammenhæng, fordi denne ansats anvendes af Rosa som teoretisk springbræt. Det væsentlige i sammenfatningen af accelerationen og modernitetsdynamikken hviler hos Rosa på en antagelse om, at accelerationen står i en bestemt relation til andre afledte sociale strukturer og dermed udgør et væsentligt element i samfundsmæssige transformationsprocesser: Det strukturalistiske træk ved Rosas bestemmelse af acceleration bliver her åbenbart, når det begrundes, hvorledes denne dynamik fungerer som fundamentalt socialt vilkår for samfundets subjekter og altså ikke differentieres på tværs af eksempelvis klasse. Her fremgår altså det, jeg vil betegne accelerationens social-ontologiske position, hvormed det understreges, at accelerationen udgør en mere fundamental, strukturel dynamik end eksempelvis andre sociale, økonomiske eller individorienterede strukturer, som subjekterne potentielt kan være ekskluderet fra på forskellig vis. Der opereres hos Rosa ud fra et tidsligt perspektiv, hvori den centrale dynamik for moderniteten bestemmes som accelererende. Som beskrevet har denne dynamik flere niveauer og står i en gensidigt afhængig relation til forskellige afledte samfundsdynamikker på flere niveauer. Dog er det endnu ikke klart, hvad begrebet i mere konkret forstand dækker, herunder eksempelvis i hvilken forstand forbindelsen mellem den teknologiske acceleration, artefaktet og subjektets oplevelse af tidsmangel skal forstås. I det følgende analyseres, hvordan accelerationen mere specifikt indvirker i forskellige sociale dimensioner, hvilket leder frem mod en klarlægning af dette i en modernitetskontekst. Side 41 If the main hypothesis of this work is that acceleration phenomena are fundamental to the cultural and structural development of modern society, it is not refuted by a demonstration that large groups within the population are excluded by the identified phenomena of acceleration because they are, say, unemployed, sick, without rights, or marginalized in some other way. Insofar as they are excluded from precisely those social spheres that are decisive for social development their importance for the structural and cultural transformation of society remains limited regardless of their quantity. (Rosa 2013a: 27) Side 42 Nis Langer Primdahl Accelerationens tre momenter Hartmut Rosa skelner mellem tre former for acceleration, en teknologisk, en samfundsmæssig og en individorienteret (Rosa 2009: 82). Den teknologiske accelerationsform er baseret på udviklingsdynamik, hvormed teknologiske artefakter og vores interaktion med disse udvikler sig. Som det både anføres hos Marx og Weber, så eskalerer udviklingshastigheden på både producerede varer og produktionsmidler ved industrialiseringens begyndelse, en udviklingstendens, der fortsætter op gennem moderniteten frem til nutidens telemedier, elbiler og høreapparater (Rosa 2013a: 71ff). Som Rosa beskriver: ”This is the form of acceleration that can be easily measured and demonstrated […]”, altså en form for acceleration kan der kvantificeres og således er direkte erfarbar; min bil kan køre hurtigere, mere stille og mere miljøvenligt end for 5 år siden, den nærmeste lufthavn kan håndtere flere fly med samme antal landingsbaner som tidligere etc. Teknikken er et redskab, der udvikler sig drevet af en bagvedliggende kapitalbaseret motor (Rosa 2013a: 49) Her lægger Rosa sig ligeledes i forlængelse af Marx og Weber, når den materielle, kapitalmotiverede udviklingsproces indsættes som et determinerende element i accelerationsbegrebet. Men Rosa er ikke blot teknologikritiker, og han ser i modsætning til andre teknologikritikere som Heidegger, Marcuse og Hylland Eriksen ikke accelerationsproblematikken som udelukkende funderet i teknikken. Teknikken er således ikke oprindelse til en lang række patologiske konsekvenser, men skal i lige så høj grad ses som et forsøg på at løse disse, eksempelvis har mange tekniske foranstaltninger en tidsbesparende funktion. Dette paradoks vender jeg tilbage til. Dermed defineres denne accelerationsform som ”the intentional acceleration of goaldirected processes” (Rosa 2013a: 74). Den anden form for acceleration betegner Rosa accelerationen af sociale forandringer (Rosa 2013a: 74). Denne accelerationsform henviser til hastigheden, hvormed organisationsmåden i samfundet ændrer sig. I relation til den teknologiske acceleration handler det om, hvor hurtigt teknologiske landvindinger implementeres i samfundet på et praktisk plan. Med henvisning til at det nutidige øjeblik, dvs. det tidsrum, der står til rådighed for sociale aktører til at udføre en handling lige nu, formindskes parallelt med accelerationen, definerer Rosa denne accelerationsform som determinerende i forhold til denne indsnævring (Rosa 2013a: 76). Den senmoderne vidensarbejder har mindre tid til at træffe det samme valg mellem de samme valgmuligheder end tidligere, og i den forstand sker indsnævringen af det øjeblik eller den begivenhed, inden for hvilken en social handling skal udføres både på et politisk, økonomisk og personligt plan. Der sker herved en reduktion i varigheden af de tidsperioder, der omgiver og bestemmer praksisser hos sociale aktører på både et individuelt og institutionelt plan: ”(…) social acceleration means that past and future must be rewritten in the various areas of society at even shorter intervals” (Rosa 2013a: 77). Den sociale acceleration forøger kravet om synkronisering mellem sociale aktører, hvilket danner bro til den tredje og sidste form for acceleration, accelerationen af hverdagslivet eller livstempoet [pace of life]. En sådan acceleration af hverdagslivet bygger på forestillingen om en indsnævring af nuet relation til subjekternes hverdagsliv. Ifølge Rosa finder en art tidslig intensivering af dagliglivet sted for det enkelte sub- A r t e f a k t, m o d e r n i t e t jekt, en intensivering, der besidder både en objektiv og en subjektiv side. På det objektive plan sker en afkortning af den tid, jeg som handlende subjekt bruger på en given handling; en indkøbstur tager kortere tid end for 30 år siden, min kalender har flere aftaler end mine forældres kalendere, da de selv var studerende, og jeg er i større grad end tidligere generationer i gang med flere aktiviteter på én gang – jeg ’multitasker’ (Rosa 2013a: 78). Since the heightening of the pace of life should be understood as a result of the scarcity of time resources, which means that the increase of the quantity of actions exceeds the technical enhancement of the speed of performance, subjectively it is expressed in the growing sense that one lacks time or is pressed for time and in a stressful compulsion to accelerate as well as in anxiety about ‘not keeping up’. The acceleration and condensation of action episodes then represents an obvious reaction to these perceptions. (Rosa 2013a: 79) Acceleration rises up from this regular and equable basis. Acceleration is constrained only by current technological capacity, technological levels of development and, importantly, the prevailing economic and political tangencies. Acceleration is an open-ended effect, but the clock remains the overall (and underlying) coordinating, organizing, rationalizing and scheduling principle. The clock generates the necessary uniformity, predictability and planning capacity without which a dynamic economic and productive system based on pure and unbridled competition would quickly degenerate into chaos and collapse. (Hassan 2009: 63) Som Hassan her pointerer, er accelerationsdynamikken i den klassiske modernitet baseret på uret. Den rationaliseringsproces som Weber opererer med samt idéen om arbejdsdelingen og den heraf afledte forøgelse af kompleksiteten, som vi finder Side 43 Som subjekter er vores hverdag i stigende grad præget af en erfaring af mangel på tid, der ikke nødvendigvis stemmer overens med et objektivt mål for dette.6 Denne oplevelse har patologiske konsekvenser (udbrændthed etc.), når den slår over i en tilstand, hvor fremtiden som mulighedsrum lukker sig.7 Det væsentlige er dog at de tre niveauer, hvor accelerationen gør sig gældende, betinger forståelsen og selvforståelsen for både samfundet på et makro-sociologisk plan og den personlige identitet på mikro-planet. Accelerationen på de tre niveauer indgår i det Rosa betegner som et accelerationskredsløb, der kan bestemmes som en form for positiv feedback-mekanisme, hvor de specifikke accelerationsdynamikker på hvert deres niveau understøtter hinanden (Rosa 2013b: 43ff). Eksempelvis fordrer accelerationen af hverdagslivet og det heraf stigende behov for rådighedstid, at vi anvender tekniske instrumenter (f.eks. opvaskemaskinen) til at spare tid. Den sociale acceleration gør, at den tidsmængde vi umiddelbart sparer ved disse redskaber i stedet bruges instrumentelt på arbejde eller selvoptimering. Man kan stille spørgsmålet om, hvordan disse ændringer i accelerationsstrukturerne kan sættes i relation til den klassiske modernitet og den standardiserede tidslighed, der opstår i den klassiske modernitet. Den klassiske modernitet implicerer ifølge Robert Hassan en form for acceleration, der er forskellig fra den form, der gør sig gældende i senmoderniteten: Nis Langer Primdahl Side 44 hos Durkheim, tematiseres her i henhold til accelerationsbegrebet. Standardiseringen af tiden vha. kalender og ure bliver således et redskab til at tøjle accelerationen, at ordne og at udnytte den. Institutionerne i den klassiske modernitet består og udvikler sig, fordi de er stand til skematisere den grundlæggende udviklingsdynamik. Dette viser sig på flere planer. På det institutionelle plan effektiveres de administrative processer ved hjælp af standardiseringen af eksempelvis sprog, tid og lovgivning, som på det individuelle plan knytter sig til både den rumlige og tidslige sondring mellem arbejdstid og fritid, der vinder frem ved det industrielle samfunds begyndelse indtil midten af det 20. århundrede (Rosa 2009: 103). Der er samtidig et skisma mellem orden, altså evnen til at kontrollere og bemægtige sig accelerationen og dens modsætning, den fleksibilitet, der gør det muligt for institutionerne at følge med tiden. Derved bærer accelerationen i sig selv en risiko for, at de afledte samfundsmæssige konfigurationer og udviklingstendenser ’ikke kan følge med’ og dermed bliver bremseklodser for accelerationen. Det afgørende er, ifølge Rosa, at der i accelerationen er en latent, iboende dialektisk spænding, som i den klassiske og sene modernitet manifesterer sig på forskellige måder, dvs. som en accelerationens dialektik. Rosa beskriver denne dobbelthed i accelerationen: (…) social acceleration always carries its own paradoxical countertendency within itself: social rigidity. Therefore the central question for an understanding of the statics and dynamics of modernity is how to conceive social acceleration and societal crystallization together on both cultural and structural levels. Only an analysis that is capable of giving an account of this can claim to do theoretical justice to the historical formation of modernity. (Rosa 2013a: 60ff) I den klassiske modernitet forekommer altså en spænding mellem rigide strukturer, eksempelvis organisationsstrukturer eller institutioner og en stadig differentiering eller udkrystallisering, der fordrer en høj grad af fleksibilitet. Og det er denne ramme, som det accelererende artefakt skal sættes ind i. Artefaktet som accelerator Artefaktet indgår som del i en dynamisk helhed og er tilstede på alle tre niveauer, der betinger den sociale acceleration. Rosa forsøger at besvare spørgsmålet om, hvorfor individet ender med mindre rådighedstid, når formålet med teknologien er at frigive mere tid til rådighed for individet. Eksempelvis er det at opgradere sin telefon forsøget på at forøge individets rådighedstid, sådan at jeg kan udføre en række handlinger, som jeg før var fem timer om, på to timer. I stedet ender jeg med at bruge telefonen i flere sammenhænge og dermed øge forbruget af den til seks timer. Dette paradoks, at artefaktet, her telefonen, reducerer individets tid i stedet for at frigive den, er velkendt. Men hvor Rosas udlægning, der indskriver artefaktet i en større helhed af accelerationsstrukturer, gør det muligt både at forklare, hvordan dette paradoks opstår, og hvorfor man ikke kan håbe på den løsning, som Hylland Eriksen taler for, altså at afsondre sig eller fraskrive sig brugen af disse tekniske hjælpemidler. Det væsentlige er her, at artefaktet er indlejret i så grundlæggende samfundsmæssige accelerationsstrukturer, at en afkobling af telefonen netop også vil medføre en afkobling fra samfundet som sådan. Tekniske gen- A r t e f a k t, m o d e r n i t e t senmoderne acceleration og giver eksempler på udveje og strategier til at undslippe samfundets fokus på forøgelse af hastigheden, hvilket kulminerer i det indledende diktum: “The logic of the cabin deserves to be globalized” (Eriksen 2001: 157). Den tilstand vi oplever i den isolerede fjeldhytte, altså en tilstand uden distraktioner og krav om fart, skal ifølge Hylland Eriksen udbredes til andre livssfærer. Spørgsmålet er dog om grænsen for det fleksible menneskes fleksibilitet, som også Sennett beskriver, kan sættes her? De senmoderne accelerationsstrukturer er tvingende på en måde, der umuliggør en flugt til hytten, og som Rosa også meget rigtigt påpeger, så ser vi et stort antal af disse coping-strategier, der mere eller mindre selv-terapeutisk forsøger at myndiggøre individet, sådan at det frit kan vælge, i hvor høj grad og hvornår, det ’deltager’ i accelerationen. Det langsommelige udgør på den måde ikke en modvægt til accelerationen, men fungerer snarere som ideologisk skinmulighed afledt af accelerationen, der foregiver, at ’slow-living’ er en reel valgmulighed for det senmoderne individ. Noter 1 Jf. desuden Marx 1971, Durkheim 1984, Heidegren 2014. 2 ”[…] that with the rise of bourgeois society the structure of time has changed drastically in the direction of higher complexity, then we must expect that this change will have its impact on every social structure and on every concept. Nothing will retain its old meaning.” (Luhmann 1976: 133-134) 3 Eksempelvis (Virilio 1986), (Heidegren 2014), (Adam 1990), (Castells 2000), (Nowotny 1994), (Harvey 1990), (Eriksen 2001) (Rosa 2013a)(Rosa 2013b) 4 Jf. desuden Rosa 2013a: 48 Side 45 stande og redskaber befinder sig i en form for lukket negativt feed-back-kredsløb, hvor den teknologiske dynamik, hvori nye objekter - f.eks. ure eller telefoner – frembringes, på den ene side bygger på et ønske om at bremse accelerationen og spare mere tid, men på den anden side ender med at forøge accelerationen af vores hverdagsliv. Man kan altså tale om den tekniske genstand som en form for ’accelererende artefakt’. Det fleksible menneske, som Sennett taler om, er således ikke mere fleksibelt, end at en frigørelse fra de genstande, der i stigende grad muliggør dette ’fleksible’ hverdagsliv, er umulig. Hvis man godtager at Rosas begreb om social acceleration og dette begrebs strukturelle betydning kan forklare, hvorfor en tro på udbredelsen af hyttens logik netop bygger på en reduktiv måde at anskue relationen mellem tekniske artefakter, modernitetsstrukturer og tid, melder spørgsmålet sig, om Rosas accelerationsbegreb i mere bred forstand kan tilskrives kritisk potentiale? Med sit begreb om acceleration inkorporerer Rosa det tidslige perspektiv som nøgleelement i sin generelle teori om samfundets udvikling i moderniteten. Det tidslige perspektiv besidder således umiddelbart stor forklaringskraft, idet forandringer i moderniteten, både på mikro- og makroplan kan forklares ved henvisning til denne grunddynamik. Derved vil jeg argumentere for, at indsættelse af det tekniske artefakt i en teoretisk helhed, baseret på ideen om social acceleration, underbygger og ekspliciterer det tidslige perspektiv på moderniteten på en sådan måde, at teoriens deskriptive gyldighed styrkes i forhold til Sennetts og Hylland Eriksens teorier. Særligt sidstnævnte teoretiker forsøger i sit værk om øjeblikkets tyranni at kritisere den Nis Langer Primdahl 5 Virilio anfører den industrielle revolution og den virtuelle revolution i det 20. årh. Se desuden Beniger 1986: 196ff for en uddybning af fartens betydning. 6 Se f.eks. Holt 2013 for empiriske studier i en dansk kontekst af denne erfaring af accelerationen. 7 Det står dog klart, at disse patologier indeholder et klart element af tidslighed, den stressede ’mangler tid’, ’fremtiden lukker sig’ for den deprimerede. Jf. Rosa 2013a: 214. Ligeledes kan den senmoderne optagethed af langsommelighed anskues som coping-strategier for subjekter i det accelererede samfund , f.eks. populariteten af aktiviteter som mindfulnes, ’slow-living’, retreats og yoga. Litteratur Side 46 Adam, Barbara (1990): Time and Social Theory, Temple University Press, Philadelphia Beniger, James (1986): The Control Revolution, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. Castells, Manuel (2000): The Rise of Network Society, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, Malden, Mass. Durkheim, Emilé (1984 [1893]): The Division of Society, Macmillan, London Elias, Norbert (2007): An Essay On Time, University College Dublin Press, Dublin Press Eriksen, Thomas Hylland (2001): Tyranny of the Moment: Fast and Slow Time in the Information Age, Pluto Press, London Giddens, Anthony (1990): The Consequences of Modernity, Stanford University Press, Stanford Gleick, James (1999): Faster: The Acceleration of just about everything, Pantheon Books, New York Habermas, Jürgen (1983): “Det Moderne – et ufuldendt projekt”, Det Moderne, Forlaget Modtryk Harvey, David (1990): The Condition of Postmodernity, Blackwell, Cambridge, Mass. Hassan, Robert (2009): Empires of Speed, Brill, Leiden Heidegren, Carl-Göran (2014): Tid – Sociologiska perspektiv, Liber, Stockholm Holt, Helle et al. (2013): Et arbejdsliv i acceleration – tiden og det grænseløse arbejde, Roskilde Universitetsforlag, Frederiksberg Koselleck, Reinhart (2004)[1979]: Futures Past, Columbia University Press, New York Koselleck, Reinhart (2009): “Is there an Acceleration of History?” i Rosa, H., High Speed Society: Social Acceleration, Power and Modernity, Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, Pa. Luhmann, Niklas (1976): “The Future Cannot Begin: Temporal Structures in Modern Society”, Social Research, nr. 1, årg. 43, spring 1976, 130-152, The New School, New York Luhmann, Niklas (1990): “Die Zukunft kann nicht beginnen. Temporalstrukturen der modernen Gesellschaft” i Slojterdijk, P., Vor der Jahrtausendwende: Berichte zur Lage der Zukunft, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main Marx, Karl (1971): The Grundrisse,Harper & Row, New York Nowotny, Helga (1994): Time – the Modern and Postmodern Experience, Blackwell, Cambridge Rosa, Hartmut (2009): “Social Acceleration: Ethical and Political Consequences of a Desynchronized High-Speed Society” i High Speed Society: Social Acceleration, Power and Modernity, Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, Pa. Rosa, Hartmut (2013a): Social acceleration: A New Theory of Modernity, Columbia University Press, New York Rosa, Hartmut (2013b): Beschleunigung und Entfremdung: Entwurf einer Kritischen Theorie spätmoderner Zeitlichkeit, Suhrkamp, Berlin Sennett, Richard (1999): Det fleksible menneske eller arbejdets forvandling og personlighedens nedsmeltning, Hovedland, Højbjerg Tomlinson, John (2007): The Culture of Speed: The Coming of Immediacy, SAGE, Los Angeles: Virilio, Paul (1986): Speed and Politics: An Essay on Dromology, Columbia University, New York Weber, Max (1995): Den protestantiske etik og kapitalismens ånd, Nansensgade Antikvariat, København Natalia Hoffman The Suckling Tree In the following article I discuss the ritual of rite of passage, and more specifically, I consider the peculiar Danish phenomenon of hanging children’s pacifiers on trees. Taking a semiotic perspective presently enriched by the anthropologist’s Arnold van Gennep’s theories of rites of passage; I focus on the symbolic dimension of pacifiers as ritualsanctioning artefacts. ties, which are performed in a sequestered place, in a particular situation and with adherence to specific, typically rigid rules and manner.1 Rituals arise and wither, yet, despite obvious differences across cultures and times, they constitute an invariably common feature of all known human societies, past and present. This in turn indicates some intrinsic need for ritualization and symbolic actions. And although their investigation through the lens of evolutionary and cognitive sciences is beyond the scope of this paper, it is noteworthy that the scientific advances of the last decade have shifted the point of inquiry towards uncovering how rituals become impacted, shaped and conditioned by human biology and environment. The scope of consideration has thus expanded beyond cultural evolution alone in an effort to bridge the gap between social, cognitive and biolo- S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 4 7 - 5 2 The connection between artefacts and rituals is easy to draw, if only for the fact that many rituals depend on artefacts for their enactment and execution – with items becoming enhanced with symbolic (often sacred) signification in the course of the ceremony. From this perspective an opportunity for novel semiotic analysis arises every time specific objects become chosen and appropriated by a community, assigned a function in a ritual’s performance and granted symbolic dimension. There are hardly any limits to the kind of artefacts that can be incorporated into ceremonial practices. So is the case with rituals at large – there seems to be no constraint to the form they take, the purpose they serve nor to benefits they offer to the participant. In a scholarly attempt at their systematization, rituals have been tentatively held to encompass sequences of activi- Natalia Hoffman gical approaches to human existence. A fully integrated formal approach is yet to be developed, while behind the walls of the Academia, collective life follows its own independent rhythm. In the city where I live, in the forest I cycle through, grows a suckling tree (Danish: suttetræ). At its core, the suckling tree is just like any other tree, and indeed more than one sapling has in time borne that title. But on the outside, what distinguishes it from the surrounding forest is the mere presence and the sheer number of pacifiers that embellish its branches, as if they were leaves of the non-deciduous kind. Side 48 (Picture taken by N. Hoffman, November 2013) New pacifiers sprout up every time a local kid learns how to curb his or her sucking reflex. At that point, the family ventures to dispose of pacifiers by hanging them on the lower branches of the suckling tree. Sometimes whole bags full of them are hung, often with a damp personal letter included. It is noteworthy, that rather than chucking the pacifiers away together with other kinds of unnecessary garbage the families should choose to make such an effort and statement. By extension, instead of having this plastic and rubber decompose somewhere in the deep sea or inconspicuously poison the earth elsewhere; it becomes quite proudly incorporated into a natural setting. From a semiotic perspective, two things seem to be at play here. Firstly, the perseverance of this phenomenon grants insight into the forming of, and indeed the need for, ritualized actions. The suckling tree marks a rite of passage. Like any other rite of passage ritual, the hanging of pacifiers signifies a transition in a person’s life; here a transition from toddler to more fully fledged human who can control his or her reflexes. Ancient Israel had a beautiful custom;2 every time a child was born, a tree was planted to honour and commemorate the event and to bear witness to the growth of life. But modern life forgoes such customs as city-dwelling makes planting of trees (and carrying out of any other ceremonies that would endorse nature at its raw) impractical for most people. So what better way to reflect on and follow the development of a personhood than to occasionally venture back to the suckling tree, marvel at how much it has grown, and try to spot a once-familiar pacifier amongst the many that have been attached to the tree in recent years. It is not unlikely, that having others hang their children’s pacifiers on the same tree can foster an expansive feeling of belonging to a community of like-minded urbanites. It may also reassure one that delighting in public displays of your child’s develop- The Suckling Tree detach oneself from the fixed point in the social structure – e.g. shaving off hair upon joining the army), liminal rites (or ‘rites of transition’ which presuppose a stage of ambiguity, where the very structure of one’s personhood and social standing are temporarily suspended; one’s sense of identity dissolves to some extent, bringing about disorientation but also new perspectives – e.g. during civil uprising), postliminal rites (otherwise described as ‘rites of incorporation’ which mark either reversion to the old order upon failed transition - e.g. newly released jailbirds return to prison, or else incorporation into a new, presumably more advanced social group).5 Although this three-fold structure of rituals differs across cultures in manner of execution, it was thought by van Gennep to form a pattern inherent to all ritual passages, and as such – universal. It is noteworthy that by suggesting the universality of the tripartite sequence (and of rites of passage at large), van Gennep made a bold claim – one that not many anthropologists make, as they tend to expose cultural diversity, while shying away from universality. The phenomenon of the suckling tree concedes with van Gennep’s observations of rites of passage and their structure in every single aspect. It requires a child to leave the old habit behind in a symbolic action of parting with the pacifier, it involves the stage of passing through a threshold – where the child masters this new type of maturity while the reversal to suckling reflexes is discouraged by the parents who act as authority and masters of ceremony, it ultimately awards the child a place in a social group with more refined habits. In other words, hanging pacifiers on trees becomes a link in some transition phase. Although peculiar (and arguably exaggerated for what it boils Side 49 ment is as normal as it gets. On the other hand, this imagined community that the tree represents can conveniently be referred to in conversations encouraging the child to give up the pacifier. (“When you’re a big boy/big girl and don’t need a pacifier anymore, we can hang yours on the tree.”) It’s conceivable that the parent would typically try to involve the child in the drafting of a parting letter and in hanging of the pacifier – in this manner avowing the riteof-passage-dimension of the deed. These letters would no doubt reveal more of the parents’ projected feelings than the child’s – while the departed beloved one is but a bit of rubberized maternal connection, and the loss voluntary, probably the loss is no less real, even occasionally traumatic.3 The concept of rite of passage taps into the general theory of socialization (formed at the beginning of the last century by the anthropologist Arnold van Gennep) and refers to the milestones in an individual’s life when one’s social status is altered. Van Gennep’s analysis of ritual behaviours in relation to the dynamics between individual and group life brought him considerable fame in anthropological circles, his theoretical formulations, however, have failed to reach other branches of social sciences. I will here briefly introduce van Gennep’s observations, for I find them enlightening and their application to semiotics of the suckling tree – fairly obvious. According to van Gennep, rites of passage, which mark, guide or celebrate individual or collective transitions in the cycle of life and nature, are common to every culture and share a specific tripartite sequence.4 It consists of preliminal rites (or ‘rites of separation’ – whereby a person carries out symbolic behaviours in order to renounce the current social status and Side 50 Natalia Hoffman down to), this ritual and the conspicuousness of its execution facilitates the understanding, supports the change and marks the recognition of a child’s development. In the semiotic microclimate of the suckling tree, the symbolic action tied to the ceremony is the most gratifying to investigate. The meaning of pacifiers as artefacts extends beyond the items’ practical use as a result of literally removing pacifiers from their prescribed context and placing them in a hugely incongruous setting: a tree – and comes to connote the tender relationship between parent and child, the pride connected to a healthy maturing of one’s offspring, and for the child the idea of a certain achievement. The sight of families conspicuously tying these objects to the branches af the trees, or the sight of them already hung there, cannot possibly be mistaken for an ordinary or mundane occurrence. It becomes clear that as the pacifiers stand for something else, they take on the function of a metaphor; they serve to explain and illustrate the somewhat abstract and difficult-to-grasp notion of the passage of time in more familiar and tangible terms. At the same time, the suckling tree itself not only serves as an emblem of growing up, but it also acquires a mythical dimension. It brings to mind the primal sacrifice of the breast, of the action of sucking in order to obtain the life-sustaining nutrients. In this way, the tree embellished with pacifiers resembling leaves, buds or fruits, symbolizes the source of weaned nourishments, which the child no longer depends on for survival (for the transition from dependence to autonomy has been accomplished). Van Gennep formed his theories over a century ago. In the light of the suckling tree ritual corresponding them so perfectly, it is noteworthy that this variant of rite of passage is relatively recent and scholastically unexplored. There are almost no articles on the topic. One dictionary states that the word ‘suttetræ’ came into popular use in the 90s,6 another source reports the practice originated thirty years ago.7 Admittedly, it might not be a long time for a ritual to fully crystalize and acquire a status of ‘tradition’, however its widespread character (spanning all major Danish cities) suggests that hanging pacifiers on trees has become a cherished custom. Additionally, it appears to be unique to Denmark – I have not seen or heard of such practice anywhere else in the world and my extended research in this area has been to no avail. Given van Gennep’s assertions about the universality of similar ceremonies, it is also interesting to note that the need for discussed here ritualised/symbolic action is so strong, that no amount of resistance on the side of vandals can suppress it. Indeed, the moment one suckling tree gets knocked over or cut down;8 another one springs in its place. Well, not quite springs – a tree right next to it gets assigned by eager parents to bear the weight and the meaning of the pacifiers. As a consequence, a reigning suckling tree stands surrounded by toppled trunks of fading significance.9 And so the second issue of semiotic analysis concerns the role these trees play in urban landscape and design. The status of a suckling tree as living sculpture is reflected in ditto peculiar collective and amateur design, wherein new elements are continually added, sustaining its validity. It is quite remarkable that although a tree embellished with pacifiers shows a complex even perplexing interplay between form and meaning – its function and use are plainly communicated and readily graspable. To be certain, the phenomenon The Suckling Tree Notes 1 Merriam-Webster dictionary for the entry “ritual” 2 Cohen, online 3 It bears mentioning that in laboratory experiments conducted by Aronson and Mills (1959) severe inductions have been reported to trigger in initiates the state of cognitive dissonance (psychological discomfort caused by simultaneously holding conflicting beliefs, ideas, or values), which in turn reinforced their commitment to the rite of passage and strengthen the appeal of the group they had just joined. This has not been the case for participants who underwent a mild to no initiation in joining a group. In other words, upon experiencing cognitive dissonance, one is compelled to reduce it and regain internal consistency by finding justification for the compliance with the unpleasantness of the initiation and the effort exerted to gain admission to the new social group. Conceivably, in a child’s eyes, the somewhat demanding and displeasing parting with a pacifier will cause distress but also contentment (further encouraged by the parent) at personal achievement. To resolve this emotional disparity, children could either downplay the unpleasantness of the initiation or raise the value of the decision to give up on a pacifier. In consequence, this ritual might just boost the will to further act in accordance with the decision already taken, as to stay satisfied with the deed. 4 van Gennep, 1961 5 ibid 6 in Den Danske Ordbog: Modern Dansk Sprog, online 7 in Danmarks Naturfredningsforening, online 8 Glasius for Jyllands-Posten Aarhus, online 9 It would likely prove revealing to investigate how the relationship between Danish parents and their toddlers differ from corresponding relationships in other Western countries (if at all) as to result in this particular phenomenon. Bibliography Bell, Catherine (1997): Ritual: Perspectives and Dimensions, Oxford University Press Cohen, Treasure for Ritualwell: Tradition and Innovation, Tree-Planting Ritual, http://www.ritualwell. org/ritual/tree-planting-ritual Revised 20-10-2014 Danmarks Naturfredningsforening, Træer fortæller historier, http://www.dn.dk/Default.aspx?ID=8733 Revised 20-10-2014 Side 51 of a suckling tree would not be endorsed and cherished, if the symbolism and the metaphorical bearing which sanction its existence were not easily comprehensible or conceptually justifiable. The success of the suckling tree’s spontaneous (and spreading across the country) design lies then in its straightforward appeal and general accessibility – it is for everybody to use and for everybody to partake in constructing by simply imitating what others have done. At last, given that pacifiers serve as a metaphor for both the passage of time (on a conceptual level), but also the tree’s leaves etc. (on an aesthetic level), it is understandable that people tend to distribute the pacifiers evenly on the branches (as if those indeed were leaves, buds or fruits). It can be argued that people crave balance and symmetry in general, but it must also be recognized that this craving is intrinsically linked to our perceptual experience of symmetry in the natural world – by extension of trees having evenly distributed leafage etc. On a final note, the very nature of the suckling tree sanctions the issue of saliva itself – the residue lingering on pacifiers, lending the suckling tree its nickname of a ‘saliva tree’. To be frank, every time I cycle by it, I get slightly disgusted and almost wish the vandals succeeded in abolishing this urban ritual once and for all. To me (who don’t have any children) the choice of pacifiers as a symbolic object – as opposed to, say, a rattle – cannot be detached from the thought of saliva and the troublesome fact that once the saliva gets out our mouths, it becomes estranged and alien – few of us would ever welcome it back. But perhaps this is precisely where the strength of this semiotic system lies; once the rite of passage has been marked – there is no turning back and we have something to remind us of it. Natalia Hoffman Side 52 Den Danske Ordbog: Modern Dansk Sprog http:// ordnet.dk/ddo/ordbog?query=suttetræ Revised 20-10-2014 Glasius, Maria Juel for Jyllands-Posten Aarhus, Børnenes suttetræer er fældet, http://jyllands-posten. dk/aarhus/politiretsvaesen/ECE4683850/boerne- nes-suttetraeer-er-faeldet/ Published 01-05-2012. Revised 20-10-2014 Merriam-Webster Dictionary http://www.merriamwebster.com/dictionary/ritual Revised 20-10-2014 Van Gennep, Arnold (1961): The Rites of Passage, University of Chicago Alessandro Miani Musical beings: is music an artefact? Do we have musicality, or are we musical? To what extent is music an artefact and how much does it shape us? It is suggested that our first musical experience is in the mother’s womb, that we result from an accurate selection by ancestral women towards ’musicians’, and that music affects our brain, cognition and mood. It will be concluded that the inseparability of humans from music makes us musical beings. Introduction Music is: This statement reached such an impressive amount of – reasonable – quotes that now is a praxis quoting him to start a paper on music. One can argue that even if music was a cheesecake, then it should be noted that sugar has an important rewarding value, which also “solve[s] the adaptive problems of survival and reproduction” (Kanazawa 2001: 1143). Philip Tagg (2014) estimated that our daily dose of music is about 4 hours. Still, if music is not important for our life, then, why do we spend so much time listening to it? S e m i k o l o n ; n r. 2 8 , å r g . 1 5 , 2 0 1 5 ; s . 5 3 - 6 2 [...] auditory cheesecake, an exquisite confection crafted to tickle the sensitive spots of at least six of our mental faculties. [...] As far as biological cause and effect are concerned, music is useless. (Pinker 1997: 528-534) Taking apart cheesecakes, music has an unquestionable value in human life: for example, the Pirahã culture, whereby language does not consider numbers, colours, and even recursive mechanisms (Everett 2005), does have music (Patel 2008). However, it is shocking for me that in more than 700 pages regarding human evolution, culture, and emergence of language, Tomasello (1999; 2008; 2014) never mentioned music. Thus, by reviewing some studies on the role of music in our life and the potentiality to shape our biology, I will raise the following, perhaps provocative question: to what extent is music a human artefact and how musical are humans? Who made what and what made whom? And lastly, do we have musicality, or are we musical being? By taking phylogenetic, cultural, and ontogenetic perspectives, in the first part it will be addressed the issue of “music made by humans”, namely, music as a trivial but Alessandro Miani Side 54 ancient artefact and its role in sexual selection. The issue of being selected for musical abilities paves the way for the second part, that is, the “humans made by music” argument, which concerns the music’s property to affect the brain, cognition, and mood. Music made by humans Trivial but ancient Steinbeis and Koelsch (2009) presented atonal musical sequences to subjects with the cues that the music was either written by a composer or generated by a computer. Results revealed that the cortical network for mental state attribution – the anterior medial frontal cortex – was activated solely when the music was supposed to be written by a composer. Paraphrased in an aesthetic fashion, such results indicate what music is: music is above all a man-made activity. However, music is an activity that does not serve direct useful purposes (see e.g. Goodman 1968). Although the Kantian idea of art fits well the aesthetic needs in attempting to grasp the ineffable, it raises – one more time – an obvious dilemma: why do we do art if we do not need it? On the lack of direct and evident gains obtained by music, John Sloboda (1985) proposed a parallel with sex: an individual can clearly live without sex, but what then about the entire species? Well, if nobody mates, then species would obviously disappear. With no doubt music is not as crucial for species as sex is, yet music is a pervasive activity: in fact, although having few universals – mostly related to psycho/biological constraints (there is a wide literature, see e.g. Brown & Jordania 2011), – music itself is a universal activity among humans, and is traced across all cultures in the world. Music is an artefact. Evolutionary speaking, it appears that there is a strong connection between human’s bipedalism and artefacts. Scientists (Mithen 2005: 144 and references therein) assert that bipedalism emerged in two stages: firstly, as a consequence of the frugivorous diet, it permitted them to use both hands in searching for fruits; secondly, as a consequence of the climatic changes in the African savannah, it forced them to “stay tall and stay cool”. Bipedalism triggered intelligence and language, which resulted from the new sensorimotor demands due to the more unstable center of gravity. It follows that the larger brain could have been used for other complex tasks, and the enhanced sensorimotor control entailed a better dexterity for tool-making, which, in turn, contributes to the expansion of the cerebral cortex (Stout et al. 2008). Evidence shows that at least 2.5 million years ago (Mya) hominids used to produce tools from broken animal bones and accurately select stones (Semaw et al. 2003); this remained the finest human technology until the hand-axes appeared 1.4 Mya. Yet, it is surprising that those butchering artefacts show a high degree of symmetry. Hence, Kohn and Mithen (1999; Mithen 2005) proposed the “sexy hand-axe hypothesis”: females were attracted by such tools because tool-making is a reliable indicator of cognitive, behavioral and physiological traits, therefore an index of reproductive success. Cues of ornamental objects (painted shells) are dated 82,000 years BP (Bouzouggar et al. 2007), while the discovery of abstract representations (on pieces of ochre) appeared at least 70,000 years BP (Henshilwood et al. 2002). These archeological records are important in the way they attest the emergence of the symbolic thought and so the music- and language-ready brain. Although it still nowadays to understand whether the music or language emerged Musical beings before or simultaneously (Cross et al 2013; Brown 2000), it has been advanced that music preceded the artistic tools (Mithen 2005) even though musical artefacts appeared relatively late – voice does not fossilize (!). The unearthing of a well-preserved bone flute (Conard et al. 2009), which undoubtedly is not a “hyena’s lunch”, and a mammoth-ivory Venus (Conard 2009) attested that at least 35,000 years BP music and figurative art were already habitual practices among modern humans. Moreover, Cross and colleagues (2002) attested that lithophones were in use at least 40,000 years BP. Again, music is apparently useless, but ubiquitous and very ancient; so, what was music for? he did have sexual liaisons with hundreds of groupies, maintained parallel long-term relationships with at least two women, and fathered at least three children in the U.S., Germany, and Sweden. (Miller 2000) Consistently, the peak of music-interest during life-span is reached in young adulthood, during the period of most intense courtship (Miller 2000), and an analysis conducted on Facebook revealed that a man who holds a guitar in the Side 55 Sexual Selection Since Darwin, pages have been written on songbird’s courtships and peacock’s tails; with particular emphasis, the latter has been the most representative and quoted case. The peacock’s tail is an honest signal, the best tail reflects the best partner to have offspring with (Miller 2000): its size requires a certain degree of physical effort, and the best plumage mirrors the well-being of the bird. However, its colours make the bird extremely noticeable for predators. Females, are picky because the costs of reproduction is higher for them than for males and they have less chances to produce offspring than the counterpart, they are attracted by these “useless” ornements since the energy the peacock spends to keep its tail healthy is an index of well-being for the reason that there are energies to be spent on luxury “items”. Similarly, in the contemporary society, elaborated houses and hundred-thousand-dollar cars display the faculty of having so much food and resources that permit a male to waste them on useless items (Levitin 2006), resembling the “giant” (30 cm) hand-axes which clearly could not have been used for butchering (Mithen 2005). About music, Mithen (2005) is one of the proposers for the music-as-sexual-selector hypothesis, arguing that (synchronised) vocalisations had a twofold value for female interests: on the one hand, the loudness of the calls is an indicator of abundance of males and so it does also for resources; on the other hand, synchronisation is related to cooperation, hence a display of certain cognitive abilities. Music making and creative behaviour in general, is an indicator of good genes: in a study conducted by Haselton and Miller (2006), women at different menstrual stages have been asked to rate attractiveness of men who could be either creative but poor or uncreative but rich. Results have shown that at their peak of fertility women chose the creative man for a short-term mate. Levitin (2006: 249) reports that “women want to sleep with rock stars and athletes than to marry them” indicating that a creative man is good as a genes provider, but the good dad is who can economically afford child rearing. In this regard, it is emblematic the case of Jimi Hendrix: Alessandro Miani photo profile is perceived as more attractive than who does not (Tifferet et al. 2012). However, there have been also taken opponent positions: the human’s potential ability to sing shows an egalitarian distribution pattern, and for every Bach with many children there may be a Beethoven who died childless, and for every popular conductor or lead guitarist there may be a lonely oboist or bassist. (Fitch 2006: 201) Side 56 In addition, Fitch remarks that the malebiased instrumental orchestras are more a cultural phenomenon rather than a biological constraints, which can explain the 10:1 ratio between albums published by men compared to those of women (Miller 2000). Humans made by music Phylogeny, culture, and ontogeny As birds have wings and they can fly, so humans have a language- and music-ready brain (Arbib & Iriki 2013) and they can speak and sing; birds have been sexually selected for flight, while humans have been sexually selected for language and music. The gene FOXP2 is in a certain way responsible for language as it is a component of the vocal learning ability (Fitch & Jarvis 2013), namely, the capacity to learn vocalisations which are not innate. This is possible by creating a neural pathway between the auditory and the motor regions involving the basal ganglia, a structure responsible for motor control and sequencing (Patel 2008) as well as for processing temporal patterns in both language and music (Grahn 2012). Another condition for the appearance of music and language is the mirror system, which is a set of neurons (area F5 in monkeys and Broca’s area in humans) activated both during observation and execution of manual actions; they are supposed to play a role in both language (Arbib 2005) and music (Fritz & Koelsch comment in Juslin & Västfjäll 2008). Anatomically speaking, the lowering of the larynx – as a consequence of bipedalism — permitted a wider array of sounds, which, with enhanced sensorimotor system, enabled humans to produce finer-grained vocalisations (Aiello 1996). Interestingly, DNA analysis has shown that Neanderthals shared with us a variant of the FOXP2 gene (Krause et al 2007), so they also were potentially speakers (Dediu & Levinson 2013) and able to manage abstract thought (Rodriguez-Vidal et al. 2014). Yet, why did Neanderthals disappear? It may be supposed that they had not the developed capacity for culture as modern humans did. It has been suggested, for example, that a complex social environment pushed the expansion of the neocortex, since it is required to think about reputation, social roles and absent people (Gowlett et al. 2012). Such increase in size permitted an enhanced capacity for managing symbols and social interactions, hence the cumulative cultural evolution, namely, the effect by which a technology is being improved without stepping back, through imitation and innovation, due to a faithful social transmission (Tomasello 1999). Interestingly, environmental information, like a traumatic odour exposure, is carried through genetic heritage to offspring (Dias & Ressler 2014); its significance is that behaviour can be genetically transmitted, in other words, culture may affect biology. In this regard, the “neuronal recycling hypothesis” (Dehaene & Cohen 2007) states that a recent technology (e.g., reading or mathematics), too recent to be Musical beings Short- and long-term effects of music Once born, babies are still very attracted by their mother’s voice: singing to infants optimises their mood, induces sleep by entering in a trance-like state and contributes to his or her general well-being (Trehub 2003a); this is a universal phenomenon (Trehub 2003b). Roy and collaborators (2012) linked the soothing effect of music to an analgesic one. Their findings shown that pleasant-relaxing music reduces pain perception by inducing positive emotions, concluding that music has a strong influence on pain. Another study shows that music also affects the consumption of sedative. Koelsch and colleagues (2011) asked patients who had to receive a regional anaesthesia to listen to musical stimuli two hours before the surgery; the same music should have been played again during the surgery. Results demonstrated that listening to music induces less stress and less need for sedation. Music is also great to enhance cognitive recovery after a stroke. In Särkämö and collaborators research (2008), patients who had a left or right hemisphere stroke were split in three groups and asked to listen to linguistic or musical stimuli for at least one hour a day. Results revealed that after three months the music group reported far better performances in terms of verbal memory and focused attention than the language one and experienced less depressed and confused mood. Listening to Mozart’s music would enhance spatial and cognitive abilities (Rauscher et al. 1993). Despite the appealing “Mozart Effect”, it has been found difficult to replicate (Chabris 1999), and it appears depending more on mood and arousal rather than to his music (Thompson et al. 2001), it is now recognised that long-term musical training has beneficial Side 57 involved in evolutionary process, involves the cortex entailing a structural and functional modification that invades older brain circuits – viz., how nurture shapes nature. Ontogenetically, we are born already musicalised. Music is a reflection of what happened in the womb. Human sensitivity to melody and rhythm is a consequence of prenatal exposure to the mother’s voice, heartbeat, and footsteps (Parncutt 1989: 50 and references therein), which create the structured musical habitat. Voice, because of the rhythmic pattern and frequency range, is the prenatal counterpart of the postnatal melody: like the musical passages, speech is often interrupted by breath, while intonation provides melodic contour. In the womb, speech occupies the highest frequency spectrum and is rhythmically irregular, compared to heartbeat and footsteps, which, in turn, provide the rhythmic stability for the intrauterine music. These elements, in addition to the rhythmic regularity, have the peculiarity of occupying the lowest part of the frequency spectrum as the rhythmic section does in many musical cultures. Noteworthy, the rhythmic pattern of footsteps may bias the postnatal beat perception: as a matter of fact, due to the asymmetrical position of the foetus, one mother’s foot is heard louder than the other. Given such a rich and structured musical environment, it is not surprising to find that from the 29th week of gestation foetus exposure to music can have long-term plastic changes on the developing brain, reflected by a great ERP activity that correlates with the amount of time spent listening to music (Partaken et al. 2013). Side 58 Alessandro Miani effects on human brain. Neuroanatomically speaking, professional musicians have a bigger volume of grey matter (up to 3%) compared to that of non-musicians, especially in motor, auditory and visualspatial regions (Gaser & Schlaug 2003). That is because throughout their musical life, they are constantly involved in translating from visual-spatial to motor domain receiving auditory feedback. They also have a bigger corpus callosum (Schlaug et al. 1995; Ozturk et al. 2002), which entails a better inter-hemispheric communication and this can be manipulated by only fifteen months of musical practice also in six-yearold children (Hyde et al. 2009). The brain, however, is not only anatomically rearranged, but also functionally, involving, as expected, auditory functions. Such issue has been reviewed by Kraus and Chandrasekaran (2010). In general, musical training does not entail an overall gain effect; rather, it does selective enhancements. For example, musicians are better to represent meaning from an auditory input: in verbal domain, American amateur musicians were better than non-musicians in learning a Mandarine-like tonal language (Wong & Perrachione 2007); musically-trained children have shown stronger electrophysiological response to incongruent sounds in respect to their native language (Besson et al. 2007), they also have better verbal abilities, motor skills, and nonverbal reasoning (Forgeard et al. 2008). Moreover, despite the effects are being small, duration of musical training during childhood correlates positively with IQ and academic achievements, and, importantly, such improvements are not limited to a specific set of cognitive abilities and are more generally extendable (Schellenberg 2004; 2006). Music and mood There is no need to read a paper to understand that music induces emotional states (Westermann et al. 1996). The salience of the music/emotion couple is evident by the amount of topics published in the Music Perception Journal: indeed, a meta-analysis revealed that emotions were a quasi-pervasive topic (Tirovolas & Levitin 2011). The emotional power conveyed by music lies on the fact that emotions are deeply rooted in music as a – supposed – consequence of phylogenetic development from apes’ vocalisations. Emotional empathy underlying music exceeds the cultural boundaries. In this regard, Patel (2008) glorified the magnificent and paradoxical power of music whereby, though there is the assumed referential meaning, it can be understood and appreciated by people who speak different languages. As a matter of fact, when music chills – i.e., when is pleasurable –, is accompanied by different physiological reactions and engages the same brain regions [...] involved in reward/motivation, emotion, and arousal [which are usually activated] in response to other euphoriainducing stimuli, such as food, sex, and drugs of abuse [...] (Blood & Zatorre, 2001: 11818) and cheesecakes. This powerful and prelexical capacity to universally communicate emotions brings humans to the pre-linguistic stage because emotions are processed in the “old brain” , bypassing cultural aspects; hence they are universally understood for the reason that they are universally expressed in the same way (Fritz et al. 2009). Finally, Steven Mithen maintains that happiness correlates with helpfulness and cooperation-- happy people tend to Musical beings evaluate others more positively and think more creatively; he then concluded: how good it would be if one were always surrounded by happy people – and if they were no happy on their own account, how nice it would be to induce a little happiness into their lives, perhaps by singing them a happy song. (Mithen 2005: 99) Conclusions Following the “romantic” vein adopted by Mithen (2005), conclusions are as strong – though opposed – as Pinker’s statement: we are made of music. The womb is the first musical “ensemble” we experience, which in a natural way forges perception and the way we make music; plausible is the idea that musicality had played a role in sexual selection and is still doing so nowadays; it has positive short- and longterm effects on the brain and is also able to modulate pain; lastly, happy music may contribute to create “a better world” made of helpful and cooperative people. The “music-made humans” statement resonates in some respects with the example provided by David Chalmers’ foreword to Supersizing the Mind by Andy Clark: Here, I would like to emphasise a parallel with music. In Clark’s view (2011), language is an extension of thought, here, Side 59 The iPhone has already taken over some of the central functions of my brain. It has replaced part of my memory […], it harbors my desires, […] I use it to calculate […], I make plans […], I even daydream on the iPhone […]. My iPhone is not my tool, or at least it is not wholly my tool. Parts of it have become parts of me. (Clark 2011: ix-x). music is an extension of emotions; both are part of us serving different needs: referencing and expressing. Fortunately, music and language are more and more often considered as two sides of a unique phenomenon which considers definite meanings on one side and affective potency on the other (e.g., Cross et al. 2013; Koelsch 2011), not even to mention the neuroanatomical overlaps between the two (e.g., Maess et al. 2001; Patel 2003). Are these two sides of the same human being-ness? If the lack of language is dreadful, then what about music? The consequences of language deprivation are clear, as the (in)famous case of Genie revealed, while examples of music deprivation have not been reported – at least in humans. Again, as for language, the only possible way to measure the effects of lack of music would be preventing people from listening to it, which undoubtedly entails social isolation and heavy repercussions on an individual’s well-being. Given our anatomical equipment, we have evolved for language and music, as birds have done for flight. Therefore, separating humans from music is tantamount to prohibiting birds from flying. In this regard, it is due to quote Alba, a woman who lost her legs in a car accident: “How much of your body can you lose and still recognise yourself?” (Peter Greenaway, A Zed and Two Noughts, 1985) How much humans we are still without music? If cutting wings prevent birds from flying, which part of the human body should be suppressed to prevent musicality? And lastly, given such inseparability, are we just musical or we are musical beings? Levitin (2012) notes that being musical human beings requires many skills such as reading, remembering, listening to, and playing music. Yet, these should be fractioned in many sub-skills: someone is good as Alessandro Miani soloist while another as accompanists; there are composers, performers and improvisers; there is also some who focalises on rhythm and some on pitch, and finally, some is more sensitive than others. What are, then, the requisites for being a musical being? To be a healthy musical being is required to spend some time in the uterus, having the apt neural equipment, and experiencing chills when a pleasurable music is played. In other words, “being a human being” and “being a musical being” are interchangeable. Concluding with the Pinker’s cheesecake, we are not a mere sugar-free surviving animals, but living animals, and music, like sugar and fat, is an important constituent of our being musical beings. Side 60 References Aiello, L.C. (1996). “Terrestriality, bipedalism and the origin of language”. Proceedings of the British Academy, 88:269-289. Arbib M.A (2005). “From monkey-like action recognition to human language: an evolutionary framework for neurolinguistics”. Behav. Brain Sci. 28, 105–168. Arbib, M.A. & Iriki, A. (2013). “Evolving the language- and music-ready brain”. In Language, Music, and the Brain (ed. Michael A. Arbib), Strüngmann Forum Reports, vol. 10, J. Lupp, series ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Besson, M., Schon, D., Moreno, S., Santos, A. & Magne, C. (2007). “Influence of musical expertise and musical training on pitch processing in music and language”. Restor. Neurol. Neurosci. 25, 399–410. Blood, A.J. & Zatorre, R.J. (2001). “Intensely pleasurable responses to music correlate with activity in brain regions implicated in reward and emotion”. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 98(20): 11818-11823. Bouzouggar, A. Barton, N. Vanhaeren, M. d’Errico, F. Collcutt, S. et al. (2007). “82,000-year-old shell beads from North Africa and implications for the origins of modern human behavior”. In Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104(24), pp:9964-9969. Brown, S. & Jordania, J. (2011). “Universals in the World’s Musics”. Psychology of Music, 41(2): 229–48. Brown, S.W. (2000). “The “musilanguage” model of music evolution”. In: The origins of music, (ed.) N. L. Wallin, B. Merker & S. W. Brown, pp. 271–300. MIT Press. Chabris, C.F. (1999). “Prelude or requiem for the “Mozart effect”?” Nature, 400, 826-828. Clark, A. (2011). Supersizing the mind: Action, embodiment, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press. Conard, N.J., Malina, M. & Munzel S.C. (2009). “New flutes document the earliest musical tradition in southwestern Germany”. Nature, 460, 737-740. Cross, I., Fitch, T., Aboitiz, F., Iriki, A., Jarvis, E.D. et al. (2013). “Culture and Evolution”. In Language, Music, and the Brain (ed. Michael A. Arbib) Strüngmann Forum Reports, vol. 10, J. Lupp, series ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Cross, I., Zubrow, E., & Cowan, F. (2002). “Musical behaviours and the archaeological record: A preliminary study”. In J. Mathieu (ed.) Experimental Archaeology. British Archaeological Reports International Series. 1035, 25-34. Dediu D, Levinson S.C. (2013). “On the antiquity of language: the reinterpretation of Neandertal linguistic capacities and its consequences”. Front. Psychol. 4, 1–17. Musical beings Koelsch, S. (2012). Brain and Music. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. Koelsch, S., Fuermetz, J., Sack, U., Baur, K., Hohenadel, M. et al. (2011). “Effects of music listening on cortisol levels and propofol consumption during spinal anesthesia”. Frontiers in Psychology, 58(2). Kohn, M. & Mithen, S. (1999). “Handaxes: products of sexual selection?”. Antiquity, 73: 518–526. Kraus N, Chandrasekaran B (2010) “Music training for the development of auditory skills”. Nat Rev Neurosci, 11: 599–605. Krause, J., Lalueza-Fox, C., Orlando, L., Enard, W., Green, R. E., Burbano, H. A., et al. (2007). “The derived FOXP2 variant of modern humans was shared with Neandertals”. Cur. Biol. 17, 1908–1912. Levitin, D.J. (2006). This Is Your Brain on Music: The Science of a Human Obsession. New York: Dutton. Levitin, D.J. (2012). “What does it mean to be musical?” Neuron, 73, 633–637. Maess, B., Koelsch, S., Gunter, T.C., & Friederici, A.D. (2001). “Musical syntax is processed in Broca’s area: an MEG study”. Nature Neuroscience, 4(5), 540–545. Miller, G.F. (2000). “Evolution of music through sexual selection”. In N. L. Wallin, B. Merker, & S. Brown (Eds.), The origins of music. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press. Mithen, S. (2005). The Singing Neanderthals: The Origins of Music, Language, Mind and Body. Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London. Ozturk A.H., Tascioglu B, Aktekin M, Kurtoglu Z, Erden I (2002). “Morphometric comparison of the human corpus callosum in professional musicians and non-musicians by using in vivo magnetic resonance imaging”. J Neuroradiol 29:29 –34. Parncutt, R. (1989). Harmony: A psychoacoustical approach. Berlin: Springer Verlag. Partanen E., Kujala A., Tervaniemi M., Huotilainen M. (2013). “Prenatal music exposure induces long-term neural effects”. PLoS ONE 8:e78946.10.1371/journal.pone.0078946. Patel, A.D. (2003). “Language, music, syntax and the brain”. Nature Neuroscience, 6, 674–681. Patel, A.D. (2008). Music, Language, and the Brain. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Pinker, S. (1997). How the Mind Works. W. W. Norton & Company. New York. Rauscher, F.H., Shaw, G.L., & Ky, K.N. (1993). “Music and spatial task performance”. Nature, 365, 611. Roy, M., Lebuis, A., Hugueville, L., Peretz, I. & Rainville, P. (2012) “Spinal modulation of nociception Side 61 Dehaene, S., & Cohen L. (2007). “Cultural recycling of cortical maps”. Neuron, 56:384–98. Dias, B.G. & Ressler, K.J. (2014). “Parental olfactory experience influences behavior and neural structure in subsequent generations”. Nat Neurosci 2014;17:89–96. Everett D. (2005). “Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition in Pirahã: Another Look at the Design Features of Human Language”. Current Anthropology, 46:621–646. Fitch, W.T. (2006). “The biology and evolution of music: a comparative perspective”. Cognition, 100, 173–215. Forgeard, M., Winner, E., Norton, A. & Schlaug, G. (2008). “Practicing a musical instrument in childhood is associated with enhanced verbal ability and nonverbal reasoning”. PLoS ONE, 3, 3566. Fritz, T., Jentschke S, Gosselin N, Sammler D, Peretz I, Turner R, Friederici A.D. & Koelsch S. (2009). “Universal recognition of three basic emotions in music”. Current Biology, 19(7):573–6. Gaser, C., & Schlaug, G. (2003). “Brain structures differ between musicians and non-musicians”. J. Neurosci. 23, 9240–9245. Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art. Second edition. Indianapolis: Hackett. Gowlett, J., Gamble, C., & Dunbar, R. (2012). “Human evolution and the archaeology of the social brain”. Curr Anthropol, 53:693–722. Grahn, J. (2012). “Neural mechanisms of rhythm perception: Current findings and future perspectives”. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1–22. Haselton, M. G., & Miller, G. F. (2006). “Women’s fertility across the life cycle increases the shortterm attractiveness of creative intelligence”. Human Nature, 17, 50–73. Henshilwood, C., d’Errico, F., Yates, R., Jacobs, Z., Tribolo, C. et al. (2002). “Emergence of modern human behavior: Middle Stone Age engravings from South Africa”. Science, 295: 1278–1280. Hyde K.L., Lerch J., Norton A., Forgeard M., Winner E., Evans A.C., Schlaug G. (2009). “The effects of musical training on structural brain development”. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1169:182–186. Juslin, P.N. & Västfjäll, D. (2008). “Emotional responses to music: The need to consider underlying mechanisms”. Behav. Brain Sci., 31, 559–575. Kanazawa, S. (2001). “De Gustibus Est Disputandum”. Social Forces, 79:1131-63. Koelsch, S. (2011). “Toward a neural basis of music perception—A review and updated model”. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 1–20. Alessandro Miani Side 62 by music”. European Journal of Pain, vol. 16, pp. 870-7. Särkämö, T., Tervaniemi, M., Laitinen, S., Forsblom, A., Soinila, S., Mikkonen, M., Autti, T., Silvennoinen, H., Erkkilä, J., Laine, M., Peretz, I. & Hietanen, M. (2008). “Music listening enhances cognitive recovery and mood after middle cerebral artery stroke”. Brain, vol. 131, pp. 866-876. Schellenberg E.G. (2004). “Music lessons enhance IQ”. Psychol Sci 15: 511–514. Schellenberg E.G. (2006). “Long-term positive associations between music lessons and IQ”. J Educ Psychol 98: 457–468. Schlaug G, Jancke L, Huang Y, Staiger JF, Steinmetz H (1995). “Increased corpus callosum size in musicians”. Neuropsychologia, 33:1047–1055. Semaw, S., Rogers, M., Quade, J., Renne, P., Butler, R., Dominguez-Rodrigo, M., Stout, D., Hart, W., Pickering, T., Simpson, S. (2003). “2.6-million-year-old stone tools and associated bones from OGS-6 and OGS-7, Gona, Afar, Ethiopia”. J. Hum. Evol. 45, 169e177. Sloboda, J. (1985). The Musical Mind: The Cognitive Psychology of Music. Oxford Univ. Press, New York. Steinbeis, N. & S. Koelsch. (2009). “Understanding the intentions behind man-made products elicits neural activity in areas dedicated to mental state attribution”. Cerebral Cortex, 19(3): 619–623. Stout D., Toth N., Schick K. D., Chaminade T. (2008). “Neural correlates of Early Stone Age tool-making: technology, language and cognition in human evolution”. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 363, 1939–1949. Tagg, P. (2014). Music’s Meanings: a modern musicology for non‐musos.New York & Huddersfield: The Mass Media Music Scholars’ Press. Thompson, W.F., Schellenberg, E.G., & Husain, G. (2001). “Arousal, mood and the Mozart effect”. Psychological Science, 12, 248–251. Tifferet, S., Gaziel, O., & Baram, Y. (2012). “Guitar increases male Facebook attractiveness: Preliminary support for the sexual selection theory of music”. Letters on Evolutionary Behavioral Science, 3(1), 4–6. Tirovolas, A. K., & Levitin, D.J. (2011). “Music perception and cognition research from 1983 to 2010: A categorical and bibliometric analysis of empirical articles in music perception”. Music Perception, 29(1), 23-36. Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Tomasello, M. (2014). A natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Trehub, S.E. (2003a). “Musical predispositions in infancy: An update”. In I. Peretz & R. Zatorre (Eds.), The Cognitive Neuroscience of Music (p. 3-20). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Trehub, S.E. (2003b). “The developmental origins of musicality”. Nature Neuroscience, 6(7):669–73. Westermann, R., Spies, K., Stahl, G., & Hesse, F.W. (1996). “Relative effectiveness and validity of mood induction procedures: A meta-analysis”. European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 557-80. FAGLIG KRITIK Denne sektion er åben for faglige kommentarer til artikler publiceret i vores to seneste numre. Alle kan bidrage til denne sektion og redaktionen vil udvælge bidrag til publikation og lægge resten på Semikolons hjemmeside. Denne sektion er ikke ment som en pendant til opinionssektionen i dagblade, ej heller egentlige anmeldelser af Semikolons samlede udtryk eller stil. Det er nærmere en plads for offentliggørelse af en “tænken-med” (eller imod) nogle argumenter i de tidligere artikler. Det kan sammenlignes med såkaldte peer-review-rapporter, men med de store forskelle, at indlæggene til Semikolon offentliggøres, og at de vil være modtaget uopfordret fra skriftets læsere. Det skal medvirke til, at den akademiske udvikling af tanker og ideer ikke er hemmelig, at gode ideer ikke strander, fordi de ikke var færdigudviklede, samt at nogle “fejl” kan gøres produktive i en anden eller større kontekst. Hvilke pointer og argumenter kan udvides, hvilke hænger ikke særligt godt sammen, hvad siger andre studier, fagretninger og anden forskning om emnet behandlet i artiklen? Det er spørgsmål, som kunne tjene som udgangspunkt for den faglige kommentar. Der er umiddelbart ikke nogen krav til formen eller indholdet af en kommentar, men længden er begrænset til tre sider i overensstemmelse med vores skrivevejledning og kritikken skal holdes til det faglige mellemværende. Gensvar på kritik i sektionen må højst være en side, men er yderst velkommne. Redaktionen har ikke modtaget nogen indlæg til Faglig Kritik i dette nummer, men sektionen er fortsat åben for bidrag. TIDLIGERE NUMRE Tidligere numre af Semikolon kan findes i PDF-format på Semikolons hjemmeside. På hjemmesiden finder du desuden de nyeste call for papers, skrivevejledning, semikolonsk historie og semikolonske nyheder. www.semikolon.au.dk Semikolon er også på Facebook. Bliv fan og støt tidsskriftet ved at synes godt om Facebooksiden, hvor vi annoncerer semikolonsk nyt. www.facebook.com/semikolon.au.dk ANMELDELSER Kasper Vestrup 66 Om Fornuftens Skæbne Anmeldelse af Kai Sørlander: Fornuftens Skæbne Anders Dræby Sørensen 67 Michel Foucaults idéhistoriske filosofi Anmeldelse af Anders Fogh Jensen: Mellem ting – Foucaults filosofi Side 66 Anmeldelser Om Fornuftens Skæbne Kai Sørlander: Fornuftens Skæbne Information, 2014; 238 sider; 217 kr. Kai Sørlander (f. 1944), har med bøger som ”Den endegyldige sandhed”(2002), ”Forsvar for rationaliteten – religion og politik i filosofisk perspektiv”(2008) og nu ”Fornuftens skæbne”(2014) erklæret sig, som en fortaler for rationaliteten og fornuftens krav til menneskets etiske og sociale overvejelser. Med den menneskelige udvikling som udgangspunkt, arbejder Sørlander mod en universel dagsorden for fornuften i bogen ”Fornuftens Skæbne”. Som sagt er Sørlanders overordnede projekt i ”Fornuftens Skæbne” er at give et bud på hvilken politisk dagsorden mennesket som globaliseret samfund skal have for fremtiden. Sørlanders struktur er tredelt: I første del udforsker han fornuftens udvikling i historien, fra de tidligste samfund og til nu. For derefter, i anden del, at diskutere hvilke problematikker fornuften og rationaliteten står overfor i det moderne multikulturelle samfund. De overordnede problemer Sørlander ser i det moderne samfund er racisme igennem partikularisme, som han historisk set ser hos nazismen og fascismen, men i moderne samfund ses i Islam. Andre problematikker det moderne globaliseret samfund møder er den såkaldte højmoral i moderne udenrigspolitik og markedsøkonomien. Mellem de to dele har Sørlander indskudt et såkaldt mellemspil, kaldet ”Det filosofiske omdrejningspunkt”. I dette mellemspil kommer Sørlander med overvejelser over sammenhænget mellem demokratiet og kristendommen og deres rolle i fornuftens udvikling, samt også en kritik af den moderne kulturrelativisme. Sørlanders kritik af relativisme er overfladisk, og han fremstiller relativismen ud fra helt basale logiske kritikker, og igennem dette gør han hverken relativismen eller kritikken af samme nogen ære. De andre problematikker som Sørlander berører i anden del, altså Islam, højmoral og markedsøkonomien kan også kritiseres på visse punkter. Sørlanders redegørelse for problematikken ved racisme igennem partikularismen er godt skrevet og historisk argumenteret for, sin seriøsitet og farlighed igennem nazismen. Men at placere moderne racistisk partikularisme på Islam, er en grov simplificering og, i min optik, fejlfortolkning af visse islamiske doktriner. Sørlander har et glorificeret syn på kristendommens rolle i den vestlige verdens udvikling og på samme måde et nedvurderende, fjendebillede i Islam. Det er ærgerligt for bogen, at dens afslutning bliver reduceret til teologisk mudderkastning. I samme omgang er hans kritik af højmoralen i moderne politik, som han især tilskriver et idealiseret billede på integration og globalisering, en gyldig kritik af den moderne politiske tankegang. Men han kan selv klandres for en form for højmoral i forbindelse med hans tolkning kristendommen, hvis praktiske anvendelighed bliver idealiseret meget. Kai Sørlander har mange gode analyser af problematikkerne ved det moderne globaliseret samfund, og politikken og religionens rolle i samfundets videre udvikling. Man skal dog ikke som filosof læse Sørlander for dets filosofiske indhold, hans system er ikke filosofisk omvæltende som sådan eller nogen videreudvikling på igangværende filosofiske diskussioner. På trods af de kritik punkter jeg har listet op, er Sørlander god til at introducere til problemstillingerne man i politik og i religion i det moderne samfund. – Kasper Vestrup Anders Fogh Jensen Mellem ting – Foucaults filosofi (2. reviderede udgave) THP, 2013; 307 sider; 197 kr. Side 67 I 1969 bliver Michel Foucault kaldt til en lærerstol ved den prestigefulde institution Collége de France i Paris. Jean Hyppolite er død året forinden, og hans lærerstol i den filosofiske tænknings historie er derfor blevet ledig. Foucault får derimod en titel som professor i tankesystemernes historie. Ikke mindst på baggrund af hans såkaldte vidensarkæologiske studier fra 1960’erne. Foucault bliver oprindeligt uddannet i filosofi. Han vedbliver med at forstå sin egen tænkning som filosofisk. Alligevel er der ikke nogen tvivl om, at han først og fremmest forstår hoveddelen af sit eget intellektuelle projekt som en form for idéhistorie. Om end Foucault i sit værk Vidensarkæologien fra 1969 også langer ud efter den idéhistorie tradition fra blandt andre Arthur Lovejoy. Derfor er det jo i udgangspunktet også særligt interessant, at Anders Fogh Jensen har valgt at sætte fokus på Foucaults filosofi. Det sker dog uden at kaste idéhistorien på møddingen. Der findes et utal af indgange til Foucaults omfangsrige forfatterskab. Hvilket ikke mindst hænger sammen med, at Foucault vedvarende forskyder sit eget fokus og til stadighed udvikler sin egen metode. Hvilket ikke udmønter sig i nogen filosofisk teori men derimod i en række konkrete idéhistoriske undersøgelser. Undervejs stopper Foucault dog lejlighedsvis op for at gøre sig nogle metaanalytiske og metodologiske overvejelser. Som for eksempel netop i det omtalte værk fra 1969, hvor Foucault på en systematisk måde sammenfatter sine bestræbelser fra 1960’erne under overskriften vidensarkæologi. Det er det her, som jeg bestræber mig på, og det er det, som jeg hele tiden har lavet! For derefter at indlede 1970’erne med nærmest at dreje rundt om sig selv og italesætte sit eget projekt på ny under den metodologiske overskrift genealogi. Af selv samme grund vælger de fleste udlægninger af Foucaults forfatterskab også at gå nogenlunde kronologisk til værks og fremstille den vertikale udvikling i det analytiske perspektiv. Jensen har imidlertid valgt at gå næsten modsat til værks, horisontalt om man vil, for at levere en tematisk indføring i forfatterskabet. På den ene side vælger Jensen hermed at afvise forestillingen om, at Foucaults forfatterskab er præget af en række faser, som er adskilt af forholdsvist radikale forskydninger. For at syntetisere en gennemgående sammenhæng i forfatterskabet. På den anden side vælger Jensen ganske interessant alligevel at udelade den tidlige del af Foucaults forfatterskab i sin introduktion og falder derfor lidt selv i gryden med faser. Jensens overordnede ambition er at vise, at der er en snæver sammenhæng i Foucaults forfatterskab mellem to hovedaspekter i form af tankesystemer og styresystemer. De er ”én og samme historie” (s. 14). Jensens systemiske fokus peger dels på en læsning af Foucault som en udpræget poststrukturalist. Der er da heller ikke nogen tvivl om, at især Foucaults vidensakæologiske værker fra 1960’erne befandt sig i slipstrømmen af den franske strukturalisme, samtidig med at Foucault netop afsvor strukturbegrebet. Langt hen ad vejen til fordel for et fokus på systemerne, omend dette begreb nærmest forsvinder ud af forfatterskabet i 1970’erne og 1980’erne. I en snæver sammenhæng med at Foucault Anmeldelser Michel Foucaults idéhistoriske filosofi Anmeldelser Side 68 ændrer sin metode. Det er derfor lidt af en tilsnigelse at ville sammenfatte forfatterskabet under en systemisk overskrift. Når Jensen alligevel gør det, så hænger det i udpræget grad sammen med, at hans egen udlægning af forfatterskabet sker i et systemperspektiv. Vi får altså en meget skematisk fremstilling af temaerne i Foucaults filosofi. Og enkelte steder bliver fremstillingen desværre enten noget oprensende eller nærmest så skematisk, at Jensens introduk- tion bliver mere vanskeligt tilgængelig end det originale forfatterskab. Til gengæld er det et prisværdigt og for så vist også originalt forehavende at ville fremstille en systematisk sammenhæng i forfatterskabet. Jensens bog er ganske udmærket. Mange steder er den også ganske letlæselig. Den vidner om en stor indsigt i Foucault og en passion for at fremstille hans tanker. – Anders Dræby Sørensen KONTAKT INFO På Semikolons hjemmeside kan du downloade tidligere numre i PDFformat, finde Call for Papers til de kommende temaer, finde skrivevejledninger til artikelskrivning og læse seneste nyt fra tidsskriftet. www.semikolon.au.dk Vis din støtte til Semikolon ved at blive fan på Facebook, hvor vi også annoncerer semikolonsk nyt. Find os på: facebook.com/semikolon.au Kunne du tænke dig at anmelde en bog, og har du ikke allerede selv fået fat i den, så kan du kontakte redaktionen, som vil være behjælpelig med at hjemskaffe den fra forlaget. Du kan naturligvis beholde bogen, hvis vi modtager en anmeldelse fra dig. Skriv til os på: [email protected] OM BIDRAGSYDERNE Kevin Crowley Juan Olvido Christoffer Basse Eriksen Nis Langer Primdahl Natalia Hoffman Anders Dræby Sørensen Alessandro Miani Kasper Vestrup Stud. mag. i Kognitiv Semiotik, AU Ph.d.-studerende ved Institut for Kultur og Samfund – Idéhistorie, AU Cand. mag. i Kognitiv Semiotik, AU Stud. mag. i Kognitiv Semiotik, AU Stud. mag. i Kognitiv Semiotik, AU Speciale-studerende i Filosofi og Sociologi, KU Forfatter, foredragsholder, mv. Stud.mag. i Filosofi, AU OM BIDRAG Semikolon modtager bidrag fra læserne i form af artikler indenog udenfor tema samt indlæg til sektionen Faglig Kritik. Bliver det mere polemisk, er der plads i den lejlighedsvise sektion Polemik. Bidrag sendes til redaktionen på [email protected] i Word eller RTF-format; illustrationer vedhæftes seperat i bedst mulig kvalitet. Redaktionen påtager sig intet ansvar for indsendt materiale. Du finder call for papers for de næste to numre på side 6-7. Skrivevejledning Alle indlæg skal overholde følgende formalia: a)Artikler er maksimalt 10 sider á 2.400 tegn, i alt 24.000 tegn. b)Indlæg til Faglig Kritik er maksimalt 3 sider á 2.400 tegn, i alt 7.200 tegn. c)Artikler indeholder titel og et abstract på maksimalt 400 tegn. d)Citater sættes i dobbelt anførselstegn og kursiv: ”Den virkelige verden har sine grænser, indbildningens verden er uendelig.” Citat i citat sættes i enkelt anførselstegn: ”Emiles Mentor tilføjer: ’Og Eucharis’ yndigheder!’ - [...]” Kursiv i citater sættes med almindelige typer: ”Den kaldes Den ydre stat.” e)Med undtagelse af citat i citat anvendes kun dobbelt anførselstegn. f) Særlige fagtermer fremhæves med kursiv, første gang de anvendes. g)Titler på bøger skrives i kursiv, titler på artikler sættes i anførseltegn uden kursiv. h)Noter er slutnoter og skal bruges begrænset. i) Litteraturhenvisninger er af formen: (Croft 2004) Ved sidehenvisning: (Nicolaisen 2004: 40) j) Litteraturlisten er for bøger af formen: Croft, William (2004): Cognitive Linguistics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. For tidsskrifter af formen: Nicolaisen, Nis (2004): “Dommerfilosofi”, Semikolon, nr. 9, årg. 4. k) Teksten skal være skrevet på dansk, svensk, norsk eller engelsk i henhold til den seneste retstavning og kommatering. SEMIKOLON Institut for Kultur og Samfund Jens Chr. Skous Vej 7 Bygning 1465-1467 8000 Århus C [email protected] www.semikolon.au.dk facebook.com/semikolon.au REDAKTION Semir Music (ansv./temared.) Jacob Hedeager Olsen (anm. red.) Janni Katrine B. Frederiksen (krea. red.) Kevin Arthur Crowley (krea. red.) Thomas Hjermitslev (wwwred.) Julie Duchemin Sara Benedicte Neukirch Valdemar Nielsen Pold Emil Vinther PRODUKTION SUN-TRYK OPLAG 360 stk. UDGIVET MED STØTTE FRA Institut for Kultur og Samfund Redaktionen 3 Leder 6 Call for papers Nr. 29: Kærlighed // No. 29: Love Nr. 30: Tillid // No. 30: Trust Tema: Artefakter Christopher Basse Eriksen 11 Er kroppen blot en maskine? – Minutiøs materialitet hos René Descartes Juan Olvido 21 Sociogenesis and stability of artifacts in cultural practices of illegal cannabis use Kevin Crowley 29 Extended Mind, Shrinking Memory Nis Langer Primdahl 38 Artefakt, modernitet – social acceleration Natalia Hoffman 47 The Sucking Tree Alessandro Miani 53 Musical beings: Is music an artifact? 65 Anmeldelser www.facebook.com/semikolon.au ISSN 1600-8529 www.semikolon.au.dk
© Copyright 2024